Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
POSTMODERNISM AND THE SUBJECT; PESSIMISM OF THE WILL
by
Robert M. Young
The splintering and ephemeralization which characterize postmodernism
seem new and alarming, but to a psychoanalytic eye they evoke familiar phenomena:
fragmentation, being in pieces, splitting, part-object relations. Nor is the present the
first time such topics have been considered in the Western intellectual tradition. The
great fissure that exists in our fundamental scheme of thought arose in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries with the breakdown of Aristotelian organicist explanation (a topic I
shall take up again in chapter eight). We have had a major split in our way of thinking
ever since. There were tensions in the late Renaissance which were tugging away at
Aristotelian explanations in terms of formal, final, material and efficient causes, but in
the scientific revolution knowledge and reality were codified in such a way that mind and
body, subject and object, culture and nature, fantasy and external reality and the whole
and the part, were split.
I could go on to list other dualisms with which we have been faced. Of
course, there have always been attempts to heal this fissure, many of them in the late
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. There have been various monisms or efforts to
enthrone one side or other of the great Cartesian split. I am thinking in our own time of
Gestalt, of holism itself, of organicism, of emergentism, of phenomenology and, in the
Marxist tradition, the point of view of totality. So, let us also note that these are not
altogether new questions. I always find that if I can reconnect something which startles
me with the history of thought, it makes me feel a little better.
I want to begin what I have to say in this chapter with three
statements. First, I am weary and live in a state of continual spiritual deprivation.
Second, it is not given to us to complete the task, but we may not give it up. Third, One
must imagine Sisyphus happy. I say these things so as not to be even more cliched and use
the epigram for all serious progressives of recent times: pessimism of the
intellect, optimism of the will (coined by Romain Rolland but made into a
programmatic slogan by the leading figure in Italian Marxism, Antonio Gramsci, as early as
1919; Gramsci, 1929-35, p. 175n). In more recent times, Paul Simon said, I
dont know a soul thats not been battered; I dont have a friend who feels
at ease. I dont know a dream thats not been shattered or driven to its
knees (Simon, 1973).
It is in this spirit that I want to approach the question: Is
there a domain of subjectivity which is irreducible to social determinations
incongruent with formal knowledge in any given discipline yet relevant to and vital
for the future of the human sciences? My answer is yes, but not just for the
human sciences. This phrase begs the question: subjectivity is relevant and vital
for humanity, not just for disciplines which we all call sciences but also for
human nature for human nature inside history, for humanity, which is able to hope
and to transcend the is in the name of a vision of the ought, but
not to be shattered by the gulf between them, which seems to me to be what we are faced
with in postmodernist deconstruction.
I am not a close student of the history that has led people to ask if
the time has come to treat the subject as a prodigal and allow it back into the family of
our concepts. Even so, I am not just daunted by, but am also suspicious of, the rhetoric
of this debate. For me, the subject never went away for a reason you may at first
find eccentric. Throughout the period during which formalisms, including structuralist and
post-structuralist ideas, were appealing to the category of science or scientificity for
legitimacy, my own research on the categories of science was finding subjectivity at the
heart of the deepest scientific concepts. When I say deepest, I do mean deep: gravity/gravitas, affinity/attraction, and natural selection. These are the deepest concepts in the most
respectable of the natural sciences physics, chemistry and biology. Natural
selection an anthropomorphic metaphor is the concept which links life to the
rest of nature and human nature to the history of life. It is the basis of the historicity
of all that is, and it is through the concept of historicity that in my own work I have
tried to link Darwin and Marx.
I was finding purposeful and teleological reasoning in the most
reductionist of the biological disciplines and anthropomorphism at the heart of the very
human sciences which were themselves keenest to be seen as respectable according to the
model of the physical sciences. Others (and this occurred rather early in my own
training in the history and philosophy of science) were finding insight and perceptiveness
in the secret places of the most behaviourist research programmes and deeply cathected
language communities in the most analytically solipsistic private domains of the analysis
of language. Charles Taylor (1964) persuaded us that behaviourist rats have insight, while
Wittgenstein (1953) and his followers put paid to the possibility of a private language.
These seem to me to be important analogies to what is being talked about here.
So, while others were finding science in Marxism and linguistics in the
unconscious, I was among those who were finding humanism and values at the heart of the
very sciences to which the formalists were appealing for legitimacy. Of course, I was not
alone in this work. It had its roots in the critique of modern sciences reductionist
paradigm of explanation, especially the mind-body dichotomy and the primary-secondary
quality distinction which I discussed above in referring to the work of Alfred North
Whitehead and Edwin Arthur Burtt, as well as the other attempts at holism mentioned
earlier. These were (coming from different directions) close cousins to the humanistic
Marxism of the Frankfurt School of critical theory and their part-allies (who may have
lost their political nerve), the hermeneuticists. Coming from yet another direction are
the American pragmatists, closely allied with a highly sophisticated group of analytical
philosophers. I am thinking here of Richard Rorty on metaphor and stories at the
heart of knowing. He, following Nietzsche, defines truth as a mobile army of
metaphors, including and especially the metaphors at the heart of science (my
remarks about gravity and gravitas are drawn from a lecture of his). He argues in
The Contingency of Selfhood (1989) for accepting metaphor over literal truth,
for a humanocentric rather than an objective world, but he does so without loss of hope
that is, without jettisoning the concept of self or subject (Rorty, 1989, pp. 17,
27, 37-41)
One route to return to the subject, then, leads to narrative or, as I
saw it put recently, Lets cut the crap and get on with the yarn. We
live, says Rorty, in story after story coherent, with plots and meanings, however
multi-layered. Yarns is another way of appropriating the concept of narrative
discourse, serving rather than supplanting the human subject. A failed narrative remains
human, while a failed science is vacuous. We find that if we attempt to build a science
out of the subject and we fail, we are left in pieces, whereas a bad yarn is still a yarn,
a human story.
There is one more main strand in my argument, but I shall return to it
later. It overlaps in some ways with the work of the Frankfurt School, that is,
psychoanalysis, especially in its object relations form. It should be acknowledged that a
deconstructionist would want to place psychoanalysis and the other traditions I have
mentioned inside the history and sociology of knowledge, but the infinite regress
generated by doing that plagues us all and does not favour nihilistic conclusions any more
than objectivist ones. Psychoanalysis says to me that the expunging of the subject is
simply not on, but I shall spell this out later in the chapter.
There is another important sense, already considered in chapter one, in
which we have made this mess for ourselves, because of our own history and our own sense
of historicity and contingency. If we say that human nature is an ensemble of social
relations and that truth is made and not found, that is, if we insist upon the social
construction of the self and of knowledge, we will find on the other side of the coin of
social construction the possibility of deconstruction without remainder. My thesis is that
the possibility of deconstruction (and I here mean this conceptually) finds the self at
the heart of the project, just as the critics of other fragmenting and reductionist
programmes find anthropomorphic and humanocentric concepts at the heart of their projects.
You may say that science is a tedious or irrelevant starting point, but
I should remind you that modernism was itself a scientism avowedly so and
postmodernism is a symptom of the failure of the abstracted scientistic project. Among the
resonances of the modernist project were purity, universality, progress, decontextualised
and self-reflexive objects (buildings and novels, for example), rather than articulated
and contextualised ones. This is true in various ways of functionalism, positivism,
Leavisite literary criticism and formalism itself, as a meta-discipline.
I well remember the grip of these scientisms during my own
undergraduate education in the early 1950s. I took home from my first year at Yale a book
on logic, because I wanted to learn to think. Believe it or not I would come
home from working in a Ford factory every night and read a textbook on logic. I studied
symbolic logic the next year and vividly recall an encounter in my final year. I was
taking a stroll with the supervisor of my Scholars of the House Project on
self-reflection, the eminent Whitehead scholar, Nathaniel Lawrence. We encountered the
arch-positivist, Arthur Pap, walking briskly towards us on a New Haven street. Lawrence
said, Hello, Arthur. Nice day. Pap replied, I presume you are speaking
metaphorically. Nobody laughed.
I also recall how earnestly I tried to read philosophical articles
which began, Take an X such that... or Y is true if and only if...
This philosophical project was exactly analogous to the overall aims of formalism
described by Raymond Williams as seeking to displace and divert our diverse actual
confusions, pains and anxieties (Williams, 1986, p. 31). It was not until decades
later that I became fully aware that this was the high tide of philosophy looking to
science for a model for all knowing, with other disciplines following suit. Richard Rorty,
who had taught me in my first year, has written a lovely essay on this period, during
which an attempt was being made to get philosophy out of the "humanities"
and into the "sciences" (Rorty, 1982, p. 219). He goes on to characterise more
recent times in which scientific method is seen by many as the mask behind which
lurks the cruelty and despair of a nihilistic age (p. 229). That is how far the
debate has moved since the 1950s.
As I see it, then, both formalism, with its isolation of the object,
and contextualism, with its attempt to achieve an exhaustive analysis of articulations,
have contributed greatly to our present distress. When a Marxist asks whether or not
determinism and articulations exhaust the subject, this is the Continental version of the
Humean empiricist question about the self discussed in chapter one. David Humes
bundle of sensations plays the same role as a candidate for lack of a centre
as an ensemble of social relations.
However and this is my key point much depends on whether
one embarks on such a project with a pessimistic or an optimistic aim. Social location and
embedding can either dissolve the subject or achieve specificity and enrichment. It can
exhaust it and scoop out its living, unique individuality, or it can illuminate the whole,
analyse in order to reconstitute, to fathom, to enhance, to understand better. Contingency
can fragment, or it can relate. The same is true of other helpful notions. I am thinking
of inscribing, of structural and epochal causation, of multiple and
multi-layered causation, of the concept of overdetermination. Each can enrich and
illuminate or impoverish and exhaust.
Kierkegaard accused Hegel of building a huge castle and then finding
himself sitting outside it. I used to take note of the outsideness; I now note the exiled
location of the self. It is a silly place to end up. The Marx versus Nietzsche lineages need not force us to a dichotomy between totality, on the one
hand, and utter fragmentation, on the other. The fact that the subject and the concept of
the subject are contingent does not eliminate either the premise or the possibility
the project of coherence. The postmodernist is no longer sanguine about science but
indulges instead in cynicism rather than critique. The object is jettisoned, while the
point of critique is to interrogate in searching ways in order to enhance understanding,
to do better.
I need hardly spend much time on despairing elements of the subject and
the consequences of this for any unified sense of human nature. Both have been
de-ontologised, while the signifier has been ontologised. Postmodernists claim that the
link can be cut between the signifier and the signified, between the word and the object,
by leaving out meaning, caring, values. The concept of mediation is itself thrown out.
Marike Finlay describes postmodernity as a psychotic defence against loss of
referential identity (Finlay, 1989, p. 59). She also speaks of it as a culturally
generalised psychosis. The late and greatly lamented Christopher Lasch says something
similar in his writings on narcissism and the minimal self: that the commodity world is
too alien to serve as a set of transitional objects and phenomena, that the current
generation is characterised by lack of project, a position echoed in
expositions of postmodernism (e.g., Newman, 1989). We are left with something fragmented,
a bricolage , parody, small-scale, anti-utopian, abandoning the project of
totality. It is consumerist, cynical, and offers only the diversions of play in return for
all it takes away. The hopes of a vision of a better world have been labelled as
idealization and trashed, converting the remains into a dumping ground, a patsy, a
scapegoat. A person whose projects in the 1960s and 70s evoked my admiration, who now
finds himself well-placed in career terms, said to me recently that his main preoccupation
is how to deal with disappointment and how to avoid falling into bitterness.
As I was pondering these matters and trying to find a way of conveying
my belief that we are dealing with both a logical point and a moral and political question
about keeping the faith, I found myself reflecting on Cubism. There cannot be a more
historically contingent phenomenon in culture than this one, which can be said to have
begun with a single painting in 1907, Les Damoiselles dAvignon, and peaked in
the 1920s (a period during which Freud penned some of his major writings). Surely the
point about Cubism, as about Surrealism and Dada, was to get past convention and the
sieves of jadedness and to reach something deeper in the human spirit and more
illuminating. The postmodernist seems to me to pronounce the jaded all we can have.
Cubism, on the contrary, still holds the object; it fragments or rises above it in
the name of reaching deeper. While breaking with the European illusionist tradition, its
ultimate aims are realistic. Non-perspectival forms and multiple perceptions achieve
discrete points of view that are meant to accumulate and then return to the composite
shape. (Fry, 1966, p. 37).
The abstraction, the geometrization, the selective exaggeration, the
deliberate abandonment of the techniques of perspective and foreshortening are all
deconstructive, but they are all in the service of illuminating the whole and are always
in tension with the imaginatively reconstituted object. The artist, like a Winnicottian
good-enough mother, must know just how far to go so as not to break the link and produce
hyperintellectualism or madness. The link with the primitive is evident in the influence
on Cubism via what Picasso drew from African and Andalucian art, notably woodcarvings
which stress the most basic shapes and images, especially of the face. All these points
were forcibly driven home to me while wandering around the Tate Gallery exhibition of the
Douglas Cooper collection of paintings by Picasso, Gris, Léger, Braque and Klee. The
historical relativists and sociologists of knowledge will say that I am only digging
myself in deeper. It does not take an art historian to point out to me what came after
Cubism, and each may draw her or his own conclusion as to whether or not the object has
been lost or the human spirit continues to be reached by abstract art. My own taste says
no, it does not, but my knowledge of the potentialities of reconstitution and reparation
insists yes.
I now want to turn an analytic eye to the urge to dismiss the subject.
I experience it as despairing, spiteful and spoiling (I am using these terms in both a
Kleinian and a lay sense). When Finlay uses the term psychotic defence, it is
important to not both words. There is an agency conducting the defence. As R. D. Laing
used to say, the psychotic has built a cocoon of symptoms to preserve the self. The
hebephrenic or the simple schizophrenic, the autistic child each can understand what is said to him or her. Anyone who has worked with catatonics in a mental
hospital will have a story to tell about one who improves after prolonged immobility and
silence and tells you something you said to them months or even years earlier when he or
she was apparently completely out of contact. There are debates in psychoanalysis about
this matter, but, as I said in chapter one, there is common ground that there cannot be
no object. The self is not completely fragmented; there is always an ego; there is the
coherence of a process. Otherwise the therapeutic work that has been done so successfully
with psychotics simply could not get off the ground. It would be heartbreaking (instead of
just very, very hard) and always a losers game. But it is not. As the work of Laing
(1960), Berke (Barnes and Berke, 1971; Berke, 1989), Searles (1960, 1965), Barham (1988),
Jackson (1994) and Rey (1994), among others (Ellwood, 1995), has shown, it is among the
most exciting and rewarding kinds of work you can do.
In addition to those writers, Klein, Winnicott, Bion, Meltzer, Tustin,
Rosenfeld and Segal have all looked into the vicissitudes of the most primitive, the
regressed, the psychotic processes of splitting, fragmentation, projective identification,
autism, the autistic cysts that exist in normal people (S. Klein, 1980). These analysts
are close students of the fragility of the self and the role of symbolism in culture and
in its maintenance. Closely analogous things can be said about the work of Balint,
Fairbairn and Guntrip. We have damaged objects, part-objects, and failed primary object
relations; we have transitional objects, spaces, phenomena. Indeed, Winnicott claims that
all of culture exists in a transitional space (see below, ch. 6). Yet all their patients
even the most regressed and primitive and crazy retain contact with the
object and, as I explained in chapter one, the object relations theory which underlies
current psychoanalysis presupposes it.
The work of these people allows us to take on board the phenomena of
splitting, fragmentation and projecting the split off bits (unacceptable because despised
or taboo) and continue to perceive these and other psychotic mechanisms as part of, rather
than an epitaph to, coherent, albeit damaged, object relations. The mechanisms of
splitting and projective identification lie at the basis of Bions theory of thinking
(see Hinshelwood, 1991, pp. 179-208, 231-7) and, in exaggerated form, are at the heart of
psychotic mechanisms at work in all of us (see Young, 1994, ch. 5; 1995). But these
mechanisms serve ongoing object relations, that is, the survival of the subject. All
experience, no matter how sophisticated, abstract, alienated or mad, continues to be
mediated through the object. The primitive path is always trodden, never superseded. Not
only does primitive emotional experience come first; it comes first, last and always.
I am saying at this point that psychoanalytic object relations theory
can easily accommodate the distressed and cynical reaction of the failed hopes of the
present generation, who dreamed so much a quarter of a century ago. The project then
becomes one of survival, of holding on, and the extremely slow processes of containment,
detoxification and reparation which have taken so many of us into analysis and some of us
into becoming therapists. I want now to look deeper and further back in our intellectual
tradition and end by speaking of ontology. I really meant this at its most fundamental,
that is, the centrality of the concept of person lying behind the original
mind-body split in the seventeenth century, with its epistemological representation in the
primary-secondary quality distinction (between shape, on the one hand, and taste, smell,
colour and other subjective qualities, on the other). We elaborate conceptual
apparatuses. This is not a voluntary or individualistic process but a historical one:
decisions were made about knowledge and being in the scientific revolution of
the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.
As any one-time Maoist could tell you, voluntarism cannot throw off
historys or natures insolent yoke. Even so, an epoch
or a culture or a sub-culture elaborates conceptual apparatuses; it is a cultural
activity. It is the task of searching and transcending vision of critique to
evaluate their deep assumptions and alter them, whatever struggle this may require.
However, as we will consider at greater length in chapter three, a given ideology remains
historical and amenable to contest: it is second nature, not first nature, no matter how
deeply sedimented or embedded it may be. Before mind, body and language was the person.
Strawson (1959) and others have shown that the concept of person is ontologically prior to
that of mind and body, subject and object. The splits which plague our ontology and
epistemology are secondary to the concept of person. As I said at the beginning, splits
are the keynote, but the object is conceptually and developmentally prior.
A person in history has a biography. I offer the concept of biography
as the place where the resolution of large- and small-scale forces meet and also where
conscious and unconscious forces meet. I do not mean this in order to promote a possessive
individualism but to place history inside the subject rather than dissolving the subject
into history, since the concept of history has no meaning apart from the experiences of
subjects.
Something similar has been said of language by Marike Finlay: The
major difference between the modern and the postmodern epochs resides in their respective
attitudes towards the recognition of the split in language between sign and concept or
referent. The modern constantly laments that cleavage and strives to repair the gap if
separation by using the symbolic as mediator of identity and difference [hear the echoes
of Winnicott and Segal]. The postmodern does not lament the split; it accepts it
and dissolves the other, be it concept, referent or person, into nonexistence
(Finlay, 1989, p. 53).
Note, however, that the possession of a capacity for symbolic language
has been, at least since Descartes, a unique defining characteristic of human subjects
(Young, 1967). Before discourse spoke the subject, the resolution of historical forces
spoke the discourse. In the beginning were the instinct, the need, the impulse and the
value, not the word. We must tolerate the contradiction that the word was God, while at
the same time it was with God the repository of a cultures husbanded
symbolism of the transcendent.
Theories and political positions mediate values through symbolism. For
example, Marxism is about mediation, but it is essential to keep a grip on what things are
mediations of. Otherwise, it is an undialectical use, a positivist appropriation,
of Marxism. Language is a mediation. I insist that it is a mediation of collective
subjectivity epochal resolutions of forces, inflected through individual
consciousness and the unconscious: inflected through, not inscribed upon. (Whenever I hear
about things being inscribed I recall the Kafka short story where a persons crime is
carved into his body: crude and brutal punishment, not subtle.)
It is no accident that my language is becoming increasingly biblical,
because it is to the Bible that I now wish to turn. One of the things of which
postmodernism is a symptom along with the failure of scientism and the idea of
progress is the absence of the transcendent in both psychoanalysis and Marxism,
something Joel Kovel has attempted to rectify in his work on liberation theology and the
spirit (1991). Lest I be misunderstood in what I am about to convey, I speak as a secular
radical, but I want to close this chapter by reminding the reader of the deep and
persistent existence of hope for coherence in the face of just how complex and awful the
world is.
I have had reason to reflect on loss and endurance in my own life and
in the face of the extinguishing of a shining beacon as a result of the death of Raymond
Williams. How do we endure and hope? Who will be our role model, now that our role model
is gone? How do we as a Kleinian would put it, abide in the depressive position? I here
offer a word about my own object. As a child I longed to meet a certain Shirley Goodness,
whose wonders were in such painful contrast with the incapacity of my own invalid and
depressed mother. I had heard of Shirley Goodness so often in church. The caring object,
the mixture of good and bad, the bearing of the truth in the valley of the shadow of death
and in the presence of mine enemies: containment and peace in green pastures and by still
waters. No irreparable depletion: I shall not want. An abundance: my cup runneth over.
Read this in a special way. Try to experience it as the testament of a small child
speaking to its object or source of security, of hope and endurance:
The Lord is my shepherd: I shall not want.
He maketh me to lie down in green pastures: he leadeth me
beside the still waters.
He restoreth my soul: he leadeth me in the paths of
righteousness for his names sake.
Yea, though I walk through the valley of the shadow of death,
I will fear no evil: for though art with me; thy rod and thy staff they
comfort me.
Thou preparest a table before me in the presence of mine enemies: thou
anointest my head with oil; my cup
runneth over.
Surely goodness and mercy shall follow me all the days of my life: and
I will dwell in the house of the Lord for
ever.
Shirley also brings to mind Bions childhood experience of the
Lords Prayer: Arf Arfur...Oo Arf in Mphm (Bion, 1982, p. 9). (First
Corinthians Chapter Thirteen invites a similar rendering with respect to faith, hope and
charity.)
One of my reasons for drawing attention to the Twenty-third Psalm is to
say something about historicity. Although the object is inside history, at the deepest
level of the Judeo-Christian tradition, it transcends period. It does not do so
completely, but if that psalm touches you, we cannot say that it does not transcend
history at all. This is the best known of the one hundred and fifty Jewish psalms. There
is a history of the psalms, as there is of any text or any cultural matter. They
have been perpetually chanted in monasteries since the sixth century. Their settings have
changed, as have the languages in which they have been chanted. They were sung in Latin
for over a thousand years, put into the vernacular in the sixteenth century and into
English in the 1530s. The psalms have served as a bridge from Judaism to Christianity and
provided assurance, protection, well-being and comfort across the centuries and in the
face of adversity.
Just in case all this example is a candidate for being dismissed as the
nostalgic self-indulgence of a superannuated duffer, here are lines from the best-selling
rock album from the U2 Rattle and Hum tour (1988): Yea, though I walk in
the valley of the shadow, yet I will fear no evil. I will curse thy rod and staff. They no
longer comfort me. Love rescue me. A similar poignant longing is found (complete
with church choir) on the track, I Still Havent Found What Im Looking
For.
We must therefore find a place for relative historicity, our
appropriation of the concept of relative autonomy in cultural studies. My point is that
throughout our intellectual and spiritual tradition pace the historicity of
the subject the object abides, and therefore so does the subject.
The self is an imputed concept, but so are human nature,
subjectivity, totality, fragmentation, Kantian schemata, socialism, and, for that
matter, the external world, whether we think it fragmented or coherent. To believe
otherwise is despairing; it is paranoid-schizoid. In short, it is pessimism of the will.
So I say again: cut the crap and get on with the yarn. We are all psalmists, all writers
of epistles, whether to Corinthians or to lovedones or to colleagues.
In conclusion, I have a slightly sardonic observation: I believe that
the formalists and post-formalists have painted themselves into a corner. People whom I
found extremely haughty a few years ago are being nicer to me now. We asked them for
bread, and they gave us stones. They are now finding this out for themselves. Many of the
most Lacanian intellectuals are in Kleinian or Middle Group analyses. Each wants someone
to love him or her best. Film-makers who did the most abstract exercises have returned to
narrative naturalism (sometimes with a fig-leaf of lots of quotations from earlier films).
People who took up the most extreme positions about social relations are now trying to
struggle in couples and with children (and some left it too late and have deep regrets).
Many things accused of being paper tigers have mauled their mockers in the left and
among feminists. Many of those who made the most scathing critiques of conventional
culture are heard talking avidly about soap operas, post-Douglas Sirk readings of
television series such as Dallas, the power of romantic novels and what it is that
doughty Conservative women know that we do not. Just as religion knows something that we
do not, so does conventional society. If our critique leads to an alienation that leaves
us bitter, without hope, in pieces and freezing in the cold, we must think again about
what we dismantle and from what point of view we do it. If our conceptual tools serve us
ill, we must make a new testament.
Paper read at multidisciplinary conference on Rehinking the
Subject in Discourse McGill University, Montreal, March 1988; published inDiscours
Social/SSocial Discourse 2: 69-81,1989; also in Free Associations. 16: 81-96,
1989; also to appear in a collection, Whatever Happened to Human Nature? (Process
Press, in press).
REFERENCES
(Place of publication is London unless otherwise specified.)
Appignanesi, Lisa, ed. (1989) Postmodernism: ICA Documents. Free
Association Books.
Balint, Michael (1952) Primary Love and Psycho-analytic Technique; enlarged
ed., 1965. Tavistock.
Barham, Peter (1984) Schizophrenia and Human Value. Oxford:
Blackwell; reprinted Free Association Books, 1993.
Barnes, Mary and Berke, Joseph (1971) Mary Barnes: Two Accounts of a
Journey through Madness. MacGibbon and Kee; reprinted Free Association Books, 1991.
Berger, Peter and Luckmann, Thomas (1967) The Social Construction of
Reality. Garden City, N. Y.: Doubleday Anchor.
Berke, Joseph (1989) The Tyranny of Malice: Exploring the Dark Side
of Character and Culture. Simon and Schuster.
Bernstein, Richard (1986) What is the Difference That Makes a
Difference? H. G. Gadamer, J. Habermas and R. Rorty, in Philosophical Profiles:
Essays in Pragmatic Mode. Cambridge: Polity, pp. 5893.
Bion, Wilfred R. (1977) Seven Servants: Four Works by Wilfred Bion. N.
Y.: Aronson.
______ (1982) The Long Weekend, 1897-1919: Part of a Life: Abingdon:
Fleetwood; reprinted Free Association Books, 1986.
Burtt, Edwin A. (1932) The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern
Physical Science, 2nd ed. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Camus, Albert (1955) The Myth of Sisyphus, in The Myth
of Sisyphus and Other Essays. Knopf; reprinted N. Y.: Vintage, 1959, pp. 88-91.
Cassirer, Ernst (1953-57) Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, 3 vols.
New Haven, CT: Yale.
Copi, I. M. (1953) An Introduction to Logic. N. Y.: Macmillan.
Ellwood, Jane, ed. (1995) Psychosis: Treatment of Choice? Jessica
Kingsley.
Fairbairn, W. R. D. (1952) Psychoanalytic Studies of the
Personality. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Finlay, Marike (1989) Post-modernising Psychoanalysis
/Psychoanalysing Post-modernity: Reontologising the Subject in Discourse, Free
Assns. no. 16: 43-80.
Fitch, Frederick B. (1952) Symbolic Logic. N. Y.: Ronald.
Fry, E. L. (1966) Cubism. Thames & Hudson.
Gramsci, Antonio (1929-35) Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci. Lawrence
and Wishart, 1971.
Greenberg, Jay R. and Mitchell, Stephen A. (1983) Object Relations
in Psychoanalytic Theory. Harvard.
Grotstein, J. S., ed. (1983) Do I Dare Disturb the Universe? A
Memorial to Wilfred R. Bion. Caesura; reprinted Maresfield, 1983.
Guntrip, Harry (1977) Psychoanalytic Theory, Therapy and the Self. Maresfield.
Hinshelwood, R. D. (1991) A Dictionary of Kleinian Thought, 2nd
ed. Free Association Books.
Hume, David (1738) A Treatise on Human Nature, 2 vols. Dent,
1911.
Jackson, Murray and Williams, Paul (1994) Unimaginable Storms: A
Search for Meaning in Psychosis. Karnac.
Jacoby, Russell (1971) Towards a Critique of Automatic Marxism:
The Politics of Philosophy from Lukács to the Frankfurt School, Telos no.
10: 119-46.
Jameson, Frederic (1991) Postmodernism: Or , The Cultural Logic of
Late Capitalism. Verso.
Jay, Martin (1973) The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the
Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research 1923-1950. Boston, MA: Little,
Brown.
______ (1984) Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from
Lukács to Habermas. Cambridge: Polity.
Kierkegaard, S. (1846) Concluding Unscientific Postscript to the
Philosophical Fragments: a Mimic-Pathetic-Dialectic Composition. An Existential
Contribution. Princeton: Princeton, 1944.
Klein, Melanie (1975) The Writings of Melanie Klein, 4 vols.
Hogarth; reprinted Virago, 1988.
______ et al., eds. (1955) New Directions in Psycho-Analysis:
The Significance of Infant Conflicts in the Patterns of Adult Behaviour. Tavistock;
reprinted Maresfield
Klein, Sydney (1980 Autistic Phenomena in Neurotic
Patients, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 61: 395-401.
Kohon, Gregorio (1985) Objects Are Not People, Free
Assns. no. 2: 19-30.
______, ed. (1986) The British School of Psychoanalysis: The
Independent Tradition. Free Association Books.
Kovel, Joel (1988) The Radical Spirit: Essays on Psychoanalysis and
Society. Free Association Books.
______ (1991) History and Spirit. Boston: Beacon.
Laing, Ronald D. (1960) The Divided Self: An Existential Study of
Sanity and Madness. Tavistock; reprinted Penguin, 1965.
Langer, Suzanne K. (1942) Philosophy in a New Key. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard.
Lasch, Christopher (1979) The Culture of Narcissism: American Life
in an Age of Diminishing Expectations. N. Y.: Norton.
______ (1985) The Minimal Self: Psychic Survival in Troubled Times. Picador.
Lyotard, J. F. (1984) The Post-Modern Condition: A Report on
Knowledge. Manchester: Manchester..
Mannheim, Karl (1929-31) Ideology and Utopia an Introduction to the
Sociology of Knowledge. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Marcuse, Herbert 1955) Eros and Civilization: A Philosophical Inqiry
into Freud. Boston, MA: Beacon; 2nd ed., with a new preface and postscript by the
author. Allen Lane: Penguin Press, 1969.
______ (1964) One Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of
Advanced Industrial Societies. Routledge & Kegan Paul; reprinted Ark, 1986.
Meltzer, Donald et al. (1975) Explorations in Autism. Strath Tay: Clunie.
Merquior, J. G. (1986) From Prague to Paris: A Critique of
Structuralist and Post-Structuralist Thought. Verso.
Newman, Michael (1989) Revising Modernism, Representing
Postmodernism, in Appignanesi (1989), pp. 95-154.
Pap, Arthur (1963) An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Eyre
and Spottiswoode.
Pfeil, F. (1985) Makin Flippy-Floppy: Postmodernism and the
Baby Boom PMC, in M. Davis, et al., eds, The Year Left: An American
Socialist Yearbook. Verso, pp. 268-95.
Rey, Henri (1994) Universals of Psychoanalysis in the Treatment of
Psychotic and Borderline States: Factors of Space-Time and Language. Free Association
Books.
Richards, Barry, ed. (1984) Capitalism and Infancy: Essays on
Psychoanalysis and Politics. Free Association Books.
Rorty, Richard (1980) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.. Oxford: Blackwell.
______ (1982) Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-80). Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
______ (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Rosenfeld, Herbert (1965) Psychotic States. Hogarth; reprinted
Maresfield, 1982.
______(1987) Impasse and Interpretation: Therapeutic and
Anti-Therapeutic Factors in Psychoanalytic Treatment of Psychotic, Borderline, and
Neurotic Patients. Routledge.
Searles, Harold (1960 The Nonhuman Environment: In normal
Development and in Schizophrenia. Madison, CT: International Universities.
______ (1965) Collected Papers on Schizophrenia and Related
Subjects. Hogarth; reprinted Karnac, 1986.
Segal, Hanna (1973) Introduction to the Work of Melanie Klein. Hogarth; reprinted Karnac, 1988.
______ (1981) The Work of Hanna Segal: A Kleinian Approach to
Clinical Practice. Aronson; reprinted Free Association Books/ Maresfield Library,
1986.
Simon, Paul (1973) American Tune, There Goes
Rhymin Simon. CBS 69035.
Skinner, Quentin R. D. 91985) The Return to Grand Theory in the
Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Strawson, P. F. (1959) Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive
Metaphysics. Methuen.
Sutherland, J. D. (1980) The British Object Relations Theorists:
Balint, Winnicott, Fairbairn, Guntrip, J. Am. Psychoanal. Assn. 28: 829-60.
Taylor, Charles (1964) The Explanation of Behaviour. Routledge
& Kegan Paul.
Tustin, Frances (1986) Autistic Barriers in Neurotic Patients. Karnac.
Whitehead, Alfred N. (1926) Science and the Modern World. Macmillan;
reprinted Free Association Books, 1985.
Williams, Raymond (1986) The Uses of Cultural Theory, New
Left Rev. no. 158: 19-31.
Winnicott, Donald W. (1951) Transitional Objects and Transitional
Phenomena, in Through Paediatrics to Psycho-Analysis. Hogarth, 1982, pp. pp.
229-42.
______ (1952) Psychoses and Child Care, in Ibid., pp.
219-28.
______ (1988) Human Nature. Free Association Books.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953) Philosophical Investigations. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Young, Robert. M. (1966) Scholarship and the History of the
Behavioural Sciences, Hist. of Sci. 2: 1-51.
______ (1966a) The Divided Science, Delta 38: 13-18.
______ (1967) Animal Soul, in P. Edwards, ed., Encyclopedia of Philosophy. N. Y.: Macmillan, vol. 1, pp. 122-27.
______ (1967a) Philosophy of Mind and Related Issues, Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 18: 325-330.
______ (1968) Association of Ideas, in P. P. Wiener, ed. Dictionary
of the History of Ideas. N. Y.: Scribners, 1968-74, vol. 1, pp. 111-18.
______ (1971) Evolutionary Biology and Ideology: Then and
Now, Sci. Stud. 1: 177-206.
______ (1973) 'The Human Limits of Nature', in J. Benthall, ed., The
Limits of Human Nature. Allen Lane, pp. 235-74.
______ (1977) 'Science is Social Relations', Radical Sci. J. no. 5: 65-131.
______ (1979 How Societies Constitute Their Knowledge: A Labour
Process Perspective (typescript).
______ (1979a) Science is a Labour Process, Sci. for the
People nos. 43/44: 31-6.
______ (1979b) Why Are Figures so Significant? The Role and the
Critique of Quantification, in J. Irvine et al., eds., Demystifying Social
Statistics. Pluto, pp. 63-75.
______ (1981) 'The Naturalization of Value Systems in the Human
Sciences', in Problems in the Biological and Human Sciences, Milton Keynes: Open
University Press, pp. 63-110.
______ (1985) Darwinism is Social, in David Kohn, ed., The Darwinian Heritage. Princeton:
Princeton, pp. 609-38.
______(1985a) Darwin's Metaphor: Nature's Place in Victorian
Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge.
______ (1985b) Is Nature a Labour Process?, in L. Levidow
and R. M. Young, eds., Science, Technology and the Labour Process: Marxist Studies. Free
Association Books, vol. 2, pp. 206-32.
______ (1986) The Dense Medium: Television as Technology, Political
Papers 13: 3-5.
______ (1986a) 'Life among the Mediations: Labour, Groups, Breasts',
talk delivered to Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of
Cambridge.
______ (1986b) Sigmund Freud: Scientist and/or Humanist, Free
Assns. no. 6: 7-35.
______ (1987) Biography: The Basic Discipline for a Human
Science, Free Assns. no. 11: 108-30.
______ (1987a) Darwin and the Genre of Biography, in George
Levine, ed., One Culture: Essays in Science and Literature. Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press, pp. 203-24.
______(1987a) 'Racist Society, Racist Science', in D. Gill and L.
Levidow, eds., Anti-Racist Science Teaching. Free Association Books, pp. 16-42;
reprinted in D. Gill et al., eds., Racism and Education: Structures and
Strategies . Sage, 1992, pp. 303-19.
______ (1988) 'Darwin, Marx, Freud and the Foundations of the Human
Sciences', Cheiron Newsletter. Spring, pp. 7-12.
______ (1989) Persons, Organisms... and Primary Qualities,
in J. Moore, ed., History, Humanity and Evolution: Essays for John C. Greene.
Cambridge: Cambridge, pp. 375-401.
______ (1989a) The Role of Psychoanalysis and Psychotherapy in
the Human Sciences, paper presented to Zangwill Club, Department of Experimental
Psychology, University of Cambridge.
______ (1989b) 'Transitional Phenomena: Production and Consumption', in
B. Richards, ed., Crises of the Self: Further Essays on Psychoanalysis and Politics. Free Association Books, pp. 57-74.
______ (1990) The Mind-Body Problem, in Robert C. Olby et
al., eds. Companion to the History of Modern Science. Routledge, pp. 702-11.
______ (1995) Across the Borderline, in Ellwood (1995).
______ et al. (1981) Science, Technology, Medicine and the
Socialist Movement, Rad. Sci. J. 11: 3-70.
Copyright: The Author
Address for correspondende: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|