Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
HUMAN NATURE
by Robert M. Young
The entry on human nature in the Dictionary of the History of Ideas occupies
a whole page and extends from Achilles, Aeschulus, Agamemnon and Alcmaeon, the last of
whom founded anatomy, to Xenophanes, Xenophon and Zeus, the last of whom founded the
world. The three founding figures of the empiricist tradition have it in the titles of
major treatises: Humane Nature: Or the Fundamental Elements of Policie (1650) by
Thomas Hobbes, An Essay Concerning Human Nature (1690) by John Locke, and A
Treatise of Human Nature (1738) by David Hume. All were concerned to deny the
existence of innate ideas in human nature. Hence, the problem of what is given and what is
experienced lies at the foundations of our question.
It is a perennial question. Without making a special effort I recalled
the following books I have read: Human Nature and Conduct by John Dewey; Human
Nature and Human History by R. G. Collingwood; Human Nature and the Social Order by
Charles Horton Cooley; Human Nature by D. W. Winnicott; The Evolution of Human
Nature by C. Judson Herrick; On Human Nature by E. O. Wilson; From Genesis
to Genocide: The Meaning of Human Nature and the Power of Behavior Control by Steven
Chorover; Human Nature by Christopher Berry; Nature, Human Nature, and Society by
Paul Heyer; Ideas of Human Nature: An Historical Introduction by Roger Trigg; Beast
and Man: The Roots of Human Nature by Mary Midgley. I almost forgot The Limits of
Human Nature, edited by Jonathan Benthall, to which I contributed a critique of the
terms of reference of the collection. If we stretch our search criteria the tiniest bit,
we soon come to The Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 and the question
of human nature as an ensemble of social relations, a phrase to which I shall return.
The phrase human nature is, once you reflect on it for a
moment, more problematic than helpful. Does it imply that humanity if wholly natural? In
some sense it must be, since we evolved as biological organisms by natural selection. But
does the modifier mean that human nature is somehow not reducible to natural processes?
And our troubles begin. That is, all versions of determinism and reductionism have wanted
it both ways: to assert that humans (biologically: our species) are wholly natural but
then to find it problematic, since our concept of nature is impoverished with respect to
the matters which we most value about our humanity, beginning with value itself or the
banishment of final causes or teleology from the official paradigm of explanation of
modern science. That paradigm had, as one way out, Cartesian dualism, where mind was
defined as that which does not pertain to matter and the essence of which was non-material
thought, free will. Passion lurked somewhere in between the poles of the
ontological dualism.
Alexander Pope put it beautifully in his Essay on Man
(1733):
Know then thyself, presume not God to scan;
The proper study of mankind is Man.
Placd on this isthmus of a middle state,
A being darkly wise, and rudely great:
With too much knowledge for the Sceptic side,
With too much weakness for the Stoics pride,
He hangs between; in doubt to act or rest;
In doubt to deem himself a God, or Beast;
In doubt his Mind or Body to prefer;
Born but to die, and reasning but to err;
Alike in ignorance, his reason such,
Whether he thinks too little, or too much:
Chaos of Thought and Passion, all confused;
Still by himself abused, or disabused;
Created half to rise, and half to fall;
Great lord of all things, yet a prey to all;
Sole judge of Truth, in endless Error hurled:
The glory, jest and riddle of the world!
We could dwell at length on this poem as an embodiment of pre-Darwinian
thinking, a perfect evocation of the middle state occupid by hmanity in
The Great Chain of Being, so beautifully explored by Arthur O. Lovejoy (1936),
the founder of the discipline of the history of ideas, which provided the most general
abstraction about the cosmos before evolution took its place in the mid-nineteenth century
Another hoary way of posing the issue is nature versus
nurture. We have the reductionism of sociobiology at one extreme, with E. O.
Wilson writing about ethics as a branch of biology. At the other we find whom?
Sartre with Existence precedes essence? The moralistic voluntarism of extreme
fundamentalist religions? I want to come at the debate in the tradition which has
influenced cultural studies from my own background and then engage with the avant garde debate. I begin by saying that if you have a developmental psychology, you have a theory
of human nature. Many, notably gays and lesbians, have sought to get off a set of
deterministic developmental tramlines which led inevitably to the heterosexual hegemony
dictated by Freuds libido theory, a theory which lies at the foundations of orthodox
psychoanalysis and is certainly, in every version Ive seen, biologically
reductionist. Indeed, as I have sketched in another paper, theoreticians of gay and
lesbian sexuality want to say, following Laplanche, that the exceptions to normality in
sexual orientation and behaviour overwhelm the rule and that there is no normal path in
the test case area of gender identity, sexual orientation and sexual practices. In their
critique of psychoanalytic theories of lesbianism, Noreen OConnor and Joanna Ryan
put forward the long-term goal of eschewing all forms of naturalism in
psychoanalytic thinking, but right after saying that they draw back from the brink
and add, but to do so does not involve denying or ignoring the significance in any
one individuals life of their biological sex as they see and experience it
(1993, p. 246).
I take the view that if you have a psychology, thats equivalent
to having a theory of human nature, however much latitude for the role of different
experiences and different developmental pathways there may be within the particular theory
you espouse. In fact, I cannot imagine that it could be otherwise. Going further, a whole
class of disciplines, problematically referred to as the human sciences, and
others more scientifically basic and so-called natural than they, depend on
some notion of human nature. Otherwise, the disciplines have no object of study. Im
thinking of human evolution, human genetics, human ethology, developmental psychology,
psychology of personality, social psychology, social anthropology, sociology, political
science and, of course, psychoanalysis and group relations. Those who would sweep aside
the concept of human nature would, I submit, have to abrogate all these disciplines. Each,
in its particular way, seeks to specify an ensemble of characteristics common to members
of our species to illuminate our species being using the methods and assumptions of
natural science and/or hermeneutics.
If we expend this location in the study of humankind, we find
philosophical notions which have been challenged as problematic but remain hardy
perennials: self and person. Critics of the mind-body dichotomy such as P. F. Strawson
argue that in the everyday metaphysics which he sets out to describe the concept of person
is ontologically prior to those of mind and body and that keeping our eye on this
philosophical point makes our agonies over Cartesian dualism much less painful.
On the other hand, we should also acknowledge that the concept of human
nature is routinely used for reactionary, demoralising and hegemonic purposes. Indeed, I
once made a film documentary about ideas of human nature which began with some clichéd
stills and voice-overs uttered by the programmes researchers to the effect that
Thats human nature. You cant change human nature.
You just have to accept it and get used to it. Yet those among us who are
psychotherapists are in the business of trying to alter the natures of the people with
whom we work, though we soon learn not to be too sanguine about how much we can
accomplish.
I now have before me two strands of argument. The first grants nature
its due. We are the product of evolution; our natures are not infinitely plastic, although
we are on the threshold of making them pretty damned malleable by as-yet incalculable acts
of genetic engineering. On the other hand, we know that political conservatism uses the
putatively given for its own reactionary purposes. Thats the point of
Social Darwinism and the functionalist tradition in the human sciences and politics.
Philosophers and cultural studies people can point this out until they are blue in the
face, but pure choice is never going to emerge. There is a third strand, one which I find
in Rortys essay on The Contingency of Selfhood (1989), which stresses
the uniqueness of the individual and points to narrative and biography as a containing
medium for both the given and the contingent and idiosyncratic.
One arena in which these matters were fiercely debated was between the
anti-instinctualism of Erich Fromm and the instinctual radicalism of Herbert Marcuse. I
cite this example to loosen our assumptions about these issues, since in this vehement
exchange Fromm, the romantic softie, was the one stressing the role of experience, while
Marcuse, the libertarian, visionary revolutionary Marxist was arguing that only belief in
instinct could guarantee the basis in human nature for negativity, for rebellion, for the
Great Refusal to be mashed into one-dimensionally by the ever more oppressive
ideology and hegemony of Advanced Industrial Society which was undermining the Freudian
ego, the authority of the father and spontaneous individuality. Leftists are not always
the lefter than thou on the nature-nurture continuum. Indeed, there is a recent
fascinating book by Paul Crook (1994) which draws our attention to the whole gamut of
positions based on Darwinian evolution, with Prince Peter Kropotkins
biologically-based anarchism in Mutual Aid (1902) at the extreme left of the
continuum.
I have so far put the issues in terms which are familiar to me as an
historian of biology and the human sciences. I now turn to the rhetoric of the Continental
critique of humanism and the concept of human nature. As I understand it, what was going
on was a critique of a concept which was so abstract and universal and so divorced from
the contingencies of history and class and collectivity that it was thought to function in
a reactionary way. It was part of a philosophical anthropology about man in
general. Much of the debate, focused on critiques of neo-Kantian enlightenment humanism,
and this was interrelated with fierce discussions about orthodoxy and humanism in the
French Communist Party. Humanism was code for Socialist Humanism, mounting a moral and
political critique of the Stalinist purge trials and of the belief that the end justifies
the means, while the alternative picture was allied with the party and presented itself as
objective, scientific, on the side of what had to be done to bring about communism. It
seems to me that this meant abrogating the basis for morality in the name of the future;
Id also say it implicitly appealed to a whoppoing great idealisation of humankind in
the communist millennium.
Arthur Koestlers Darkness at Noon (a roman a clef about the purge
trial of Nikolai Bukharin) was one battlefield in France, just as Animal Farm was
in England. The central character, Rubashov, finally confessed to whatever his
interrogators required, but he also came, by a painful process of self-examination, to
feel that, as he put is, not only did the end not justify the means, but, as he put it, on
the contrary, only purity of means can justify the ends. This book was such an
important focus in the debate that I want to quote the crucial passage, which occurs very
near the end of the book:
;It was quiet in the cell. Rubashov heard only the creaking of his steps on the tiles.
Six and a half steps to the door, whence they must come to fetch him, six and a half steps
to the window, behind which night was falling. Soon it would be over. But when he asked
himself, "For what actually are you dying?", he found no answer.
It was a mistake in the system; perhaps it lay in the precept which until now he
had held to be uncontestable, in whose name he had sacrificed others and was himself being
sacrificed: in the precept, that the end justifies the means. It was this sentence which
had killed the great fraternity of the Revolution and made them all run amuk. What had he
once written in his diary? We have thrown overboard all conventions, our sole
guiding principle is that of consequent logica: we are sailing without ethical
ballast.
Perhaps the heart of the evil lay there. Perhaps it did not suit mankind to sail
without ballast. And perhaps reason alone was a defective compass, which led one on such a
winding, twisted course that the goal finally disappeared in the mist.
Perhaps now would come a time of great darkness.
Perhaps later, much later, the new movement would arise with new flag, a
new spirit knowing of both: of economic fatality and the oceanic sense.
Perhaps the members of the new party will wear monks cowls, and preach that only
purity of means can justify the ends. Perhaps they will teach that the tenet is wrong
which says that a man is the product of one million divided by one million, and will
introduce a new kind of arithmetic based on multiplication: on the joining of a million of
individuals to form a new entity which, no longer an amorphous mass, will develop a
consciousness as an individuality of its own, with an oceanic feeling
increased a millionfold, in unlimited yet self-contained space.
Rubashov broke off his pacing and listened. The sound of a muffled drumming came
down the corridor. Koestler, 1940, pp. 206-7)
(This, buy the way is the source of the motto of Process Press, while
the name of the imprint is intended to evoke the political position that process
determines result, another version of Rubashovs slogan.) For Koestler, like Orwell
and his Russian inspiration, Zamiatin (the author of We, a Taylorist dystopia set
in post-revolutionary USSR), treating people like animals or automata, was bound to
bring about disaster. People have to be treated with dignity, because they are fellow
human beings to whom a sense of universal humanity was attributed, no matter how reduced
their circumstances, no matter how noble the cause which might justify denigrating them.
Another of the foci of the debate was the wake of Nazism and Vichy, which made it
painfully apparent that individualism (even if wrapped up in the abstracted ethics of the
Kantian categorical imperative) would not do in the face of organised evil.
Even though I have mentioned the events and political and philosophical
debates around the Second World War, it is too easy to think of this controversy about
human nature as abstruse. I have recently come upon the most current versions of it and
have been told by a perceptive email correspondent how fellow graduate students at his
American university bandy the latest contemptuous phrases which have been coined to look
down upon the preoccupations of superannuated people who dont know where cultural
debate is at at the moment. He was thinking ruefully that these poseurs
havent the faintest idea why these issues matter. Culture is the domain where values
are celebrated, tested, cultuivated (cultured), husbanded. The context of this
debate or at least the early phase which I am considering here was the
gathering storm of the war and what became apparent in its aftermath: purge trials, Vichy,
collaboration, genocide, the Russian Front. It is hard to keep this context vivid. The
urgency of the purchase of morality could not have been greater or more immediate. Certain
key books and films help me to keep a sense of perspective. Vichy brings to my mind
Lacombe Lucien and Casablanca. Genocide recalls Julia,
Sophies Choice, The Power and the Glory, Shoah,
Schindlers Ark, The Diary of Anne Frank, The moral atmosphere of Naziam
and its aftermarh evokes Leni Riefenstals The Triumph of the Will,
Albert Speers Diaries, William Shirers history of Nazism. The Russian purges
and war recall The 900 Days (siege of Leningrad), Cancer Ward, The First Circle,
The Gulag Archipelago, Reds. The moral climate of post-war Europe
brings up The Third Man, The Prisoner (Alec Guiness) and the
writings of John Le Carré .
These provide images to add flesh and bone and the face of agony and
despair to the six million jews who perished and the the twenty-five million Russians who
were lost in the war. Less is known about how many died in the Gulag, but I read an
article on the historiography of this matter which considered estimates between eighteen
and twenty-one and a half million, of whom a third are thought to have been executed. The
lowest estimate I have seen is 799,455 Soviet citizens executed by the secret police
between 1921 and 1953, of whom 681,692 were killed in 1937-38.
This period saw the greatest willed destruction of human life in
recorded history. The values the centre, as the poet has it
which did not hold during those years, was the domain which the culture dubbed
humanism and to which it imputed value because of a shared human nature. It is
a grotesque understatement to say that these values did not ptotect and preserve human
dignity and life. And this is what the (mainly French, with Heidegger as a fequent source)
intellectuals did: Sartre, de Beauvoir, Camus, Merleau-Ponty, Garaudy, followed by Levi
Strauss, Althusser, Foucault, Derrida, Baudrillard, Lacan, Deluze, Guattari, Lyotard, with
foreign fellow-travellers Jameson, Jencks, Rorty Not to have brought these concepts
which were basic to a sense of what the UN called a Universal Declaration of Human Rights
would have been stupid, immoral and head-in-the-sand in the extreme.
Moving focus to a newer generation which did not centre its thought on
debates about repression, genocide, orthodoxy and the justification of Stalinism,
feminists, gays and lesbians have as Ive mentioned their own reasons
for opposing essentialism, the shibboleth that anatomy is destiny or that patriarchy is so
universal that it is natures way. Some of my correspondents on the internet deny all
connection between debates about Marxism and communism and their anti-humanism and
opposition to notions of human nature. They quote Foucaults disclaimer: he was never
a structuralist, never a Marxist.
Here are some of the terms in the debates in question. In my view they
are all exemplars of the debate over Marxs Sixth Thesis on Feuerbach, but Ill
mention them before turning to that text. Here are the terms which I have harvested:
determination, inscription, construction (and, of course, its cynical heir,
deconstruction), resolution of forces, socialisation. When we spell out some of the
determinations which make the general terms more contingent, more inside history, they
divide into things like class, nationality, race, caste, education, gender. Some of the
dichotomies are humanism versus science, humanism versus orthodoxy, humanism versus
structuralism, alienation versus surplus value, subjective versus objective, subjects
versus structures, intentions versus structural causation, moral versus factual, and
again socialist humanism versus structuralist Marxism, the claim that Marx
was first a humanist and then, after an epistemological break, an analyst of structural
causation. It is my view that the move from people and history to inscription and
discourse to rooting the debate in language and texts has not yet been
sufficiently lluminated or sufficiently subjected to critique.
I believe that the question of human nature per se versus an
'ensemble of social relations' is a foundational debate in these matters. What Norman
Geras did in his rather rabbinical but admirable exegetical study, Marx and Human
Nature: Refutation of a Legend (1983), was to analyse away the claim that Marx ever
believed that saying that human nature is an ensemble of social relations meant that he
rejected the idea of human nature. I believee that what he does is more than an exegesis:
it is a convincing exemplar and settles the debate for me. I shall therefore rely heavily
on his argument in what follows. Geras takes the view that Marxs well-known
emphases on historical specificity and historical change did not detach him from every
general conception of human nature (p. 19). He argues that there is much conceptual
space between something fixed and unchanging, on the one hand, and utter changeability, on
the other. There is a wide range, many degrees of mutability (p. 24).
Let us dwell on this key text. Marx wrote, Feuerbach resolves the
essence of religion into the essence of man. But the essence of man is no
abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the
social relations (q. p. 29). Marx is, of course, attacking Feuerbachs
conception of religion as ahistorical and asocial, abstracted from any social formation.
Religion is a social product, and the abstracted individual belongs to a particular form
of society (pp. 29-30). The phrase usually translated as the essence of man or
the human essence can equally correctly be rendered as human
nature. Marx is objecting to Feuerbachs viewing humanity exclusively in terms
of general, species or natural characteristics. Marx says that Feuerbach refers too
much to nature and too little to politics (q. p. 31). Human nature is, says Marx,
no abstraction inherent in each single individual (q. p. 32). It is more than
that, which is why he invokes social relations (p. 34). Human nature must include
historicity and variability (p. 39). To stress social relations is not to deny general
characteristics (p. 47). Marx is concerned to stress the relation of humanity to history
and not to set up an antithesis between nature and history (p. 61).
Here is a collection of quotations from participants in the debate who
opposed the concept of human nature: Q pp. 50-52, 53, 54.
Geras sums up his opposition to the anti-human nature position as
follows: ...if the nature of man depends on the ensemble of social relations, it
does not depend wholly on them, it is conditioned but not determined by them, because they
themselves depend on, that is, are partly explained by human nature, which is a component
of the nature of man (p. 68). Indeed, Marx frequently lists a set of universal human
needs: food, clothing, shelter, fuel, rest, sleep, hygiene, maintenance of the body, fresh
air and sunlight, intellectual requirements, social intercourse, sexual needs, support in
infancy, old age, infirmity, a safe and healthy working environment. These determine the
universal metabolism between humanity and nature (p. 83). As the Communist Manifesto puts it, in order to see that these needs get met, we need an association in which
the free development of each is the condition of the free development of all (which,
by the way was the motto of Free Association Books until it went commercial).
We are touching here on the assumptions of historical materialism,
Marxs whole distinctive approach to society. It is clear from the above,
says Geras, that it rests squarely upon the idea of a human nature. It highlights
that specific nexus of universal needs and capacities which explains the human production
process and mans organised transformation of the material environment; which process
and transformation it treats in turn as the basis of both the social order and of
historical change. So, it is not even true, in other words, although frequently supposed,
that being for its part general and unchanging, human nature cannot itself enter into the
explanation of change. On the contrary, if human beings have a history which gives rise to
the most fabulous variety of social shapes and forms, it is because of the kind of beings
they, all of them, are; human nature... plays a part in explaining the historical
specificities of the nature of man (pp. 107-8).
The components which are natural and those which are social make up the
mixture of causal factors which the nature-nurture debate finds endlessly problematic.
Social constructivists like Donna Haraway and me would make it more so by pointing to the
social construction and ideological constitution of the parameters and terms of reference
of the concepts of both nature and nurture. The sensible point is that human nature is
never pure and ahistorical. As Geras insists, it is always socially mediated (p. 112). Nor
are natural characteristics found in a pure state. They are also socially mediated:
they do not form a separate reality, ontologically distinct from qualities
that are culturally induced (p. 114). Human nature is an abstraction but a
valid one, denoting some common, natural characteristics of humankind. These may not be a separate reality, ontologically distinct and what have you. but they are a reality (p.
115).
I am not yet a close enough student of some of the key texts in these
debates to say whether or not I would want to mount the same arguments about humanism as I
have about human nature, but I am inclined to think that I would. In my part of the
academic world history, philosophy and social studies of science humanism is
broadly seen as the alternative to scientism. The humanists are the progressive and
enlightened ones, embattled by the positivists and Popperians. Humanism is also the term
applied to a progressive movement in the Renaissance, returning to the Greeks and leading
to the origins of modern thought, and I have no hesitation in choosing between those
alternatives between humanism and its opponents, if I am forced to such a simplistic
choice. In fact, it is of the essence of recent developments in this interrelated set of
disciplines that science is inside culture, not an alternative to it. Here is a typical
quotation from an essay by Yankelovitch on the concept of human nature: 'Nature does not
exist apart from culture. Each is constitutive of the other. It is misleading even to
conceive of human nature as something that can exist outside culture' (Yankelovich, 1973,
p. 424). Indeed, there is good contact between these debates, with Rorty arguing that
science is nothing more than one of the bibliographical niches in the library. That it not
to say that there is no nature per se only that we can only know it through
cultural forms, of which science is one, not the foundational one, and certainly not the
last court of appeal if science means reduction to physico-chemical explanations and an
impoverished view of our humanity.
Having, I trust, smitten the ignorant opponents of the idea of human
nature before your eyes, I now feel in a position to specify some candidates which
psychoanalysis has to nominate for elements of a defensible idea of human nature. Each
such element is open to challenge and some are more controversial than others. Any
objection to the concept of the unconscious, to unconscious motivation, to the superego,
to infantile sexuality, to the Oedipus complex, to adolescence? What about transference
and countertransference? If we move on to concepts which hail from different sects, I
would, as I have already said, nominate object relations theory as the heart of a
psychoanalytic idea of the centre of the inner world and the locus of the sense of self.
We should note in passing that in the Kleinian theory of object relations, certain imagoes
are said to be innate. I would also propose Winnicotts transitional objects and
transitional phenomena and Kleins concepts of unconscious phantasy and the
paranoid-schizoid and depressive positions. Nominations remain open. Also, ask yourself
what these concepts are if not candidates for elements of a psychoanalytic model of human
nature.
I turn now to some more detailed examples. If we accept this, we can
begin to think of our psychoanalytic work inside the larger political and cultural project
which postmodernism has either eschewed or attempted to abrogate. Here are passages which
are dear to my heart (which some of you will know) about translating between Kleinian and
Freudian concepts about the Oedipus complex and what Kleinians call the Oedipal
situation. 'The primitive Oedipal conflict described by Klein takes place in the
paranoid-schizoid position when the infant's world is widely split and relations are
mainly to part objects. This means that any object which threatens the exclusive
possession of the idealised breast/mother is felt as a persecutor and has projected into
it all the hostile feelings deriving from pregenital impulses' (Bell, 1992, p. 172)
If development proceeds satisfactorily, secure relations with good
internal objects leads to integration, healing of splits and taking back projections. 'The
mother is then, so to speak, free to be involved with a third object in a loving
intercourse which, instead of being a threat, becomes the foundation of a secure relation
to internal and external reality. The capacity to represent internally the loving
intercourse between the parents as whole objects results, through the ensuing
identifications, in the capacity for full genital maturity. For Klein, the resolution of
the Oedipus complex and the achievement of the depressive position refer to the same
phenomena viewed from different perspectives' (ibid.). Ron Britton puts it very
elegantly: 'the two situations are inextricably intertwined in such a way that one cannot
be resolved without the other: we resolve the Oedipus complex by working through the
depressive position and the depressive position by working through the Oedipus complex'
(Britton, 1992, p. 35).
In the recent work of Kleinians this way of thinking has been applied
to broader issues, in particular, the ability to symbolise and learn from experience.
Integration of the depressive position which we can now see as resolution of the
Oedipus complex is the sine qua non of the development of 'a capacity for
symbol formation and rational thought' (p. 37). Greater knowledge of the object 'includes
awareness of its continuity of existence in time and space and also therefore of the other
relationships of the object implied by that realization. The Oedipus situation exemplifies
that knowledge. Hence the depressive position cannot be worked through without working
through the Oedipus complex and vice versa' (p. 39). Britton also sees 'the depressive
position and the Oedipus situation as never finished but as having top be re-worked in
each new life situation, at each stage of development, and with each major addition to
experience or knowledge' (p. 38).
This way of looking at the Oedipal situation also offers a way of
thinking of self-knowledge or insight: 'The primal family triangle provides the child with
two links connecting him separately with each parent and confronts him with the link
between them which excludes him. Initially this parental link is conceived in primitive
part-object terms and in the modes of his own oral, anal and genital desires, and in terms
of his hatred expressed in oral, anal and genital terms. If the link between the parents
perceived in love and hate can be tolerated in the child's mind, it provides him with a
prototype for an object relationship of a third kind in which he is a witness and not a
participant. A third position then comes into existence from which object relationships
can be observed. Given this, we can also envisage being observed. This provides us
with a capacity for seeing ourselves in interaction with others and for entertaining
another point of view whilst retaining our own, for reflecting on ourselves whilst being
ourselves' (Britton, 1989, p. 87). To recapitulate, I trust that it is clear that we have
here a candidate for a component of human nature called insight and
self-knowledge.
I want now to quote in full the locus classicus for a concept
which I believe to be central to our understanding of human aggression and
destructiveness. The concept is Kleins most influential one, projective
identification. It is defined in her paper, Notes on Some Schizoid Mechanisms
(1946). Klein concludes seven pages on the fine texture of early paranoid and schizoid
mechanisms as follows: 'So far, in dealing with persecutory fear, I have singled out the
oral element. However, while the oral libido still has the lead, libidinal and aggressive
impulses and phantasies from other sources come to the fore and lead to a confluence or
oral, urethral and anal desires, both libidinal and aggressive. Also the attacks on the
mother's breast develop into attacks of a similar nature on her body, which comes to be
felt as it were as an extension of the breast, even before the mother is conceived of as a
complete person. The phantasied onslaughts on the mother follow two main lines: one is the
predominantly oral impulse to suck dry, bite up, scoop out and rob the mother's body of
its good contents... The other line of attack derives from the anal and urethral impulses
and implies expelling dangerous substances (excrements) out of the self and into the
mother. Together with these harmful excrements, expelled in hatred, split-off parts of the
ego are also projected onto the mother or, as I would rather call it, into the
mother. [Klein adds a footnote at this crucial point, to the effect that she is describing
primitive, pre-verbal processes and that projecting 'into another person' seems to
her 'the only way of conveying the unconscious process I am trying to describe'. Much
misunderstanding and lampooning of Kleinianism could have been avoided if this point was
more widely understood.] These excrements and bad parts of the self are meant not only to
injure but also to control and to take possession of the object. In so far as the mother
comes to contain the bad parts of the self, she is not felt to be a separate individual
but is felt to be the bad self.
'Much of the hatred against parts of the self is now directed towards
the mother. This leads to a particular form of identification which establishes the
prototype of an aggressive object-relation' (Klein, 1946, pp. 7-8). Note carefully that we
have here the model the template, the fundamental experience of
all of the aggressive features of human relations. Six years later Klein adds the
following sentence: 'I suggest for these processes the term "projective
identification"' (ibid.).
Whether or not you find this helpful or would willingly place
projective identification on your list of accepted concepts, it is certainly a candidate
for inclusion as a basic aspect of the destructive side of our species and can help to
illuminate much of what we regret about the history of human inhumanity, what Freud meant
when he said, in Civilization and Its Discontents, Man is a wolf to other
men. Ill now try to bring it into contact with the Marxist debate which I was
discussing earlier.
One way of capturing the good side of concepts of human nature while
avoiding the reactionary aspects is to have a look at the concept of second nature. Second
nature is not first nature or biology. It is deeply sedimented experience, so deeply
embedded that we experience it as natural, intuitive, common sense. I have argued in Mental
Space that to become a member of a society, tribe, sect, gang or other grouping, one
has to take on its projective identifications. That is what it is to be a member. A way of
thinking about this in Marxist terms is to consider the concept of second nature.
Second nature is what we are up against in ourselves, our families and
groups, our institutions and in the dead labour of the conversion of relations between
people into relations between things, which occurs in the real subordination of
manufacturing and in routine at work. It is the enemy of spontaneity and of Eros. It is
thanatic, i.e., derived from the death instinct or Thanatos. Thinking about treating
relations between people as though they were relations between things lies at the heart of
Marx's critique of the fetishism of commodities (Marx, 1976, pp. 163-77). It is part of a
family of concepts about alienation in capitalist society, which includes the split
between facts and values, the treatment of social relations as though they could be
reduced to laws and the extension of the categories of science into other domains, which
is characteristic of scientism, economism, so-called vulgar Marxism, and also
characterised the Marxism of the latter part of the nineteenth century, during the Second
International (Young, 1977). Those who have invoked the concept of second nature within
the Marxist tradition see all of the above as forms of it. This analysis can be extended
into more recent theoretical excursions of science into social relations which, as
Ive already said, characterise sociobiology and functionalism in the social sciences
and systems theory in psychotherapy and psychiatry (Young, 1981; Kitcher, 1985).
The person who did most to develop the critique of second nature within
the Marxist tradition was the Hungarian philosopher Georg Lukács. The locus classicus for
his work in this area is his essay on 'Reification and the Consciousness and the
Proletariat' (Lukács, 1923, pp. 83-222). In it he characterised the ways in which human
praxis, that is, willed behaviour based on thought-out goals, is converted into process.
Reification means, literally, 'thingification' the conversion of social relations
into thing-like regularities, devoid of conscious, meaningful deliberation. He did not,
however, originate the concept. Some would say Democritus did when he opposed Aristotle's
belief that the qualification to rule was determined at birth, by nature. Democritus
argued that it was informed by education, which constituted a 'second nature' (Jacoby,
1981, p 118). In the eighteenth century Rousseau saw second nature as something to create in order to repair what nature lacked to provide organic unity. It was also a
concept in Hegel's philosophy and was developed in Lukács' Theory of the Novel, where
he describes second nature in vivid terms as 'a charnel-house of long-dead interiorities'
(Lukács, 1971, p. 64). The self-made environment was described as a prison rather than a
parental home (Ibid.).
In his fine book on the concept of totality, Martin Jay describes
Lukács view as follows, 'Extrapolating from Marx's discussion of the "fetishism of
commodities" in Capital and applying insights from Bergson, Simmel and Weber,
he introduced the notion of reification to characterise the fundamental experience of
bourgeois life. This term, one not in fact found in Marx himself, meant the petrification
of living processes into dead things, which appeared as an alien "second
nature". Weber's "iron cage" of bureaucratic rationalisation, Simmel's
"tragedy of culture" and Bergson's spatialisation of dure were thus all
part of a more general process' (Jay, 1984, p. 109). Lukács' view of the result of
revolutionary change was that 'The mysterious impenetrability of the thing-in-itself will
be revealed as no more than the illusion of a reified consciousness incapable of
recognising itself in its products', once the external world is 'no longer perceived as
ruled by alien forces experienced as if they were "second nature" (Jay, 1984, p.
111). Society as second nature was thus an illusion to be shattered (Jay, 1984, p. 269).
However, to do this in theory is far from achieving de-reification in practice. 'Focusing
solely on the "second nature"' that was reified history, he neglected to probe
the role of 'first nature' in human life, a mistake for which Western Marxists of very
different persuasions were to take him to task' (Jay, 1984, p.116). This was particularly
true of the critiques of his work by Antonio Gramsci and Karl Korsch.
Other Marxists who were, I suppose I should say, more pessimistic, have
taken up the concept to good effect. Theodor Adorno wrote about the natural laws of
history as ideology so far as they are hypostatized as unchangeable givens of nature
(Adorno, 1973). Even so, they are real as the laws of movement of an unconscious society
(quoted in Jacoby, 1981, p. 119). Second nature should be seen not as biology but
as history that is congealed into nature. It became congealed because it is imprisoned in
the dungeons of repetition both in social forms and in individual neurosis. It is frozen
history in the social forms and frozen distress in the individual. (ibid.). (A
group of psychoanalysts working to develop the mental health services in Nicaragua have
drawn attention to a related phenomenon the frozen grief of people suffering so
much from social turmoil that they cannot mourn.) All forms of social and individual
alienation can be thus characterised, including culture itself and especially capitalist
institutions (Jay, 1984, pp. 43 & 78).
Jean-Paul Sartre also took up the concept and wrote about 'the inertia
of infrastructures, the resistance of economic and even natural conditions, the binding of
personal relations in things'. All of this is what Sartre called the 'practico-inert', the
sedimentation of human actions into social structures that lost their human quality and
resisted the freedom of individuals and groups (Poster, 1975, p.177-8). What in
reality is the socially mediated sedimentation of second nature is therefore presented as
nature as such, and in psychology is seen as primal, instinctual nature (Schneider, 1975,
pp. 52, 59-60). So, reification becomes the capitalist form of second nature 'the
form of unconsciousness of an unliberated humanity' (Jacoby, 1981, p. 120). If we apply
these concepts to psychoanalytic theory, the ego becomes reified and automated within
these social forms. This can, of course, be as true of a nominally adjusted person as it
can of a neurotic one. This issue was a central concern in Joel Kovel's book The Age of
Desire (Kovel, 1982).
I won't be surprised if all this seems very new and esoteric to some
and very old hat to others. What I am offering is a perspective which attempts to bring
social critique and psychoanalytic theory into one shared mode of discourse about human
nature. For example, psychosomatic disease can be seen as self-reification, the lodging of
unresolved unconscious conflicts into organic structures and processes.
Now socialism and Marxism set out to cast all this aside, and Freud
thought this a forlorn hope. De-reification is an attempt to recapture the human origins
of the social world that have been mystified under capitalism as a kind of second nature.
(Jay, 1984, p. 228) The revolutionary process and especially the elimination
of private property is designed to overcome this alienation. Freud is often thought
of as someone who did not hold overtly political views, although he is always considered a
liberal. In fact, near the end of his life, he wrote a set of New Introductory Lectures (Freud, 1933) which were designed to help the publishing house with which he was
associated to get out of a situation (which I know too well) of not quite being able to
break even. In the last lecture he addressed himself to the whole question of
psychoanalysis in relation to world views. He says that the political aim of the abolition
of private property sprang from a misguided illusion about human nature. He did not
himself take a view on the economic consequences of the Soviet attempt to build communism
but said, 'I can recognise it's psychological presuppositions as an untenable illusion'
(quoted in Gay, 1988, p. 549). He argued that aggression was not created by property but,
rather, was a source of pleasure (ibid.). Freud's theory of civilisation 'views
life in society as an imposed compromise and hence as an essentially insoluble
predicament' (Gay, 1988, p. 547). He says that we can neither live without civilisation
nor live happily within it, but at best we can achieve a truce between desire and control'
(p. 548). Freud wrote, 'I recognise ever more clearly that the events of human history,
the interactions between human nature, cultural development, and the precipitants of
primeval experiences (as whose representative religion pushes to the fore) are only the
reflection of the dynamic conflicts among the id, ego, and superego, which psychoanalysis
studies in the individual the same events repeated on a wider stage. (quoted in Gay, 1988,
p. 547)' Peter Gay comments: 'He could not have stated the essential unity of his thought
any more forcefully' (ibid.).
In conclusion, I suggest that Freuds simplistic and reductionist
concepts have their equivalents in the gee whiz of Lukács idea of ceasing to see through
a glass darkly under socialism. Both are in need of sophistication. I think what Klein and
Bion said about the psychotic anxieties and the paranoid-schizoid and depressive positions
which underlie Freuds bottom line help to illuminate why individuals, groups and
institutions operate as they do, especially the regrettable aspects. I think the concept
of second nature can serve as a bridge between the psychological and the political and
ideological levels of discourse. I also think that if we jettison the concept of human
nature a concept which for me is inside history and inside culture and concerns the
historicity of the unconscious unless, as I say, we hold on to some notion of human
nature, we are up Shit Creek without a paddle.
This is the text - still a draft of a talk given to the staff
seminar at the Centre for Psychoanalytic Studies, University of Sheffield, March 1995.
(7529 words)
Address for correspondence: 26 Freegrove Rd., London N7 9RQ.
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
© The Author
|
|