Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
SCIENCE, IDEOLOGY AND DONNA HARAWAY
by Robert M. Young
The concept of ideology refers to legitimation and to the intrusion of
values into putative facts. At a deeper level, it refers to how frameworks get constituted
and how criteria for acceptable conclusions get established on the basis of value systems
or world views. There are two particular concepts at work here. One is social location or
interest group; the other is power. Ideologies reflect social locations and serve
established or aspiring powers.
Recent work has made it clear to those with eyes to see that there is
no place in science, technology, medicine or other forms of expertise where you cannot
find ideology acting as a constitutive determinant. My own research has been concerned
with the biological and human sciences, with particular reference to their bearing on
conceptions of human nature. This biases the examples which I explore. In biology you can
find ideological determinants in conceptions of microprocesses, and you can go step by
step from there to to the most general features of organisms and on to social systems,
cultures, larger political systems, even the world and the universe. That is, in a way,
what we mean by a world view, for example, when we say that science is a world view and
that the scientific revolution of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries could have made
other conceptual choices than it did.
This is especially true of the way some of its leading figures dealt
with the role of purposes or final causes in scientific explanations, i.e., they banished
them from the so-called mechanical philosophy and thereby created a sub rosa theme
in the history of science which re-admitted values and purposes at levels which were
fundamentally important but not apparent on the surface of scientific writings (Young,
1989a). As a result, ideology is pervasive but often implicit (Young, 1977).
When I canvassed various examples I might have gone into to try to make
my main point about what has happened to the concept of ideology, I thought of many - too
many, too easily. One is at the cutting edge of popular expositions of natural science,
Richard Dawkins' writings on The Selfish Gene (1976) and The Blind Watchmaker (1986). These are widely regarded as among the best writings about the world view that
follows from neo-Darwinian evolutionary thinking. Another candidate for illustrating
ideology at work is Darwin's concept of natural selection, the explanatory principle which
lies at the heart of biological change, as fundamental as gravity is to physics and
affinity is to chemistry (Young, 1985a, ch. 4, 1992). Biological and social theory are
mutually constitutive in the concept of social Darwinism, which has had a renaissance in
social policy and debates about the economy of nature in these hard times (Young, 1985).
There are debates about these issues - especially among advocates of close readings of
Darwin's research materials, an activity which is too often conducted at the expense of
assessing the role of broader and deeper determinations (Bohlin, 1991, believes that he is
doing close analyses in the service of demonstrating broader and deeper determinations) -
but I would still claim that the constitutive role of ideology is well-established for all
but the most blinkered textual exegete.
In the social sciences, the ideology of biologism carries over into
functionalist explanation in psychology, sociology, anthropology, economics (Young, 1981).
It turns up again in architecture and town planning (Meller, 1990), while an even more
general version of the same way of thinking - systems theory - is to be found in all sorts
of disciplines (Boulding, 1985; Lilienfeld, 1978) and is making great headway in
psychiatry and family therapy (Treacher,1986). Functionalism uses an orgasmic model of
systems as the basic reality, draws on concepts of structure and function from physiology
and stresses adjustment or adaptation as a goal for organisms, social groups or whatever
(Gouldner, 1970; Demerath and Peterson, 1967).
There are links between functionalist thinking and theology in the past
and present. In the past, functionalism developed as a secularisation of natural theology,
whereby there was mutual harmony, directed by Divine plan. All was for the best in the
best of all possible worlds. Whatever was was as it should be and coadapted to what else
there was (Paley, 1802; Young, 1985a, ch.5; Brooke, 1977, 1979, 1991). These ideas became
secularised during the nineteenth century and were expressed in physiological analogies
applied to the social realm in the work of Herbert Spencer (Greene, 1959; Peel, 1971;
Young, 1970, ch. 5).
In the early twentieth century the admixture of respectable physiology
and confident extrapolation to society became characteristic of a whole school of writers,
led by Lawrence Henderson on the fitness of the environment and the social system (1913,
1970; Heyl, 1968) and Walter Cannon on the wisdom of the body (1932; Benison et al., 1987;
Cross and Albury, 1987). The sociological version of functionalism eventually came full
circle, and its scientistic analogies were applied to the history and sociology of science
itself, in the work of Robert K. Merton (1938, 1968). A theological version of this way of
thinking - a basis for mutual harmony - has recently been revived in the Gaia hypothesis,
according to which an eminent scientist, James Lovelock, invites us the see the universe
and all that is in it as a vast, mutually adaptive system in which all parts are in
equilibrium with all others. His notion of Gaia is thought to ensure the co-ordination
(Lovelock, 1979, 1988).
One way of thinking about the role of ideology in all these disciplines
is to see their concepts as part of an overall ideological project - the naturalization of
value systems which have a conservative tendency. I have listed the above concepts and
disciplines in the service of the claim that there have been fairly convincing ideological
critiques across a broad range of scientific ideas, and I have cited publications
referring to each of them.
The same can be said of many other individuals and their work, although
I will refrain from annotating every example. I am thinking of Isaac Newton and esoteric
knowledge (Rattansi, 1973); of Mary Shelly and Erasmus Darwin on theories of life
(Jordanova, 1986; McNeil, 1987); of Gall and Spurzheim on phrenology, and the origins of
brain research, of other key figures in the history of brain research in the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries, e.g., Magendie, Broca, Ferrier, Sherrington, Pavlov, Eccles; of
the history of the dispensing of partronage of the natural, social and medical sciences by
the Rockefeller charities (Brown 1979, 1979a; Abir-Am, 1982; Kohler, 1991); of some of
their most prolific proteges, the molecular biologists, whereby there flowed from Watson
and Crick's double helix a whole plethora of developments, leading to a belief that
genetic engineering can voluntarily reshape all of life, including humanity, eventually
virtually at will (Yoxen, 1983, 1986). Once again, there are admirable learned writings on
each and every one of these subjects.
But they are twice-told tales, and I don't want to tell them again. I
want instead to offer a single quotation and then explain why I gave up on setting forth a
version of the expositions listed above. The quotation is most interesting. I was reading
the television review in The Observer for 28 October 1990, when I saw a passage I
had also laboriously copied off a video of a natural history television programme. I had
the same experience as the reviewer, John Naughton. He was completely bowled over by one
sequence. He wrote, 'The dominant image of the week came... from Part Four of "The
Trials of Life" (BBC1), in which Whispering Dave Attenborough finally hit his stride.
The programme dealt with the grisly subject of how animals hunt and are hunted. It started
with some relatively innocuous piracy practised by seabirds on one another, then moved to
some truly terrifying footage showing a pack of killer whales catching and apparently
torturing seal cubs.
'It was the closing sequence of the film, however, which will live
forever in the minds of all who saw it. Mr. Attenborough gave a breathless running
commentary as a group of chimpanzees closed in on a hapless colobus monkey which they then
proceeded to dismember. As the hunters went for the kill, the rest of the group cheered
and shrieked in an orgy of savagery.
'Creeping up on them as they digested their meal, Attenborough turned
to the camera and said: "These bloodstained faces may well horrify us. But we might
also see in them the faces of our long-distant hunting ancestors. And if we are appalled
by the mob violence and and blood lust we might see in that, too, perhaps, the origins of
the teamwork that has, in the end, given human beings many of their greatest
triumphs." It was a sobering moment, for which he had chosen just the right words.
People said that if he lived to be a hundred, Mr. Attenborough would never cap the scene
in "Life on Earth" in which he was cuddled by a huge gorilla [and whispered so
as not to alarm the beast]. Well, they were wrong.'
I thought of spending an entire essay on unpacking that quotation,
because of its social Darwinist assumptions about 'man the hunter', because of the kind of
voyeurism involved, because of the belief that these were the origins of
co-operation in the history of the division of labour. The whole topic of science as
ideology is there in one short passage.
After I had thought through all of the above possible ways of making my
point about the concept of ideology it began to dawn on me that there is definitely
something passe about the framework of ideas and issues within which the science/ideology
dichotomy is a central problem. It also dawned on me that it is more that two decades
since I first wrote an article which treated science as ideology (Young, 1971).
Today, however, 'ideology' is one term in a dichotomy, the other member of which can no
longer sustain its role as Other in a sharp split. The forebears of the modern formulation
of ideology in the writings of Karl Mannheim set a deeply ambivalent task. The original
Ideologues of the French Revolutionary period set out 'to subject the ideas of science to
the science of ideas'. This is an intriguing phrase, setting a self-contradictory task. It
tacitly assumes that there was some stand-point for the science of ideas which would allow
one to view - presumably with an advantage more illuminating than scientific objectivity -
the ideas of putatively objective science (Rosen, 1946; Temkin, 1946; Lichtheim, 1967).
I suggest that a deeper shift was occurring, one which was
characteristic of another concept that has earlier and later connotations, just as
'ideology' has. That concept is 'positivism' (Kolakowski, 1972; Simon, 1963). We juxtapose
the nineteenth-century positivism of Auguste Comte and his British part-allies, Mill,
Spencer, Harrison, with idealist science (Annan, 1959; Eisen, 1964, 1967). Yet they were
actually in opposition to realist science in arguing that something not objective,
in the sense of being separate from human consciousness, was the true source of knowledge:
phenomena. Similarly, the original Ideologues - Cabanis, Destutt de Tracy - were arguing
that there was a discipline about something intra-human - ideas - to which the ideas of
science are accountable and which they considered to be more epistemologically basic. So
ideology, then as now, doubted that nature speaks for itself and asks where else we ground
knowledge (Thompson, 1990, ch. 1; Eagleton, 1991, ch. 3).
In its Mannheimian form, the concept of ideology juxtaposed
situationally-contingent knowledge with situationally non-contingent knowledge. Where, if
at all, that boundary could be drawn has been the subject of an ongoing debate within the
discipline Karl Mannheim founded when he wrote Ideology and Utopia (1929-31),
subtitled An Introduction the the Sociology of Knowledge. The startling and
subversive claim of his position was that knowledge has a sociology, that is, it is
socially located and therefore contingent (pp. xxiii, 36, 68-9, 185, 269). This undermined
the notion that knowledge could be like natural science was supposed to be: neutral,
objective, above the contending forces in society and culture. In the end, Mannheim
believed that the sociologist of knowledge could find an interest-free vantage point. He
adopted a position of 'relationalism' which eschewed the toughest epistemological
questions (pp. 70, 71, 77, 166, 253).
Once the question about whether or not there can be situationally
non-contingent knowledge (outside of purely deductive systems) was put, there seemed to be
no obvious stopping-place (Berger and Luckmann, 1967; Habermas, 1971; Young, 1971, 1973).
History and the human sciences were ideological. Was economics? Perhaps there was soft
economics - economic policy - which is ideological and tough economics - mathematical
economics - which was still scientific. What about psychology? Is psychoanalysis
ideological, while behaviourism is scientific? There was a time when behaviourism
presented itself as 'purely' scientific. Nowadays it would be more likely to be seen as
more nearly purely ideological. Psychoanalysis went through a very scientistic phase from
the mid-1930s until the 1960s, but is now largely proud of its humanistic strains (Rayner,
1990; Young, 1986, 1992a). I've already touched on the recent inroads into the claimed
objectivity of biology. Then there are chemistry and physics.
Successive waves of challenges to the objectivist account did not stop
at the threshold of natural science. Those who sought to separate the substance of
knowledge from its context (or, in its Popperian form, the context of justification from
the context of discovery) often lost hold of their neat distinctions. Where Robert Merton
opened the door to the sociology of scientific knowledge with his studies of
Puritanism and the Scientific Revolution (1938), others went to the heart of physics, for
example, Paul Forman (1971) , in his work of Weimar Culture and quantum physics - how the
latter adapted to the former.
My own work on evolutionary biology and ideology attempted to go to the
basic assumptions of Darwinian evolutionary theory and the functionalist sciences, while
Steve Cross, Edward Yoxen (1981) and others addressed themselves to other aspects of
biology - organismic, functionalist and molecular biological research. I shall return to
some of these questions below.
For the moment, however, I want to recall my point about the concept of
ideology feeling passe, because the science/ideology dichotomy no longer feels
dichotomous. This is not only because the concept of ideology seems less scandalous than
it did two decades ago. Indeed, the subject has received sustained attention (Harris,
1968; Larrian, 1970; Plamenatz, 1970), and there is something of a new vogue for writing
about ideology: witness recent books on the subject (albeit not concerned with natural
science) by Thompson (1984, 1990), McLellan (1986), Susser (1988), Zizek (1989), and
Eagleton (1991). Let us pause to recall how scientists and philosophers of science (left,
right and centre) squealed in the 1970s that to bring ideological analysis into science would lead (how quaint it sounds to the 1990s ear, jaded by the fragmentations and
nihilism of postmodernist discourse) to unthinkable relativism.
I have never thought of myself as a relativist, but I vividly recall
how academically eminently radical scientists sought to burn me and others at the stake
for mounting ideological critiques of biological (Young, 1977) and IQ research
(Levidow, 1978). By using the concept of ideology in our own view of science, instead of
labelling conservative and reactionary science as ideological and therefore wrong, we were
joining the polluters and abandoning the left's claim to special affinity to the truth.
'Science as ideology', like the subsequent provocative phrase, 'science as culture', was thought to betray the bedrock of realism in the theory of knowledge of
orthodox marxism. The goal of all good socialists, as one put it, should be to wash
science again and again, until the stain of ideology was removed. Left science was to be
the whitest on the block, and we polluters were claiming to find ideology everywhere. One
critic went so far as to say that one might as well have put 'shit' in place of
'scientific fact' in one of my arguments, so prurient was my position. We were violently
attacked in The Socialist Register (Rose and Rose, 1979), subjected to a whispering
campaign (including the allegation that we had obscure CIA connections), and given the
right of reply, only to have that reply rejected, so we published it ourselves (RSJ
Collective, 1981).
While orthodox scientists, historians and philosophers were defending
those ramparts, the citadel of science was being both outflanked and undermined in so many
ways that we modern-day ideologues should, by contrast, have looked tame. Indeed, the
safety of the received view of science - free of metaphysics and world views - if they but
knew it, had long-since been in peril. Eminently unradical philosophers of science had
already historicised and exposed the philosophical muddles in the most basic ideas of
science. I am thinking of the subversive metaphysical explorations of the contradictions -
even the absurdities - in the world view of modern science penned by Alfred North
Whitehead in Science and the Modern World (1925) and by Edwin Arthur Burtt in The
Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science (1932).
A related challenge was being mounted by Arthur O. Lovejoy, whose The
Great Chain of Being: A Study in the History of an Idea (1936) was the model for
research in the history of ideas and the periodical his research inspired, The Journal
of the History of Ideas (1940-). At one level this was eminently respectable, but at
another, the claim that scientific ideas have histories, whose study could
be a legitimate domain of research, relatively independent of empirical data, was anathema
to traditional inductivist and hypothetico-deductivist notions of science and of
scientific progress. Science is not just - or even largely - about facts: it is about
traditions and ways of looking at things. The history of ideas was, in its way, profoundly
ahistorical in its willingness to eschew the social context of scientific research, its
roots in the productive process and other aspects of the socio-economic and cultural base.
What was subversive about all this was twofold. It expressed the
vicissitudes, the contradictions, the compromises, illogicality and sheer cussedness of
what had been hailed by idealisers of the great scientific revolution of the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries and the subsequent progress of the advancing 'edge of objectivity'
(Gillispie, 1960). It also showed how much continuity there was between Late Renaissance
thought and the supposedly New Philosophy of the virtuosi of the Royal Society and their
Continental correspondents. Neo-Platonism and Hermeticism were rife in the thinking of
writers who were being hailed as making a decisive break with superstition. What was being
represented by historians who were sycophantic to the self-conceptions of scientists as a
radical epistemological break was nothing of the sort, or, to put the point more modestly,
was nothing like as complete as its celebrants were prone to claim. ('Epistemological
break' is an anachronistic phrase from the 1970s; what they thought had occurred was an
end to epistemology, replaced by a linear notion of positive science, which made
philosophy largely redundant, except as a handmaiden to science itself.) This was
especially true in chemistry and what was later to be called biology. William Harvey may
have been hailed as a mechanist in Descartes' Discourse on Method (1637, Part
Five), but he was a devoted Aristotelian when he was at home and never tired of saying so
(Young, 1989a). Similarly, chemistry was much, much slower to break with alchemy and to
become fully mechanistic and atomistic than reductionists would have us believe.
Eminent historians like Owsei Temkin (1946) and George Rosen (1946)
wrote about medicine and ideology in one framework of discourse. Leonora C. Rosenfeld
(1941) and Aram Vartanian (1953, 1960) showed that debates about human nature and
mechanist reductionism of animals and humans were utterly philosophically-led (Young,
1967), while Walter Pagel (1951, 1967) made similar claims for the histories of physiology
and medicine. E. J. Dijksterhuis (1950) and C. C. Gillispie (1951) showed, respectively,
that the mechanization of the world picture and the origins of scientific geology were
inseparable - at the very moment of scientific triumph - from theological preoccupations
and controversies. Not science versus theology but science in the context of
theology. The mechanical philosophy of Robert Boyle was integral with his natural
theology. Newton's mathematical principles were of a piece with his Biblical ruminations.
Charles Lyell's uniformitarian geology was carefully composed so as to be consistent with
his views on Genesis, and he never deviated from believing in the separate creation of
man, no matter how much he conceded to Darwin with respect to the evolution of other forms
of life. Similar claims about science being conceived within a framework of basically
theological assumptions were later to be convincingly made about Darwin (Moore, 1979;
Desmond and Moore, 1991), Wallace and their generation (Smith, 1972; Durant 1979).
By virtue of these and other excellent historical researches, science
came more and more to be seen as rooted in wider intellectual history, conceived in the
broadest cultural terms, although there was much less tendency to root it in contending
class forces and movements in the socio-economic base. We were made privy to sects and
interest groups, but their social and economic bases were not explored until much later.
Even so, the notion of the unencumbered scientific mind testing value-neutral facts as
they bore on purely intellectual hypotheses never had a chance at the hands of unblinkered
historians of thought.
In the 1950s and 1960s, N. R. Hanson (1958), Gerd Buchdahl (1969), A.
C. Crombie (1959), Mary Hesse (1980) and others enriched our understanding of the
philosophical bearings of scientific thought. A subsequent generation, including P.M.
Rattansi (1973), Charles Webster (1975), Quentin Skinner (1969) and John Dunn (1969),
linked those ideas to wider political and social concerns. Thereby the epistemological
goals of modern science came eventually to be rooted in genuine social history, not merely
the history of ideas.
Related work was occurring in Renaissance studies, showing how strong
were the continuities between Renaissance thought and aspects of the scientific revolution
which had been underemphasised. The leading lights in this work were D. P. Walker (1958)
and Frances Yates (1971). She was a delightful women who looked rather like Miss Marples
and was as good at unravelling mysteries. I vividly remember the raunchy way she once
said, with glee, 'Next I'm going to get Descartes,' meaning that she would knock him off
his ultra-rationalist pedestal by showing his links with the very traditions we think of
him as having eschewed.
Cartesian dualism is in no way a clear distinction between two forms of
ontologically basic kinds: extended substances and thinking substances. His conceptions of
body and of mind make up an historic compromise between the claims of the church, certain
notions of the individual soul and the requirements of his peculiar version of mechanism.
Cartesian dualism was a resolution of historical forces rather than a scientific law. The
process that led to it is more like the way a secular law gets codified than it is like a
Platonic Form, written in the fabric of Being. It is an historical compromise which, as
Whitehead stressed so eloquently, is then subjected to the fallacy of misplaced
concreteness (1925, esp. ch.3), whereby our abstract notions get seen as the most concrete
rendering of reality, rather than as ideas that should be changed if, as this one
certainly has, they serve us ill, according to particular value choices which are in
conflict with those which dictated the original conceptualisation. And yet Cartesian
dualism is one of the most basic ideas in the modern world view (Young, 1989).
I am suggesting that the union of the history of ideas with the history
of culture played a very subversive role with respect to received accounts of the history
of science and its epistemological status as a bastion of rationalism. The
science/ideology dichotomy was very hard to maintain if one read the writings of
historians and philosophers who were not cut off from the connections or articulations of
science. Twentieth-century positivism saw to it that most scientists had no inclination to
study the writings of the thinkers whom I have listed, and people like Charles Singer
(1959) provided them with the decontextualised histories of scientific discoveries which
perpetuated their isolation from the determinations that constitute ideas in science, just
as they do in other dimensions of culture.
I'll only sketch the other movements which have undermined the
science/ideology dichotomy. I have stressed various aspects of the history of ideas,
because it is easy to think of that discipline as passe, rather than realising how
subversive it was, long before anyone set out - as an avowedly political project to push
against the distinction between science and ideology. The history of ideas provided the
essential basis for joining forces with social and cultural studies.
Other ways of challenging the rationality and autonomy of science have
a more contemporary ring. I am thinking of neo-Marxist ideas of nature in which nature is
seen as a societal category with a history (Lukacs, 1971; Schmidt, 1972; Young, 1985b).
Science has always accepted the concept of natural history; it is a more radical thought
that nature has a history, that it is inside history, in so far as we can know it
(Gold and Young, 1982). Nature outside history is a noumenon - a thing in itself,
unknowable, in principle. Lukacs essayed on this, just as Gramsci wrote about the
historicity and ideological determination of notions of matter and the atom (Gramsci,
1971, pp. 446, 465-66). Other Marxists have dwelt on the mediations between socio-economic
base and intellectual superstructure (Young, 1985a, ch. 6).
Alongside politically committed ideas of this kind are nominally
apolitical approaches such as contextualism, social constructionism, the anthropology of
knowledge in the abstract and fieldwork anthropological studies in labs, studying a
particular tribe, its belief system and its ritualistic practices, moving from Robin
Horton's (1967) juxtaposition of African traditional thought with Western science to Bruno
Latour and Steve Woolgar's (1979) investigation of the culture of a particular lab.
The person whose theoretical and applied work I have found
astonishingly fruitful with respect to science, nature and other social practices is Mary
Douglas, whose Purity and Danger and essays 'In the Nature of Things' (1975, pp.
210-29) and 'Environments at Risk' (1975, pp. 230-48) never cease to prove helpful in
surprising directions. Her insight that 'Dirt is matter out of place' may be the single
most fruitful notion for the insight that how we see any part of the world and life
is inescapably inside a belief system, no matter how esoteric that bit of the world may be
- from fundamental physical particles to the universe. I find this approach worth more
than reams of what is on offer as 'the social studies of science', even though much of
that tendency also acknowledges a debt to her ideas.
The philosopher whose work has, for me, been as important as Douglas'
is Richard Rorty, whose Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1980) and essays
collected in The Consequences of Pragmatism (1982), Contingency, Irony and
Solidarity (1989) and Philosophical Papers (1991) dethrone the category of
science and place it on a par with other classificatory categories of librarianship, i.e.,
just one kind of story-telling. His assertion that 'Truth is made and not found' is as
insightful as Douglas' anthropological version of the same conventionalism. Hers is
tribal; his is epistemological. He offers a devastating critique of the high tide of the
philosophy of science when logical positivism claimed hegemony for science above other
forms of knowing (Rorty, 1982, ch. 12).
All of which brings me to Donna Haraway, to whose work I shall devote
the rest of this essay. In particular, I want to celebrate her masterpiece, Primate
Visions: Gender, Race and Nature in the World of Modern Science, which is among the
dozen best books I have ever read. Before going any further I should declare an interest.
She is generously cited in my work, as I am in hers. I have made a television film in
which her ideas loom large (Postle and Young, 1982) and have published her essays
(Haraway, 1991). But make no mistake. I do not praise her because I made the film and
published the essays; I did those things because I admire her and her work - enough to put
serious time and resources into trying to make them better known.
She is a feminist, rather loosely a neo-Marxist and (until a paper to
which I shall allude below) a postmodernist. Her topic is the use of primates as a model
for humans. This topic is at the intersection of many issues, as I shall try to indicate.
Primatology is the discipline in which we create a pedigree for the concept of humanity in
the family, society, et cetera, which we want to legitimate. It its therefore a
contested terrain. She traces the vicissitudes of this modelling through the histories of
disciplines, research careers of individuals, the rise of institutions and research
facilities, granting bodies, personal patronage, the relevant aspects of political,
geopolitical, imperialist, social and cultural history, adverts, films, television
programmes, you name it.
She even points out that one of the people who sought to teach language
to apes, Roger Fouts, was an adviser for the latest remake of 'Tarzan' - 'Greystoke: The
Legend of Tarzan, Lord of the Apes' (1984; Haraway, 1989, p. 132). Tarzan was a vastly
popular embodiment of the idea of a gentle bond between simians, other aspects of the
(Rousseauesque) 'state of nature' and humankind. African animals, our kin, had something
to teach us about a caring, thoughtful state of nature, if we approached it in the right
frame of mind. The Johnny Weissmuller film series (p.155) was part of the common
experience of my generation, and subsequent actors' portrayals have been staples of
children's television since the 1950s. The l984 Earl of Greystoke is Tarzan's latest
incarnation, based on the best version of recent studies of animal behaviour that
consultancy fees can buy.
Part of the richness of Haraway's explorations lies in the interweaving
of the academic, the popular and the commercial in illuminating how we come to think of
our place in the economy of nature. She grants that there are many subjects in the history
of biology and anthropology which could serve her purposes in writing Primate Visions.
She chose primate sciences because 'monkeys and apes, and human beings as their taxonomic
kin, exist on the boundaries of so many struggles to determine what will count as
knowledge' (p. 13). There follows the first of innumerable lists of disciplines and issues
- each concerned with border disputes (p. 14), leading to the general issue: she wants to
'set new terms for the traffic between what we have come to know historically as nature
and culture' (p. 15).
I have been a student and admirer of her work since I first encountered
it during a visit to Johns Hopkins in 1979, but nothing in my previous reading of it
prepared me for the rich, highly-textured, highly-articulated, multi-layered, genuinely
profound text that constitutes the book. Her work is heir to all the traditions I
canvassed above, and she is quite explicit about their roles in her thinking. She studied
biology as a graduate student at Yale, where the influence of G. E. Hutchinson fostered a
broad, cultured sense of biological meanings. Interdisciplinary studies at Yale provide
both a model and many of the case studies for her research as an historian. She joined the
faculty at Johns Hopkins, perhaps the leading institution in upholding the Germanic ideals
of scholarship in graduate work (Geiger, 1986) - the place where A. O. Lovejoy (1948)
founded the discipline of the history of ideas and Owsei Temkin set the highest standards
in culturally and philosophically based historical studies of medicine and biology. She
moved from there to the University of California at Santa Cruz, whose unique program in
History of Consciousness offers an even broader perspective on human self-reflectiveness
and where Norman O. Brown (1959) and Hayden White (1984) are colleagues whose historical
and historiographic perspectives are very enabling.
What strikes me as so powerful about her story is that she sets new
standards for sheer immersion in the texture of the history of ideas, institutions,
research traditions, individuals' reflections in themselves. It is exhausting to read, and
her style makes no concessions to mellifluous cadences, yet it is very, very exhilarating.
It is 'too much' in the best sense. She takes us through the minutiae of complex networks,
the mediations, the resolutions of forces that lead to scientific patronage, conception,
research, publication and dissemination. The texture is so fine, the networks so highly-articulated that any hope of maintaining a dichotomy between the substance and the
context of science or between science and ideology becomes forlorn. Context and substance
are not just interdigitated but inextricably intertwined or mutually constitutive.
This is all quite deliberate. She says at one point, 'I will periodize
primatology in order to confuse the inside/outside boundary. My argument is not that
"outside" influences have continued to determine primatology into the period of
problem-oriented, quantitative studies, but that the boundary itself gives a misleading
map of the field, leading to political commitments and beliefs about the sciences that I
wish to contest. My periodization takes pleasure in confusing boundaries' (p. 125). She
concludes, 'I do not wish to tell a causal tale, but to multiply associations and
clusters, so that the chronology of discoveries and explanatory transitions in primatology
becomes provocatively problematic. The main point is not that the following associations
are indisputable, but on the contrary, to illustrate how a chronology is necessarily a
political history' (pp. 125-6).
Most of the comments on this book that I have read have been very
uncomprehending, especially in the British press. Readers don't know what the hell to do
with it. They say, in effect, 'All this is very interesting and industrious, but the
thesis is unproven'. They don't grasp that it is the cumulative weight of textured
entanglement that makes her case. It is not an argument in the ordinary sense. It's more
like the Tar Baby: the more you make contact with it, the more you get stuck into it
('Born 'n bred in the briar patch! Born 'n bred in the briar patch!'). Some commentators
have been irritated, a few hostile to her avowed (but utterly unstrident) feminism, some
are sardonic and partronising, unable to acknowledge her consummate knowledge of her
chosen domains of study and their myriad interrelations. I say shame on those critics. Her
book reminds me of Black Athena, Martin Bernal's critique of received views on the
origins of classical Greece's putatively purely Aryan civilisation. (Indeed, she pays
tribute to his work in a recent essay - Haraway, 1990a, p. 54, n11.) Once one has been
immersed in his or her argument, one is left wondering how anyone could have thought
otherwise.
It bulges; it overflows; it spills out concepts: stress, patronage,
aspects of functionalism, how television documentaries get sponsored, how films about
cyborgs get made, how science fiction gets written, why women do or don't get jobs in
academic departments, who their partners and lovers are or were, the impact of divorces
and of sexual practices and the bearing of these experiences on what gets published and on
how primates get seen and conceptualised. There is a relentless quality about it. All very
'unscientific' but a cornucopia of scholarship and insight of the sort one gets in bull
sessions among researchers and students in a field when one is being told what really went on.
Indeed, her own research is an example of the kind she describes. It is
a nodal point or intersection in a very gratifying network of mutually influencing
scholars, especially including Steve Cross, William Albury, Constance Clark, Ludi
Jordanova, Karl Figlio and me. There is a long, long list of acknowledgements,
appropriately including seventeen of her own doctoral students. She shows how such debates
and patronage networks end up defining a discipline. Here is an example: 'Debates raged
about whether the peaceful chimpanzees and gorillas or the tight-assed baboons were the
better model for "man's" evolutionary past and so future hopes. Books were
published on the connections of primate studies to man's putative propensities toward
xenophobia and territoriality. E. O. Wilson named "the xenophobic principle" in Sociobiology (1975). Man's natural aggressiveness versus his peace-loving capacities were argued on
college campuses while the Vietnam War killed the Vietnamese and the darker-skinned and
white working-class contemporaries of the young people in the audiences' (p. 126). There
follow two pages of titles of books in this particular time frame which justified 'man the
hunter', man the aggressor,e.g., The Territorial Imperative, The Social Contract, The Hunting Hypothesis, The Naked Ape, The Human Zoo, The Imperial
Animal, On Aggression, The Inevitability of Patriarchy, on and on. After
softening us up with this saturation bombardment of otherwise risibly implausible titles
by eminently respectable people, she asks how else than by reference to the geopolitics of
the period can one account for such an outpouring of books providing a pedigree for what
the American government was up to in the late 1960s and early 1970s. The result is that
one is at first alarmed by her apparently sly elision between Wilson's sociobiological
categories and the Vietnam War, only to find it appropriate in the light of the
accumulating list of warmongering titles.
She tells a parallel story about the National Geographic specials,
which are among the most-watched programmes in television history. Five of them have been
about nonhuman primates: Miss Goodall and the Wild Chimpanzees (1965), Monkeys,
Apes and Man (1971), Search for the Great Apes (1975), Gorilla (1981),
and Among the Wild Chimpanzees (1984). To celebrate nine years of underwriting the
series, Gulf Oil launched an advertising campaign with a full-colour photo, showing 'two
wrists and hands reaching in from opposite sides of the page to meet in gentle embrace.
The hands are richly sensuous; they fill the space in which they intertwine. One is white,
young, with well-trimmed nails; the other, about the same size, is brown, hairy, showing
signs of a harder life. Both hands are open and vulnerable' (p. 133). The advert is
entitled 'Understanding is Everything', and the text says, 'In a spontaneous gesture of
trust, a chimpanzee in the wilds of Tanzania folds his leathery hand around that of Jane
Goodall - sufficient reward for Dr. Goodall's years of patience"' (ibid.).
Donna Haraway asks, 'What mediates spontaneity?... when may (white)
woman best represent (species) man? How do the race, species, gender, and science codes
work to reinvent nature in the Third World for First World audiences within post-colonial,
multinational capitalism?' (pp. 134-5). Her reply provides a characteristically bold
synthesis of science as legitimation and as available for appropriation for the purposes
of corporate image: 'Gulf took on sponsorship of the series the same year the giant
company, ranked number 8 among the Forbes 500 and traditionally one of the Seven Sisters
of international oil companies, was in the news for major slush fund scandals to U. S. and
overseas politicians, resulting in the forced resignation of the Chairman of the Board.
The 1970s were not only scandal -ridden for the oil giant; they were also economically
disastrous because of the formation of OPEC (Organization of Petroleum Exporting
Countries) and Kuwait's subsequent takeover of its oil fields. Gulf moved from the
unbeatable ally of British Petroleum, ruling the rich oil fields of a small Middle Eastern
country, from which Gulf's profits amounted to more that a $1 million per day in the
mid-1970s, to a supplicant for crude oil from an assertive Kuwaiti government. The years
of intense media focus on the system of international oil profits and politics and on the
"energy crisis" brought a new form of advertising by the energy multinationals.
Ads were full of scenes of natural integrity and environmental restoration and
preservation through the enlightened, scientifically guided practices of giant companies.
It was a good time for Gulf to associate itself with the thesis that "no thinking
person can share in the destruction of anything whose value he understands... Association
with the National Geographic Society and with the television specials is only one aspect
of Gulf's lively concern for the environment. But it is an especially proud one"' (p.
135). It is also 'association' in another sense. It is hoped that as a result of their
generous patronage of such lovely television specials we will not associate Gulf Oil with
scandal, economic imperialism and despoiling of nature but with the gentle symbiosis
between this gracious woman, her fellow-creatures and a pastoral rendering of the earth.
Science, its ideological bases, popularisation and wider ideological
and hegemonic purposes are here intertwined in a multilayered message. This example
reminds me of a Sunday magazine photograph which I once analysed. It depicted Richard
Dawkins, looking like a cross between a choirboy and a movie star, a wise, bearded,
elderly Charles Darwin, Konrad Lorenz (a founder of ethology, a Nobel Laureate and a
follower of Hitler in the 1930s), Robert Ardrey (a playwright and conservative autodidact
who also essayed on the biological inevitability of private property, hierarchy,
patriarchy, competition, etc.), E. O. Wilson (the father of recent sociobiology, offering
a much-disputed basis for many of the same things in the behaviour of ants and other
organisms in the evolutionary chain). All were pictured alongside Watson and Crick's
double helix. Biological inevitability is conveyed at many levels in a single collage. It
comes across as a unified story, legitimated by the strands of DNA twisting down the side
of the picture. I agree with Donna Haraway that people actually learn their deepest
assumptions about nature and humanity in this mixed up way. They do not pause (nor are
they invited to do so) to discriminate between the level of molecular biology, fairly
close extrapolations, mixtures of original work and wild overgeneralizations, and frankly
popular and propagandist potboilers.
She also enlightens us about how and why 'King Kong' was made, though
I'm sorry to report that there is no analysis of the macho classic 'Any Which Way but
Loose', which teams Clint Eastwood as a bare knuckle street fighter with a particularly
pugilistic chimp. Instead, we are treated to innumerable examples of the partronage of the
Rockefeller and Wenner-Gren foundations (whose financial resources came from exploitative
technologies) and the Josia Macy Foundation (money from Macy's department store). Their
vast funds have been used across a wide range of fields to support a (relatively
enlightened) version of stable, biologicstic order in animal and human social affairs.
Whole disciplines and innumerable institutions were directly established by these patrons,
notably the Yale Institute of Human Relations (pp. 71-3, 220), the Tavistock Institute of
Human Relations (Dicks, 1970), sociobiology (in an earlier incarnation), molecular biology
(Abir-Am, 1982), the integration of biological, medical and social sciences (pp. 103-4;
Brown, 1979, 1979a), world-wide organisations for the promotion of western ideas about
medicine and mental health (p. 104; Fisher, 1978).
It is not too much to say that these activities (and many more not
listed here) were part of a world-wide conspiracy to palliate class conflict and make the
world safe for international monopoly capitalism. Organismic thought became the universal
rhetoric, precluding thought in terms of contradiction, dialectic, or any other model not
compatible with market notions of competition and distributive justice. Individuals,
groups, industries, nations - all could be seen as having an essential contribution to
make to the smooth running of 'the social organism' (the title of a pioneering paper by
the evolutionary philosopher, Herbert Spencer, 1860), just as cells, organs and systems
play their parts in the overall physiology of the biological organism.
The larger goals were quite explicitly spelled out in the foundations'
internal documents. In some cases the aims were avowed in the projects, for example, the
Rockefeller-funded Trilateral Commission for world order, drawing on leaders from around
the globe, rather like a super-U. N. (the land for whose New York headquarters they also
donated) with the philanthropic oil family as hosts. This world-wide scheme is helpfully
examined in a collection edited by Holly Sklar (1980). There was also the Rockefeller
Foundation's huge programme in promoting the so-called Green Revolution for a single world
system of agriculture in the guise of ways of increasing crop yields in the Third World.
The manifest project was intensive cultivation, requiring expensive fertilisers; the
latent and final effect was the world-wide demise of the peasant farmer, whose small plot
was integrated into 'economically viable units', suitable for world crop markets.
The research projects, ongoing support of scientific meetings and
seminars and the funding of institutions and careers created a relatively stable set of
interrelating subcultures, whose participants got doctorates, jobs, publications, and
achieved the colonisation of other academic and research institutions and professional
organisations, periodicals and curricula. She shows us exactly how it's done.
For example, 'The hoped-for unity of the sciences through the new
communications theories was actively promoted by an important social mechanism immediately
after World War II: the series of ten Macy Foundation conferences on cybernetics,
beginning in 1946 with a meeting entitled "Teleological Mechanisms in Society"
and ending in 1953 with the last of the conferences entitled "Cybernetics: Circular
Causal and Feedback Mechanisms in Biological and Social Thought". These meetings had
profound consequences for cybernetic evolutionary theories of animal behavior developed in
the 1950s. The Macy Foundation sponsorship grew out of its commitment from its origin in
1930 to a holistic approach to health through the integration of biological, medical and
social sciences.... The Foundation's special technique was the conference series, in which
about fifteen scientists were invited to form an original nucleus to meet for two days at
least once a year for three to five years. Between 1940 and 1950, the Foundation sponsored
132 conferences with over 800 participating scientists. The interdisciplinary emphases of
Macy, coupled with its long-term interest in mental health, human relations and the
physiology of integrative, homeostatic processes, led the Department of State to ask the
Foundation in 1946 to conduct sessions on human relations in the Department, drawing on
its resources in clinical psychology and cultural anthropology. In 1948, Macy facilitated
the London International Congress on Mental Health, which preceded the founding of the
World Federation of Mental Health, charged with applying mental health principles to human
relations within and among nations and serving as a consultative organization to UNESCO
and the World Health Organization' (pp. 103-4).
That example of the patronage of ideas is complementary to how ideas
get wedded to personal research pedigrees and lineages. At the dawn of the era of
foundation funding, the careers of Robert Yerkes and James Rowland Angell showed how the
combination of ideas and access to patronage could build intellectual empires. Her
succinct accounts of status convey this well: 'The connection of Yerkes with human
engineering were direct and multi-levelled. He held a key place in liberal corportate
reform linked to human engineering institutionalized thorough the National Research
Council, its Division of Psychology and Anthropology, the Engineering Foundation, the
Research Information Service, the Personnel Research Foundation. Yale's Institute of
Psychology and Institute of Human Relations, the Rockefeller and Carnegie philanthropies,
and critical people like James Rowland Angell, the president of Yale who helped Yerkes
build his primate laboratory. Angell had been a prominent advocate of "functional
psychology" at the University of Chicago early in this century. He chaired the
Department of Psychology at Chicago from 1905-19, was dean of the university faculties
from 1911-19, and acting president from 1918-19. He chaired the National Research Council
from 1919-20, was president of the Carnegie Corporation from 1920-21, and president of
Yale from 1921-37. Angell was a director of the New York Life Insurance Company and the
National Broadcasting Company, served on the National Committee for Mental Hygiene, and
was a trustee of the Rockefeller Foundation from 1928-36. Angell and Yerkes planned Yale's
graduate-oriented Institute of Psychology, funded by the Laura Spellman Rockefeller
Memorial in 1924. Angell paradigmatically represented the elaborate interconnections of
university, industry, philanthropy, and science policy in the development of the material
structures and ideologies of the scientific management of society' (p. 67).
In her chapter on 'Remodeling the Human Way of Life: Sherwood Washburn
and Physical Anthropology, 1950-80', she shows how a highly contentious social Darwinist
idea - 'man the hunter' - gets embedded in doctoral theses, careers, publications and the
curricula of institutions: 'Washburn actually did little observing of living primates in
the field; but his students at Chicago and Berkeley defined a major body of primatological
practice. Prior to the time [1955-6], only two Ph.D.s (one of them Washburn's) had been
earned in anthropological departments for some branch of primatology since the publication
of Robert and Ada Yerkes's monumental tome, The Great Apes, in 1929. Between 1960
and 1979, there were to be 161 more (although only a portion of them were behavioral field
studies) - with others still in departments of psychology and biology or zoology. Of the
first nineteen of those in anthropology, fifteen were supervised by Washburn; of
forty-seven behavioral primatological doctorates in anthropology prior to 1979, twenty
were granted at Berkeley, which also awarded fourteen of the forty-two anatomical primate
Ph.D.s... The nearest competitors were Chicago, where the Washburn influence remained
after he left, and Harvard, under his former student, Irven DeVore' (p. 218).
She concludes this detailed account by spelling out the colonization of
institutions: 'Although after 1970, the number of primate students not associated with
Washburn increased, his students dominated the field in the United States in the 1960s and
have remained a force well beyond. They got important jobs during the period of the
subject's institutional consolidation (up to 1975), e.g., at the Davis, Berkeley, San
Diego, and Santa Cruz campuses of the University of California, and at Harvard, Chicago,
Stanford, Pennsylvania, Oregon, and Texas. They in turn supervised the dissertations of a
large percentage of the next wave of field workers. While the dense institutional network
associated with Washburn does not indicate a tight intellectual community, it does
indicate patterns of access to careers, recognition, and publication, as well as shared
explanatory background and assumptions about field practice, which were to be the basis of
both criticism and revolt' (p.223). She elsewhere describes Washburn - only
half-ironically - as a 'patriline', 'a very visible father in the primate order' (Haraway,
1991, p. 850.
After the account of Washburn's influence, she plunges straight into a
similar patronage network founded by David Hamburg, whose accounts of human stress built
on the foundations laid by Washburn. Hamburg extended evolutionary models of human nature
into psychiatry and went on to become Chief of Adult Psychiatry at the National Institutes
of Mental Health and president of the National Academy of Sciences Institute of Medicine
(pp. 223-6).
When she turns, in Part Three, to detailed examination of the ideas and
careers of women scientists, the tone changes radically. She sets out to explore
primatology 'as a genre of feminist theory', using as her case studies Jeanne Altmann,
Linda Marie Fedigan, Ardrienne Zihlman and Sarah Hrdy (there is a summary of their
problemmatics on p. 350), with a reprise on science fiction, especially a story by Octavia
Butler about Lilith, whose biology is complex and has been altered by intervention and
whose ruminations about her life provide the book's final sentence: 'I suppose I could
think of this as fieldwork - but how the hell do I get out of the field?' (p. 382).
Throughout the final chapters Haraway dwells on how people in less than
powerful situations, and perhaps not keen to be in them, negotiate meanings. Indeed, the
whole book is about the origins, negotiation, deployment and propagation of meanings. In
that sense, all of the things I have stressed above about power, status and careers are
secondary.
She says early on, 'Such structures enable and constrain meanings: they
do not directly produce them' (p. 111). There are other determinants of knowledge,
including animals and other objects. 'But these objects are radically mediated for us.'
The meanings in a particular tradition are not merely bad science or ideology. They are
'that which can be known in a particular time and place, called Nature'. 'Meanings are
applications; how meanings are constituted is the essence of politics.... Semiosis is
politics by other means' (ibid.).
Throughout the book - and most eloquently in the closing chapters - she
is contesting the very conceptions of Nature and the ways that they have been produced
that she has so wonderfully described in her analytic narratives of the history of
patriarchal primatology. At bottom, you see, this is a work of feminist epistemology in
practice, offered as an example of what it advocates. (Just how inclusively she thinks of
'sexual politics' is evident from a list of topics which fills page 351.) There are
innumerable startling passages in the final chapters. For example, 'Jane Altmann's career
and writing may serve as an allegory for feminist queries about gender and science, i.e.,
about relationships between positioning as a gendered social subject and the production of
knowledge and the philosophy of science' (p. 305). Again: 'But category formation at all
the powerful nodes in the apparatus of knowledge production can, perhaps, be thoroughly
destabilized. If those unsettled conditions can be produced in a discursive field, like
primatology, then fundamental change - transformation in the generative field - is just
possible. Destabilizing the positions in a discursive field and disrupting categories for
identification might be a more powerful feminist strategy than "speaking as a
woman"' (p. 310).
She has no time for feminist readings of nature which are a mirror
image of patriarchal ones: 'Feminist projects in science are distinctly not feminine
science. Rather, what might be problemmatically named feminist science in local practices
destabilizes meanings of both sex and gender and restructures the "science/gender
system" as it maps the field of meanings ordered by the axes of nature/science and
sex/gender. It is specifically the permanent tension between construction and
deconstruction, identification moves and destabilization moves, that I see, not as
uniquely femininst, but as inherent to feminism - and to science. Both feminist and
scientific discourses are critical projects built in order to destabilize and reimagine
their methods and objects of knowledge in complex power fields. Addressed to each other,
western and feminist scientific discourses warp each other's story fields and redraw
possible positions for claiming to know something about the world, including gendered
social space and sexed bodies' (p. 324).
She is determined not to suck nature up into ideology. Animals are
really out there and have a certain refractoriness to our plots. Animals are not
'"pre-discursive bodies" just waiting to validate or invalidate some discursive
practice, nor are they blank screens waiting for people's cultural projections. The
animals are active participants in the constitution of what may count as scientific
knowledge. From the point of view of the biologist's purposes, the animals resist, enable,
disrupt, engage, constrain, and display. They act and signify, and like all action and
signification, theirs yield no unique, univocal, unconstructed "facts" waiting
to be collected. The animals in behavioral biology are not transparent; they are dense.
Like words, machines, equations, institutions, generic writings, people, and landscapes,
the animals have specific kinds of solidity in the apparatus of bodily production' (pp.
310-11).
Just before the end of the book she puts her overall project very
clearly and, in doing so, gives an apologia for some of the more trying and challenging
aspects of her style: 'Throughout Primate Visions, I have read both popular and
technical discourses on monkeys and apes "out of context". My hope has been that
the always oblique and sometimes perverse focusing would facilitate revisionings of
fundamental, persistent western narratives about difference, especially racial and sexual
difference; about reproduction, especially in terms of the multiplicities of generators
and offspring; and about survival, especially about survival imagined in the boundary
conditions of both the origins and ends of history, as told within western traditions of
that complex genre. Primate Visions is replete with representations of
representations, deliberately mixing genres and contexts to play with scientific and
popular accounts in ways that the "original" authors would rarely authorize. But Primate Visions is not innocent of the intent to have effects on the authorized
primate texts in both mass cultural and scientific productions, in order to shift reading
and writing practices in this fascinating and important cultural field of meanings for
industrial and post-industrial people.
'Primate Visions does not work by prohibiting origin stories, or
biological explanations of what some would insist must be exclusively cultural matters, or
any other of the enabling devices among primate discourses' apparatuses of bodily
production. I am not interested in policing the boundaries between nature and culture -
quite the opposite, I am edified by the traffic. Indeed, I have always preferred the
prospect of pregnancy with the embryo of another species... Gender is kind, syntax,
relation, genre; gender is not the transubstantiation of biological sexual difference. The
argument in Primate Visions works by telling and retelling stories in the attempt
to shift the webs of intertextuality and to facilitate perhaps new possibilities for the
meanings of difference, reproduction, and survival for specifically located members of the
primate order on both sides of the bio-political and cultural divide between human and
animal' (p. 377).
The conclusion I draw from her work is this: If science is culture, and if culture is not to be ontologically and epistemologically privileged (in
the way the 'science of ideas' was privileged by the French Ideologues), then the concept
of ideology no longer has a privileged or scandalous conceptual space to occupy. It has no
Other with which to be in contrast; it is passe, because positivist and objectivist
notions of science, no matter how qualified and rehabilitated, are utterly discredited.
There is no way to 'get out of the field'. There are only contested terrains, and it
behooves us to get off the terrain of 'we caught you' critiques and to construct our own
accounts, our own artefacts, our own natures and Nature.
After all this heartfelt and fulsome praise, I want to add two notes of
severe regret on behalf of inner and outer reality. In the past she has been hostile to
psychoanalysis. In a footnote to Primate Visions she seems to have moved nearer:
'Lurking just underneath the discussion of difference throughout this book has been
feminism's relations to psychoanalytic theory, especially Lacanian versions. It is too
late to force this potent monster up from the depths, breaking the surface tensions of my
discussions of difference, to join the monkeys and apes in the upper stories of the
primate text. Let the beast continue to inhabit the fluid regions that threaten to flood
the primal scenes where "almost minds" communicate' (p. 431 n6). I find this coy
and evasive and believe strongly that the psychoanalytic dimension - including and
especially the kinds of critiques of its appropriation by anthropologists and
functionalist social scientists which she would be likely to mount - is essential to the
overall critical and reconstructive project to which her work is a central contribution.
I also think that when, in work not reviewed in this essay, she turns
to the positive project of reconstituting Nature and human nature (which she calls
'artifactualism'), a healthy dose of (especially Kleinian) psychoanalysis would add a
cautionary note. There is more than an hint of voluntarism and idealism in her positive
programme, and I am also left with a nagging sense that we may never emerge from the realm
of discourse into more traditional politically and economically contested terrains, with
their own stubborn refractorinesses. Remaining on the terrain of discourse tempts one to a
sense that perhaps our good will and our serious and sustained studies might win the field
of contested meanings. For all my admiration of her work, I sometimes feel seduced away
from both the outer and the inner worlds and into a playful space, where it would not be
right to remain for too long, lest I forget the long-term goals of changing ourselves and
the world.
The inner world (not solely the immunological one which she does address with characteristic subtlety) has its own stubborn but not, one hopes, utterly
unmodifiable 'second nature'. The unconscious aspects of human nature, in its individual
and collective manifestations, are not transparent any more than primates or modes of
production are: they are dense, though not impenetrable, just as she rightly insists that
the subtler ways of other primates are. The concept of second nature allows us to say that
ways of being, thinking, behaving and organising economies are deeply sedimented and
experienced as 'natural' - as biological or 'first nature'. Nevertheless and however
refractory they are, they are also potentially modifiable as a result of appropriate,
patient struggle to gain insight and to change.
One last point. After I had drafted all of the above and decided to
offer her work as central to my case for setting aside the science/ideology dichotomy, a
new paper by her turned up in the post. It is entitled, with characteristic terminological
cussedness, 'The Promises of Monsters: A Regenerative Politics for Inappropriate/d
Others'. In a footnote in which she ruminates the categories of modernism, postmodernism
and (what Bruno Latour wants to call) 'amodernism', she concludes that science
studies can no longer remain immune to cultural studies. Indeed, the concluding sentence
of her recent book of essays says, 'Science is culture' (Haraway, 1991, p. 230). In
the new essay, she argues the case: 'Further, the addition of science studies to cultural
studies does not leave the notions of culture, society, and politics untouched, far from
it. In particular, we cannot make a critique of science and its constructions of nature
based an ongoing belief in culture or society. In the form of social constructionism, that
belief has grounded the major strategy of left, feminist, and anti-racist science
radicals. To remain with that strategy, however, is to remain bedazzled by the ideology of
enlightenment. It will not do to approach science as social or cultural construction, as
if culture and society were transcendent categories, any more than nature or the object
is. Outside the premises of enlightenment - i.e., of the modern - the binary pairs of
culture and nature, science and society, the technical and the social all lose their
constitutive, oppositional quality. Neither can explain the other' (Haraway, 1990, n7).
I would, of course, add that the same is true of 'science and
ideology'. Where we go from here is not to a particularly epistemologically safe project.
I suppose it's rather prosaic: the task of telling the best stories we can. Her own
ruminations also point to telling stories: 'When the pieties of belief in the modern are
dismissed, both members of the binary pairs collapse into each other as into a black hole.
But what happens to them in the black hole is, by definition, not visible from the shared
terrain of modernity, modernism or postmodernism. It will take a superluminary SF journey
into elsewhere to find the new interesting vantage points' (ibid.).
At a recent event at London's determinedly avant garde Institute
of Contemporary Arts I overheard a young couple discussing the formation of a Donna
Haraway reading group. I remember well how, in the 1970s, my contemporaries and I felt
that we had to be in a reading group to sustain the morale and will power to read Marx's Grundrisse.
It is a sign of the times that Primate Visions is the equivalently post- or
a-modern challenge to the imagination and to solidarity in cultural politics.
This article appeared in Science as Culture (no. 15)
3:165-207,1992
REFERENCES
Place of publication is London unless otherwise specified.
Abir-Am, P. (1982) 'The discourse of physical
power and biological knowledge in the 1930s: a reappraisal of the Rockefeller Foundation's
"policy" in molecular biology', Social Stud. Sci. 12:341-82.
Annan, N. (1959) The Curious Strength of Positivism in English
Political Thought. Oxford.
Benison, S., Barger, A. C. and Wolfe, E. L. (1987) Walter B. Cannon:
The Life and Times of a Young Scientist. Harvard University Press.
Berger, P and Luckmann, P. (1967) The Social Construction of Reality.
Garden City, N. Y.: Doubleday Anchor.
Bohlin, I. (1991) 'Robert M. Young and Darwin historiography', Soc.
Stud. Sci. 21:597-648.
Boulding, K. E. (1985) The World as a Total System. Sage.
Brooke, J. H. (1977) 'Natural theology and the plurality of worlds:
observations on the Brewster-Whewell debate', Annals of Sci. 34:221-86.
______(1979) 'The natural theology of the geologists: some theological
strata', in L. J. Jordanova and R. S. Porter, eds., Images of the Earth: Essays in the
History of the Environmental Sciences. Hassocks: Harvester, pp. 39-64.
______(1991) Science and Religion: Some Historical Perspectives.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brown, E. R. (1979) 'He who pays the piper: foundations, the medical
profession and medical education', in S. Reverby and D. Rosner, eds., Health Care in
America: Essays in Social History. Philadelphia: Temple Univ. Press, pp. 132-54.
______(1979a) Rockefeller Medicine Men: Medicine and Capitalism in
America. University of California Press.
Brown, N. O. (1959) Life Against Death: The Psychoanalytic Meaning
of History. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.
Buchdahl, G. (1969) Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science: The
Classical Origins Descartes to Kant. Blackwell.
Burtt, E. A. (1932) The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical
Science (1924), 2nd ed. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Cannon, W. (1932) The Wisdom of the Body. N. Y.: Norton.
Crombie, A. C. (1959) Augustine to Galileo (1952), 2nd ed., 2
vols. Heinemann.
Cross, S. J. and Albury, W. R. (1987) 'Walter B. Cannon, L. J.
Henderson, and the organic analogy', Osiris 2nd ser. 3:165-92.
Darnovsky, M. (1991) 'Overhauling the meaning machines: an interview
with Donna Haraway', Socialist Rev. 21, no. 2:65-84.
Dawkins, R. (1976) The Selfish Gene. Oxford University Press.
______(1986) The Blind Watchmaker. Longman.
Demerath, N. J. III and Peterson, R. A. (1967) System, Change, and
Conflict: A Reader on Contemporary Sociological Theory and the Debate Over Functionalism.
Collier-Macmillan.
Descartes, R. (1637) Discourse on Method and the Meditations.Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1868.
Desmond, A. and Moore, J. (1991) Darwin. Michael Joseph.
Dicks, H. V. (1970) Fifty Years of the Tavistock Clinic.
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Dijksterhuis, E. J. (1950) The Mechanization of the World Picture.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961.
Douglas, M. (1966) Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of
Pollution and Taboo. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970.
______(1975) Implicit Meanings: Essays in Anthropology.
Routledge.
Dunn, J. M. (1968) 'The identity of the history of ideas', Philosophy 43:85-104.
Durant, J. (1979) 'Scientific naturalism and social reform in the
thought of Alfred Russel Wallace', Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 12:31-58.
Eagleton, T. (1991) Ideology: An Introduction. Verso.
Eisen, S. (1964) 'Huxley and the Positivists', Victor. Stud.
7:337-58.
______(1967) 'Frederick Harrison and the religion of humanity', So.
Atlantic Quart. 66:574-90.
Figlio, K. (1979) 'Sinister medicine? A critique of left approaches to
medicine', Rad. Sci. J. 9:14-68.
Fisher, D. (1978) 'The Rockefeller Foundation and the development of
scientific medicine in Great Britain', Minerva 16:20-41.
Forman, P. (1971) 'Weimar culture, causality, and quantum theory,
1918-1927: adaptation by German physicists and mathematicians to a hostile intellectual
environment', Histor. Stud. Physical Sci. 3:1-115.
Geiger, R. L. (1986) To Advance Knowledge: The Growth of American
Research Universities, 1900-1940. N. Y.: Oxford University Press.
Gillespie, R. (1991) Manufacturing Knowledge: A History of the
Hawthorne Experiments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gillispie, C. C. (1951) Genesis and Geology: The Impact of
Scientific Discoveries upon Religious Beliefs in the Decades before Darwin. N. Y.:
Harper Torchbooks, 1959.
______(1960 The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of
Scientific Ideas. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gold, M. and Young, R. M. (1982) 'A History of Nature', Crucible:
Science in Society. Channel Four Television.
Gouldner, A. W. (1970) The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology.
Heinemann.
Gramsci, A. (1971) Selections from the Prison Notebooks.
Lawrence and Wishart.
Greene, J. C. (1959) 'Biology and social theory in the nineteenth
century: Auguste Comte and Herbert Spencer', reprinted in J. C. Greene, Science,
Ideology and World View: Essays in the History of Evolutionary Ideas. University of
California Press, pp. 60-94.
Habermas, J. (1971) 'Technology and science as ideology', in J.
Habermas, Toward a Rational Society. Heinemann, ch. 6.
Hanson, N. R. (1958) Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the
Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haraway, D. J. (1989) Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in
the World of Modern Science. Routledge.
______(1991) Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature.
Free Association Books.
______(in press) 'The promises of monsters: a regenerative politics for
inappropriate/d others', in P. Treichler. C. Nelson and L. Grossberg, eds., Cultural
Studies Now and in the Future.
______(in press a) 'Otherworldly conversations; terran topics; local
terms', Sci. as Culture.
Harris, N. (1968) Beliefs in Society: The Problem of Ideology.
Watts; reprinted Harmondsworth: Pelican, 1971.
Henderson, L. J. (1913) The Fitness of the Environment:An Inquiry
into the Biological Significance of the Properties of Matter. N. Y.: Macmillan;
reprinted Boston: Beacon, 1958.
______(1970) L. J. Henderson on the Social System: Selected Writings.
University of Chicago Press.
Hesse, M. B. (1980) Revolutions and Reconstructions in the
Philosophy of Science. Brighton: Harvester.
Heyl, B. (1968) 'The Harvard "Pareto Circle"', J. Hist.
Behav. Sci. 4:316-34.
Horton, R. (1967) 'African traditional thought and western science', Africa 37:50-71, 155-87.
Kohler, R. E. (1991) Partners in Science: Foundations and Natural
Scientists 1900-1945. University of Chicago Press.
Kolakowski, L. (1966) Positivist Philosophy from Hume to the Vienna
Circle, revised ed., Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1972.
Larrian, J. (1979) The Concept of Ideology. Hutchinson.
Lichtheim, G. (1967) The Concept of Ideology and Other Essays.
N. Y.: Vintage Books.
Lilenfeld. R. (1978) The Rise of Systems Theory: An Ideological
Analysis. N. Y.: Wiley-Interscience.
Lovejoy, A. O. (1936) The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the
History of an Idea. Cambridge, MA; Harvard University Press; reprinted N. Y.: Harper
Torchbooks, 1960.
______(1948) Essays in the History of Ideas. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press; reprinted N. Y.: Capricorn Books, 1960.
Levidow, L. (1978) 'A marxist critique of the IQ debate', Rad. Sci.
J. 6/7:13-72.
Lovelock, J. E. (1979) Gaia: A New Look at Life on Earth.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
______(1988) The Ages of Gaia: A Biography of Our Living Earth.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lukacs, G. (1923) History and Class Consciousness, new ed.,
1967, with preface. Merlin, 1971.
Latour, B. and Woolgar, S. (1979) Laboratory Life: The Social
Construction of Scientific Facts. Sage.
Mannheim, K. (1929-31) Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the
Sociology of Knowledge. Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1960.
McLellan, D. (1986) Ideology. Milton Keynes: Open University
Press.
McNeil, M. (1987) Under the Banner of Science: Erasmus Darwin and
His Age. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Meller, H. (1990) Patrick Geddes: Social Evolutionist and City
Planner. Routledge.
Merton, R. K. (1938) Science, Technology and Society in
Seventeenth-Century England; reprinted N. Y.: Harper and Row, 1970.
______(1949) Social Theory and Social Structure, 3rd ed.
Collier-Macmillan, 1968.
Moore, J. R. (1979) The Post-Darwinian Controversies: A Study of the
Protestant Struggle to Come to Terms with Darwin in Great Britain and America 1870-1900.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pagel, W. (1951) 'William Harvey and the purpose of the circulation', Isis 42:22-38.
______(1967) William Harvey's Biological Ideas: Selected Aspects and
Historical Background. N. Y.: S. Karger.
Paley, W. (1802) Natural Theology: or, Evidences of the Existence
and Attributes of the Deity. Collected from the Appearances of Nature, new ed. Baynes,
1816.
Peel. J. D. Y. (1971) Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a
Sociologist. Heinemann.
Plamenatz, J. (1970) Ideology. Macmillan.
Popper, K. R. (1934) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. N. Y.:
Basic Books.
Postle, D. and Young, R. M. (1982) 'Behaving Ourselves', Crucible:
Science in Society. Channel Four Television.
RSJ Collective (1981) 'Science, technology, medicine and the socialist
movement', Rad. Sci. J. 11:3-72.
Rattansi, P. M. (1973) 'Some evaluations of reason in sixteenth- and
seventeenth-century natural philosophy', in M. Teich and R. M. Young, eds., Changing
Perspectives in the History of Science: Essays in Honour of Joseph Needham. Heinemann,
pp. 148-66.
Rayner, E. (1991) The Independent Mind in British Psychoanalysis.
Free Association Books.
Rorty, R. (1980) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell.
______(1982) Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-1980).
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
______(1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
______(1991) Objectivism, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical
Papers Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
______(1991) Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers
Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rose, H. and Rose, S. (1979) 'Radical science and its enemies', Socialist
Register, pp. 317-35.
Rosen, G. (1946) 'The philosophy of ideology and the emergence of
modern medicine in France', Bull. Hist. Med. 20:328-39.
Rosenfeld, L. C. (1941) From Beast Machine to Man-Machine: Animal
Soul in French Letters from Descartes to La Mettrie. N. Y.: Oxford University Press.
Schmidt, A. (1962) The Concept of Nature in Marx. New Left
Books, 1972.
Sklar, H. (1980) Trilateralism:The Trilateral Commission and Elite
Planning for World Management. Boston: South End Press.
Simon, W. M. (1963) European Positivism in the Nineteenth Century.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Singer, C. (1959) A History of Biology, 3rd. ed. N. Y.:
Abelard-Schuman.
Skinner, Q. R. D. (1969) 'Meaning and understanding in the history of
ideas', Hist. and Theory 8:3-53.
Smith, R. (1972) 'Alfred Russel Wallace: philosophy of nature and man', Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 6:177-99.
Spencer, H. (1860) 'The social organism', reprinted in The Man
versus the State with Four Essays on Politics and Society. Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1969, pp. 195-233.
Susser, B. (1988) The Grammar of Modern Ideology. Routledge.
Temkin, O. (1946) 'The philosophical background of Magendie's
physiology', Bull. Hist. Med. 20:10-35.
Thompson, J. B. (1984) Studies in the Theory of Ideology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
______(1990) Ideology and Modern Culture. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Trahair, R. C. S. (1984) The Humanist Temper: The Life and Work of
Elton Mayo. Transaction Books.
Treacher, A. (1986) 'Invisible patients, invisible families - a
critical exploration of some technocratic trends in family therapy', J. Fam. Ther.
8:267-306.
Vartanian, A. (1953) Diderot and Descartes: A Study of Scientific
Naturalism in the Enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
______(1960) La Mettrie's L'Homme Machine: A Study in the Origins of
an Idea. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Walker, D. P. (1958) Spiritual and Demonic Magic from Ficino to
Campanella; reprinted Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975.
Webster, C. (1975) The Great Instauration: Science, Medicine and
Reform 1626-1660. Duckworth.
White, H. (1984) 'The question of narrative in contemporary historical
theory', Hist. and Theory 23:1-33.
Whitehead, A. N. (1925) Science and the Modern World. Free
Association Books, 1985.
Wilson, E. O. (1975) Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Yates,, F. A. (1971) Giordano Bruno and the
Hermetic Tradition. Routledge. Young, R. M. (1967) 'Animal Soul', in P. Edwards, ed., The Encyclopediaof Philosophy. N. Y.: Macmillan, vol. 1, pp. 122-27.
______(1970) Mind, Brain and Adaptation in the Nineteenth Century:
Cerebral Localization and Its Biological Context from Gall to Ferrier. Oxford:
Clarendon Press; reprinted N. Y.: Oxford University Press, 1990.
______(1971) 'Evolutionary biology and Ideology: then and now', Sci.
Stud. 1:177-206.
______(1973) 'The human limits of nature', in J. Benthall, ed., The
Limits of Human Nature. Allen Lane, pp. 235-74.
______(1977) 'Science is social relations', Rad. Sci. J.
5:65-129.
______(1981) 'The naturalization of value systems in the human
sciences', in Problems in the Biological and Human Sciences. Milton Keynes: Open
University Press, pp. 63-110.
______(1985) 'Darwinism is social', in D. Kohn, ed., The
Darwinian Heritage. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 609-38.
_____(1985a) Darwin's Metaphor: Nature's Place in Victorian Culture.
Cambridge University Press.
_____(1985b) 'Is nature a labour process?', in L. Levidow and R. M.
Young, eds., Science, Technology and the Labour Process: Marxist Studies, vol. 2.
Free Association Books, pp. 206-32.
______(1986) 'Freud: scientist and/or humanist', Free Assns.
6:7-35.
______(1988) 'Biography: the basic discipline for a human science', Free
Assns. 11:108-30.
______(1989) 'The mind-body problem', in R. C. Olby et al., eds. Companion
to the History of Modern Science. Routledge, pp. 702-11.
______(1989a) 'Persons, organisms and... primary qualities', in J. R.
Moore, ed., History, Humanity and Evolution: Essays for John C. Greene. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 375-402.
______(1989b) 'Post-modernism and the subject: pessimism of the will', Free
Assns. 16:81-96.
______(1992) 'Darwin's metaphor and the philosophy of science', Sci.
as Culture, in press.
______(1992a) Mental Space. Free Association Books, in press.
Yoxen, E. J. (1981) 'Life as a productive force: Capitalising upon
research in molecular biology', in L. Levidow and R. M. Young, eds., Science,
Technology and the Labour Process: Marxist Studies, vol. 1, pp. 66-122.
______(1983) The Gene Business: Who Shall Control Biotechnology? Pan Books; reissued Free Association Books, 1986.
______(1986) Unnatural Selection: Coming to Terms with the New
Genetics. Heinemann.
Zizek, S. (1989) The Sublime Object of Ideology. Verso.
Address for correspondence: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ.
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
© The Author
|
|