Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
THE UBIQUITY OF PSYCHOTIC ANXIETIES
by Robert M. Young
When I began composing this paper I could not decide whether the point
I am trying to make is banal and obvious or really rather important. Perhaps its
both at once. As Wilhelm Reich said, it is essential to subject things to the searching
scrutiny of naive questions.
My point is that the Freudian definition of the unconscious and, a
fortiori, the Kleinian one, says in a quite flat-footed way that fundamentally
irrational processes are going on all the time in our inner worlds. The difference between
the Freudian and the Kleinian versions of this point is that on the Kleinian account these
processes are in a complex interplay with other, less irrational ones, from moment to
moment, and the way Kleinians write about them and make interpretations of them makes them
seem more extreme - in a word, crazier, playing a larger and more manifest part in
everyday behaviour. Whatever one may want to say about the difference of tone or degree
between Freudian and Kleinian accounts, its not startling news that crazy things go
on in the unconscious. It is worth recalling that on both accounts, by far the larger part
of what goes on in the mind is unconscious, where the rules of Aristotelian logic do not
apply.
Why, then, might my point be rather important? There are a number of
interrelated reasons. First, one might ask why this conference seemed necessary, that is,
why are psychotherapists and psychoanalysts on the whole wary of and out of touch with
psychosis and why are most psychiatrists equally (perhaps more) out of touch with
psychodynamic formulations of psychotic phenomena? There seems to be a barrier or, at
least, imperfect communication. Therapists and analysts do not commonly treat psychotics.
All but a tiny minority of psychiatrists would not dream of using the talking
cure as the treatment of choice with such patients. Indeed, Im told that in
America an analyst was recently successfully sued for doing so and that the ensuing debate
is ongoing in the American psychiatric journals. There are notable exceptions, to some of
whom Ill return: Wilfred Bion, Hanna Segal, Herbert Rosenfeld Donald Meltzer, Murray
Jackson, Michael Conran in this country and Harold Searles in America. But it is not
common and is usually seen as research with limited therapeutic goals. Searles work with a
number of patients over decades is the object of bemusement and ridicule in some circles,
though Im bound to say that the more I do psychotherapy with psychotics, the more I
admire him and envy his ability to find and convey the meaning and sense in what
psychotics say.
Then there is the burgeoning literature on so-called borderline
states and pathological organisations, categories which are problematic
and whose legitimacy are the subject of intense debate in some quarters at the same time
that the literature about them is rich and fascinating for what it suggests about the
inner world and the refractory structures in individuals (Searles, 1986; Rosenfeld, 1987;
Spillius. 1988, vol. 1, part 4; Silver and Rosenbleuth, 1992; Rey, forthcoming).
This leads on to the question of nosology, a topic which has a narrow
and a wide focus. The narrow focus is the gulf that exists between psychoanalysts and
psychotherapists on the one hand and psychiatrists on the other with respect to the
relevance of psychiatric nosology. This gulf may be described quite simply.
Psychotherapists dont think much in terms of disease entities or syndromes. Of
course they do in a loose way, but their overwhelming emphasis is on unconscious dynamics.
Orthodox psychiatrists tend to think in terms of categories, while therapists tend to
think in terms of levels and movements back and forth between positions or emotional
states.
Not only do we find a big difference of emphasis with respect to the
extent to which classifications of the sort found in DSM - III-R are used, I also
find that the distinctions between normal and neurotic and psychotic arent much
used, at least in Kleinian circles. I hasten to add that the distinctions are around and
relevant and that I carry around in my head terms which I attach to my patients in some
reflective moments and in supervision, for example, paranoid,
borderline, pathological organisation, depressed,
schizoid, hysterical, and so on. But these are rarely in my mind
during sessions.
The wider focus of the topic of nosology is the problematic role of
classifications in medicine and science. Classifications are put forward as facts of
nature, analogous, in the first instance, to disease categories in medicine, which, in
turn, claim some affinity to natural classifications of species in biology and particles,
elements and compounds in physics. This is a central feature of the scientific enterprise:
the search for a definitive specification of natural kinds. The trouble with the attempt
to find a natural classification in psychopathology is that the project of achieving such
classifications opens up a very large can of worms about human nature, nature and the
theory of knowledge - epistemology.
By this I mean that the attempt to classify mental phenomena has no
language of its own. It is a consequence of Cartesian mind-body dualism that bodies are
described in terms of primary qualities - extension and figure, treated geometrically and
mathematically, while mind is negatively defined as that which does not pertain to body
(Young, 1989; in press, ch. 1). The languages employed by scientists, which includes
medics and therapists (regarded as rather pale shadows of proper scientists),
are generated by analogy from more scientifically respectable disciplines. For
example, the association of ideas was itself dreamed up as an analogy to the
ways physical particles were thought to interact in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries - a sort of billiard-ball impact physics (Young, 1970, pp. 94-100). The very
notion of psychopathology was an attempt, begun in the mid-nineteenth century, to
found the theory of mental disturbance on the disease model - hence mental
disease - and a description of the features of such disorders was made analogous to
the exciting new findings of the study of the pathology of organs and cells - hence the
use of terms such as syndrome and morbid anatomy. The term
psychopathology entered English in 1847 as a transliteration of the title of a
book by Baron von Feuchstersleben, and there were titles around mid-century such as Elements
of the Pathology of the Human Mind (Mayo, 1838), Chapters on Mental Physiology (Holland, 1852) and Henry Maudsleys Physiology and Pathology of Mind (1867) . Books
with psychopatology in their titles were still being written in the 1980s (Berrios, 1991),
and I currently lecture on the subject in several psychotherapy trainings
The history of ideas in psychopathology is the history of the extended
use of a somatic analogy which, it was thought by Freuds teachers, would soon be
securely founded on the actual findings of cerebral pathology (Amacher, 1965). Indeed, it
is worth recalling that it was in this field that he chose to work (Bernfield, 1944, 1949,
1951; Kris, 1950). It was the subject of his first book, On Aphasia (1891; Stengel,
1954; Riese, 1958). He turned to treating neurotics because he couldnt afford to
continue working as an academic researcher (Young, 1986; Gay, 1988, pp. 22-37). Throughout
his writings we find analogies and metaphors drawn from physics, anatomy, physiology and
pathology. Anatomical and reflex models were pervasive in The Interpretation of Dreams, and at the end of his life he was still thinking this way in the New
Introductory Lectures, one of which was entltled The Dissection of the Psychical
Personality (Freud, 1933, ch. 31)
Not only is it the case that psychopathological nosology is based on an
extended and increasingly dubious analogy to the natural and biomedical sciences, but
these efforts at placing the vicissitudes of human suffering on the bedrock of putatively
natural classifications turn out, according to recent research in the history, philosophy
and social studies of science, to be eminently historical. Ill repeat that ,
since it is crucial to what I am trying to say. Disease categories in psychiatry are
eminently historical and change over time as a result of wider forces in the history of
ideas and the history of culture. If that wasnt obvious before, systematic
nosological work was attempted, it should be transparent from the fact that the official Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual has gone through four revisions in its short history since it
first appeared in 1952 (APA, 1987, pp. xviii-xix). You could say that they are moving
progressively toward a refined truth, but the changes are not of that kind. It is more
like the history of encyclopaedias, which may have been conceived in the belief that
knowledge accumulates in a linear way. In fact, however, its categories, frameworks and
terms of reference have also changed in successive editions. I have the eighth edition of The
Encyclopedia Britannica, dated 1860. It includes a long article entitled
Deluge, which goes into lots of complicated matters about the Biblical flood.
The next edition, which appeared less than two decades later, has no such entry but does
have a new one called Evolution. There are related changes throughout the
edition, including the disappearance of a preliminary volume of essays called
Dissertations and Discussions, which sought to encompass all of knowledge.
Between those two editions the whole interllectual landscape had been recast as a result
of the publication of Darwins Origin of Species.
You might think I am leading up to a sharp distinction between human
knowledge and natural knowledge, but I submit that the example I have just given points
the other way and shows that the historicity of categories also applies to natural
knowledge. As I have tried to show in my films and other writings, ideas of nature have a
history (Young, 1973, 1985, ch. 6; Young and Postle, 1981; Young and Gold, 1982). One
inspiration for this approach is Georg Lukács, who argued, the idea of nature in any
period is the theoretical reflection and projection of the social milieu of
the times (Lukács, 1923, p. 38). Nature is a societal category. That is to
say, whatever is held to be natural at any given stage of social development, however this
nature is related to man and whatever form his involvement with it takes, i.e.
natures form, its content, its range and its objectivity are all socially
conditioned (ibid., p. 234). What is true of nature in general also applies
to the framing of natural kinds or classifications. So the attempt to found the
understanding of human distress on an analogy to somatic pathology, which is, in turn,
reducible to physiology, biochemistry, chemistry and physics, fails to take note that the
bedrock is itself changing as a function of broader movements in the culture. This is less
obvious in the physico-chemical sciences, but it is still the case. It is obviously so in
medicine, as a brilliant and pioneering series of essays by Karl Figlio has shown with
respect to the rise and fall of certain eminently somatic diseases - chlorosis and
miners nystagmus (Figlio, 1978, 1979, 1985). He has moved on, following Harold
Searles profound book on The Nonnhuman Environment, to explore we experience and
deploy the external world in our unconscious projective processes (1990).
Note carefully that I am not saying that there was no such thing as
chlorosis or miners nystagmus. The medical textbooks and hospital records prove that
there was and that their natures changed over time. These syndromes were discovered and
treated as natural kinds. One had as its pathognomonic symptom a kind of anaemia, the
other a disorder of the eyes. They waxed and waned in the medical literature as the
constellation of social forces which evoked them changed over decades. The same is true of
the nosological categories in DSM. An example is ego-syntonic
homosexuality. It has simply ceased to be a disease, though if you have the non-ego
syntonic variety you are still - according to the current classification - sick. I learned
this system of ideas - what anthropologists call a belief system - as a psychiatric aide
in Arizona (where promiscuity and priapism were still considered grave illnesses) and got
to be a dab hand at making diagnoses, just as I later learned to do assessment interviews
in a psychotherapy department and to make dynamic formulations which met the prevailing
standards. Even diagnostic categories which have been challenged can elicit high degrees
of reliability which meet scientific standards of intersubjective validation, as Alex
Tarnopolsky (1992) has shown with respect to borderline disorders.
You can be forgiven for thinking that I am spending a long time in the
foothills of my argument. My reply would be that I am at the summit of it in a number of
respects. Even so, if I may vary the metaphor, I am poised for re-entry to the part of my
text which concentrates on the modifier psychotic. My vehicle for re-entry is
Peter Barhams breathtakingly wise book on Schizophrenia and Human Value, in
which he argues that we must move off the nosological relegation of schizophrenics to
demented chronicity and learn to think of them as living lives, of which it can be said,
thereby hangs a tale, that is, a narrative which has meaning and value and
merit our attentiveness, whether or not the cause of schizophrenia turns out to be largely
biochemical. (I have never understood why people think that biological causation diminshes
the meaningfulness of what psychotic people say and do.) Barham has gone on to say that
because they tell a recognisably meaningful story - mented, as it were, rather
than de-mented - the lives of these people merit provision appropriate to
fellow human beings who, like people in wheelchairs, are in need of certain kinds of
spaces which facilitate their doing whatever they can, rather than the stark alternatives
of hospitals or cardboard cities (Barham, 1992).
Barham argues his thesis on general humanitarian grounds but also draws
on writings by Alisdair MacIntyre and Richard Rorty which are critical of the hegemonic
claims of scientific rationality and seek to promote narrative, story-telling, evaluative
and humanocentric ways of speaking about things, especially human things, by which I mean not treating the relations between people as if they were relations between things. This goes
against the grain of the history of scientism, whereby scientific rationality and
materialist explanations were offered as the models for all of knowledge - a movement
which peaked in the 1950s and has recently been under attack in general philosophy and in
the philosophy of both the natural and the so-called human sciences (Rorty, 1982, ch. 12).
It is at this point that two strands of my argument meet. First, there
is a widespread and growing critique of reductionist explanations based on the
increasingly historicised bedrock of natural science. Second, and closely allied, there is
a movement of critique of rationalist views of human nature in psychology and social
studies - moving away from enlightenment and positivist models and toward a more tolerant
and inclusive view of the role of primitive processes in our lives. These strands meet at
the point where human phenomena are increasingly described in terms which are recognisably
human, rather than - as was the case at the high tide of scientism - in terms which reduce
the human to the parameters of scientific rationality and human nature to a split between
the rational and the Other, whereof one cannot speak.
I hope I have said enough to make plausible the project of addressing
my title and pointing out the ubiquity of psychotic anxieties. I have set the stage in the
way I have in order to make clear that what I shall now say about Freudian and Kleinian
ideas is not just a re-hash but a repositioning of these ideas in the context of a
broader movement in philosophy and the study of humanity, society and the world. It puts
primitive processes in the context of a broader cultural movement which is challenging the
privileging of forms of discourse drawn directly or by analogy from natural science.
That movement is not entirely new. It has a distinguished history. What
is new is that the claim that primitive and irrational processes are central to human
nature, and it should not provoke a scandalised response. There is a good analogy to
related developments in epistemology. The word ideology and the adjective
ideological have had pejorative meanings since Napoleon trashed the movement by that name
in the early nineteenth century (Young, 1971, 1973, 1977). But ideology only held its
terrors in virtue of being in paired opposition to science, rather as
fact and value are paired. But if the strong claims hitherto made
for science are seen to melt away, then ideology - the colouring of accounts of things by
interest groups - becomes the norm, not the deviation (Haraway, 1989, 1990; Young, 1992a).
If the science/ideology and the fact/value distinctions are undermined, because science is
ideological and facts are value-laden, then the closely related split between psychotic
and non-psychotic (or normal) should also be reconceptualised.
The distinguished history to which I refer is easily recalled. Plato
banished the poets and songsters from his rationalist republic. The role of the senses and
accidental connections was, in very different ways, one of sullying knowledge in the
purest of both the rationalist and empiricist traditions. But David Hume, the deepest of
the empiricists, made passion central to human nature and knowing. Illumination from
witches and hermetical and magical processes remained strong themes in Renaissance thought
but also in the eminently respectable writings of Paracelsus, van Helmont and other
figures in early chemistry and, most notably, in Newtons world view (Webster, 1982).
The point of this is that the official line - that meaning and purpose and the so-called
final causes of the Aristotelian tradition were banned from scientific
explanation - leaves out the hugely important fact that they remained active in the
deepest assumptions of the greatest scientists such as Newton and Darwin (Rattansi, 1973;
Young, 1985, 1989 1992b)
If we look at the history of painting for evidence of the profound
truths which have been believed to inhere in the irrational, one need only mention Bosch,
Breughel, Goya, van Gogh, Surrealism and Dada for a continuous tradition of illumination
sought from primitive, irrational and disturbing images. Think of Magritte and Man Ray and
the films of Buñel. Similar stories can be told about literature, culminating in the
significance attached to automatic writing and stream of consciousness in recent times.
The history of psychiatry tells the same story, as Foucault has shown
in Madness and Civilisation and as was made part of a movement in aspects of the
so-called anti-psychiatry movement which was (in part wrongly) associated with the work of
Laing, Cooper and Esterson (Laing, 1960; Cooper, 1972; Laing and Esterson,1970; Boyers and
Orill, 1972; Ingleby, 1981). There is a common theme here - that we must pay attention to
what is usually called psychotic. It has a meaning. This is sensitively demonstrated in
Laings writings and exemplified in detail by Barhams analyses of discussions
among chronically schizophrenic patients (Barham, 1984, chs. 4 and 5). It could be said
that most of the four volumes by Harold Searles are demonstrating the meaningfulness of
psychotic utterances (Searles 1960, 1965, 1979, 1986), while his gladiatorial dialogue
with Langs defends his special competence in this utterly demanding work (Langs and
Searles, 1980, esp. ch. 4 and appendix).
Lets take stock. I have granted that there are banal and
potentially illuminating versions of my thesis. I have reminded you of certain differences
of preoccupation and approach of psychiatrists and those who think psychoanalytically. I
have contrasted nosology and dynamics. I have made a critique of the claims of
classification to be based on an unproblematic idea of the natural, since the natural is
itself historical - part of the history of culture. Finally, I have begun an attempt to
bring the primitive and irrational - the psychotic - to the centre of our humanity. In
doing so I have been implicitly undermining orthodox, ego psychology models, along with
orthodox psychiatric ones.
Now to psychotic anxieties per se.. Lest it be thought that the
strands of my argument are not being interwoven into a recognisable pattern, let me say
what I want you to discern in the final product. It is that human distress, if we are to
treat it as human, must be interpreted as intelligible all the way to its deepest roots as
well as its broadest determinations. A whole set of interpreters has helped us to place
ideas - including scientific, medical, psychiatric and psychological ideas - inside the
broader history of culture. They have not been as assiduous in doing this with primitive
forces in human nature, though, God knows, we have plenty of evidence at the moment for
the baleful effects of such forces. These, too, must be treated as part of the mainstream
of human nature in the individual and in groups, institutions, cultures and communities.
The fact that it is hard to find a language adequate for characterising and interpreting
pre-linguistic and sub-linguistic feelings only makes the problem more difficult and
challenging. It does not excuse abrogating the constitutive role of intense irrational
motives in how we think, feel and behave. To say with the philosopher that nothing
human is foreign to me is to open the door of theory and practice to the ubiquity of
psychotic anxieties and to begin to break down the barriers of mutual incomprehension and
subcultural separation between psychotherapy and psychiatry. I see these as
institutionalised forms of the splitting off of deep and irrational feelings from the
received account of how we think. If science is to be reintegrated with meaning, purpose,
goals and values - including ideology and politics - then psychotherapy, psychoanalysis
and psychiatry must, as part of the overall project, be reintegrated with the deepest
sources of the evalutive dimension. This has implications for both communities and for
training as well as practice.
I begin with some classic texts. This from Freuds
Formulation on the Two Principles of Mental Functioning (1911): With the
introduction of the reality principle one species of thought-activity was split off; it
was kept free from reality-testing and remained subordinated to the pleasure principle
alone. This activity is phantasying., which begins already in childrens play,
and later, continued as day-dreaming, abandons dependence on real objects
(Freud, 1911, p.222) The strangest characteristic of unconscious (repressed)
processes... is due to their entire disregard of reality testing; they equate reality of
thought with external actuality, and wishes with their fulfilment - with the event - just
as happens automatically under the dominance of the ancient pleasure principle (ibid.,
p. 225). Freud says here that the persistence of the irrational is fundamental to human
nature and remains so as we develop.
This from Joan Rivieres On the Genesis of Psychical
Conflict in Early Infancy (1952): I wish especially to point out... that from
the very beginning of life, on Freuds own hypothesis, the psyche responds to the
reality of its experiences by interpreting them - or rather, misinterpreting them -
in a subjective manner that increases its pleasure and preserves it from pain. This act of subjective interpretation of experience, which it carries out by means of the
processes of introjection and projection, is called by Freud hallucination; and it forms
the foundation of what we mean by phantasy-life. The phantasy-life of the
individual is thus the form in which his real internal and external sensations and
perceptions are interpreted and represented to himself in his mind under the influence of
the pleasure-pain principle. (It seems to me that one has only to consider for a moment to
see that, in spite of all the advances man has made in adaptation of a kind to external
reality, this primitive and elementary function of his psyche - to misinterpret his
perceptions for his own satisfaction - still retains the upper hands in the minds of the
great majority of even civilized adults.) (Riviere, 1952, p. 41). In claiming that
experience is characteristically misinterpreted at source and that hallucination is the
foundation of experience, Riviere is saying that there is no neutral observation language
in everyday life. The same claim is made of science in recent work in the philosophy of
science.
I want to turn now to the history of ideas about psychotic processes in
Klein, Bion and Meltzer. Klein described schizoid mechanisms as occurring in the
baby's development in the first year of life characteristically... the infant suffered
from states of mind that were in all their essentials equivalent to the adult psychoses,
taken as regressive states in Freud's sense (Meltzer, 1978, part 3, p. 22). Klein
says in the third paragraph of her most famous paper, 'Notes on Some Schizoid Mechanisms'
(1946), 'In early infancy anxieties characteristic of psychosis arise which drive the ego
to develop specific defence-mechanisms. In this period the fixation-points for all
psychotic disorders are to be found. This has led some people to believe that I regard all
infants as psychotic; but I have already dealt sufficiently with this misunderstanding on
other occasions' (Klein, 1975, vol. 3, p. 1). Meltzer comments that 'Although she denied
that this was tantamount to saying that babies are psychotic, it is difficult to see how
this implication could be escaped' (Meltzer, 1978, part 3, p. 22).
Kleinian thinking evolved in three stages. As in the above quotation,
Klein saw schizoid mechanisms and the paranoid-schizoid position as fixation points,
respectively, for schizophrenia and manic-depressive psychosis. Then the paranoid-schizoid
(ps) and depressive (d) positions became developmental stages. Her terminology included
'psychotic phases, 'psychotic positions' and then 'positions' (Klein, 1975, vol. 1,
pp. 275n-276n, 279). Thirdly, in the work of Bion and other post-Kleinians, these became
economic principles and part of the moment-to-moment vicissitudes of everyday life. The
notations 'ps' and 'd' were connected with a double-headed arrow - ps Ö d - to indicate how easily, frequently and normally
our inner states oscillate from the one to the other and back again (Meltzer, 1978, part
3, p. 22).
In Bion's writings on schizophrenia an ambiguity remained as to whether
or not the psychotic part of the personality is ubiquitous or only present in
schizophrenics (Bion,1967, esp. ch. 5), but Meltzer concludes his exposition of Bion's
schizophrenia papers by referring to the existence of these phenomena in patients of every
degree of disturbance, even 'healthy' candidates in training to be therapists (Meltzer, op.
cit., p. 28). Going further, he and colleagues have drawn on the inner world of
autistic patients to illuminate the norm (Meltzer et al, 1975; Frances Tustin 1986) has
essayed on autistic phenomena in neurotic patients, while Sydney Klein (1980) has
described 'autistic cysts' in neurotic patients. In his most recent writings on The
Claustrum (1992), Meltzer has elegantly shown that desperate defences against
schizophrenic breakdown account for much of the psychology and behaviour of competitive
and dramatically successful executives and leaders. Those who live in the claustrum - the
lower colon of the mental digestive tract - have inner worlds dominated by virulent
projective identification.
Klein's views on these matters are based on Freud and Abraham's notions
of oral libido and fantasies of cannibalism (Gedo, 1986, p. 94). She begins her essay,
A Contribution to the Psychogenesis of Manic-Depressive States (1935), with
claims about the extreme feelings of all babies: My earlier writings contain the
account of a phase of sadism at its height, through which children pass during the first
year of life. In the very first months of the babys existence it has sadistic
impulses directed, not only against its mothers breast, but also against the inside
of her body: scooping it out, devouring the contents, destroying it by every means which
sadism can suggest (Klein, 1975, vol. 1, p. 262). Once again, the projective and
introjective mechanisms of the first months and year give rise to anxiety situations and
defences against them, 'the content of which is comparable to that of the psychoses in
adults' (ibid.).
Orality is everywhere, for example, in the 'gnawing of conscience' (p.
268). Riviere says that 'such helplessness against destructive forces within constitutes
the greatest psychical danger-situation known to the human organism; and that this
helplessness is the deepest source of anxiety in human beings' (Riviere, 1952, p. 43). It
is the ultimate source of all neurosis. At this early stage of development, sadism is at
its height and is followed by the discovery that loved objects are in a state of
disintegration, in bits or in dissolution, leading to despair, remorse and anxiety, which
underlie numerous anxiety situations. Klein concludes, 'Anxiety situations of this kind I
have found to be at the bottom not only of depression, but of all inhibitions of work'
(Klein, 1975 vol. 1, p. 270).
It should be recalled that these are pre-linguistic experiences
developmentally, and sub-linguistic in adults. They are hard to characterise and hard to
think about. It is a characteristic of the world view of Kleinians that the primitive is
never transcended and that all experiences continue to be mediated through the mother's
body. Similarly, there is a persistence of primitive phantasies of body parts and bodily
functions, especially biting, eating, tearing, spitting out, urine and urinating, faeces
and defecating, mucus, genitals. One of the reasons we dont like to think about
these matters is that it is very hard to characterise them.
Why is all this such an innovation? Riviere points out that anxiety was
of great significance to Freud, but that much of his rhetoric was scientific, especially
physiological. He did not concern himself with the psychological content of
phantasies. Indeed, he and many of his so-called Freudian followers have
tended to use scientistic analogies instead of conveying human distress in evocative
language. By contrast, 'Anxiety, with the defences against it, has from the beginning been
Mrs Klein's approach to psycho-analytical problems. It was from this angle that she
discovered the existence and importance of aggressive elements in children's emotional
life... and [it] enabled her to bring much of the known phenomena of mental disorders into
line with the basic principles of analysis' (Riviere, 1952, pp. 8-9).
This contrast between Freud and Klein takes us back to one of the major
themes of my argument - the need to break away from describing the inner world in terms
drawn from a metapsychology based on analogies drawn from physics and biology. I am
advocating, instead, the bold use of terms drawn from the language of everyday life -
including and especially primitive emotional life - and the employment of any way of
representing primitive processes that comes to hand. This involves a move from the
didactic and objectivist language of natural science and the epistemologies which kow-tow
to it and toward evocative and phenomenological ways of attempting to convey the inner
meaning of experience. Mental space need not be reduced to the realm of extended
substances; it can be filled and populated by whatever kind of account helps us to keep
feeling alive. Rather than defer to the canons of Cartesian dualism, our criterion should
be whether or not a given account resonates with the dialectic of experience.
Kleinians have consistently written in a language which eschews
physicalist scientism, albeit Klein did retain a notion of instinct, even though this was
largely redundant as a result of her object relations perspective. They went on to propose
elements of a general psychology, including the claim that there is 'an unconscious
phantasy behind every thought and every act' (p.16). That is, the mental expression of
primitive processes 'is unconscious phantasy' (ibid.). It is not only a background
hum, as it were. Susan Isaacs claims that 'Reality thinking cannot operate without
concurrent and supporting unconscious phantasies' (Isaacs, 1952, p. 109). And again:
'phantasies are the primary content of unconscious mental processes' (pp. 82, 112). 'There
is no impulse, no instinctual urge or response which is not experienced as unconscious
phantasy' (p. 83). 'Phantasies have both psychic and bodily effects, e.g., in conversion
symptoms, bodily qualities, character and personality, neurotic symptoms, inhibitions and
sublimations' (p. 112). They even determine the minutiae of body language (p. 100). The
role of unconscious phantasy extends from the first to the most abstract thought. The
infant's first thought of the existence of the external world comes from sadistic attacks
on the mother's body (Klein, 1975, vol. 1, p. 276; vol. 3, p. 5). 'Phantasies - becoming
more elaborate and referring to a wider variety of objects and situations - continue
throughout development and accompany all activities; they never stop playing a great part
in mental life. The influence of unconscious phantasy on art, on scientific work, and on
the activities of everyday life cannot be overrated' (Klein, 1975, vol. 3, p. 251; cf. p.
262).
These anxieties are not only ubiquitous: they interact in complicated
ways. As Riviere points out, 'It is impossible to do any justice here to the complexity
and variety of the anxiety-situations and the defences against them dominating the psyche
during these early years. The factors involved are so numerous and the combinations and
interchanges so variable. The internal objects are employed against external, and external
against internal, both for satisfaction and for security; desire is employed against hate
and destructiveness; omnipotence against impotence, and even impotence (dependence)
against destructive omnipotence; phantasy against reality and reality against phantasy.
Moreover, hate and destruction are employed as measures to avert the dangers of desire and
even of love. Gradually a progressive development takes place... by means of the interplay
of these and other factors, and of them with external influences, out of which the child's
ego, his object-relations, his sexual development, his super-ego, his character and
capacities are formed' (Riviere, 1952, pp. 59-60).
It was on the foundation of these ideas about individual psychology
that the classical work on groups and institutions of Bion, Elliott Jaques and Isabel
Menzies Lyth was built. Bion argued that group phenomena required a deeper explanation
than the Freudian one employing the family and id, ego and superego. He did not repudiate
these but delved deeper into the realm of psychotic anxieties, which he believed operated
in all groups. The forms of distress that converted sensible work groups into
mad ones dominated by what he called basic assumptions, correspond so
closely with extremely primitive part objects that sooner or later psychotic anxiety,
appertaining to these primitive relationships, is released. The defensive measures
to which the groups resort are the same as those which individual babies employ in the
face of their earliest anxieties (Bion, 1955, p. 456). Bion suggests that these primitive
anxieties contain the ultimate sources of all group behaviour (p. 476).
Jaques begins his essay on 'Social Systems as a Defence against
Persecutory and Depressive Anxiety' (1955) by reiterating that 'social phenomena show a
striking correspondence with psychotic processes in individuals', that 'institutions are
used by their individual members to reinforce individual mechanisms of defence against
anxiety', and 'that the mechanisms of projective and introjective identification operate
in linking individual and social behaviour'. He argues the thesis that 'the primary
cohesive elements binding individuals into institutionalised human association is that of
defence against psychotic anxiety' (Jaques, 1955, pp. 478-9). He points out that the
projective and introjective processes he is investigating are basic to even the most
complex social processes and directs us to Paula Heimann's argument that they are at the
bottom of all our dealings with one another (p. 481, 481n).
His conclusion is cautionary and points out the conservative - even
reactionary - consequences of our psychotic anxieties and our group and institutional
defences against them. He suggests that as a result of these reflections on human nature
'it may become more clear why social change is so difficult to achieve, and why many
social problems are so intractable. From the point of view here elaborated, changes in
social relationships and procedures call for a restructuring of relationships at the
phantasy level, with a consequent demand upon individuals to accept and tolerate changes
in their existing patterns of defences against psychotic anxiety. Effective social change
is likely to require analysis of the common anxieties and unconscious collusions
underlying the social defences determining phantasy social relationships' (p.498).
I turn finally to the investigator who, in my opinion, has made the
most of this perspective, Isabel Menzies Lyth, who built her research on the shoulders of
Bion and Jaques. She has investigated a number of fraught settings, extending from the
fire brigade to the Institute of Psychoanalysis, but the piece of research which has
deservedly made her world-famous is described in a report entitled 'The Functioning of
Social Systems as a Defence against Anxiety' (1959). It is a particularly poignant
document, which addresses the question why people of good will and idealistic motives do
not do what they intend, that is, why nurses find themselves, to an astonishing degree, not caring for patients and leaving the nursing service in droves. It would be repetitious to
review the mechanisms she describes. They are the ones discussed above. What is so
distressing is that they operate overwhelmingly in a setting which has as its very reason
for existence the provision of sensitivity and care. Yet that setting is full of threats
to life itself and arouses the psychotic anxieties I have outlined. She says, 'The
objective situation confronting the nurse bears a striking resemblance to the phantasy
situations that exist in every individual in the deepest and most primitive levels of the
mind. The intensity and complexity of the nurse's anxieties are to be attributed primarily
to the peculiar capacity of the objective features of her work situation to stimulate
afresh those early situations and their accompanying emotions' (Menzies Lyth, 1988, pp.
46-7).
The result is the evolution of socially structured defence mechanisms
which take the form of routines and division of tasks which effectively preclude the nurse
relating as a whole person to the patient as a whole person. 'The implicit aim of such
devices, which operate both structurally and culturally, may be described as a kind of
depersonalisation or elimination of individual distinctiveness in both nurse and patient.
For example, nurses often talk about patients not by name, but by bed numbers or by their
diseases or a diseased organ: "the liver in bed 10" or "the pneumonia in
bed 15". Nurses deprecate this practice, but it persists' (pp. 51-2). She lists and
discusses the reifying devices which reduce everyone involved to part-objects, including
insight into why the nurse wakes you up to give you a sleeping pill (p. 69). There is a
whole system of overlapping ways of evading the full force of the anxieties associated
with death, the ones which lie at the heart of the mechanisms which Klein described (pp.
63-64; cf. Riviere, 1952, p. 43).
Menzies Lyth also draws a cautionary conclusion: 'In general, it may be
postulated that resistance to social change is likely to be greatest in institutions whose
social defence systems are dominated by primitive psychic defence mechanisms, those which
have been collectively described by Melanie Klein as the paranoid-schizoid defences'
(Menzies Lyth, 1988, p. 79). In recent reflections on her work and that of her colleagues,
she has reiterated just how refractory to change institutions are (Menzies Lyth, 1988, pp.
1-42 and personal communications).
That completes my exposition of the Kleinian and post-Kleinian
literature. I find it sobering and profoundly challenging to any hope for a better world.
I do not think it can be squared with at least two other traditions. The first is the
orthodox and neo-Freudian one where the egos mechanisms of defence manage to keep
irrational forces at bay or to neutralise or tame them before they enter consciousness.
Nor do I find it compatible with the convenient distinction between people who are either
normal (or normally miserable and neurotic) and others who are in a different state called
psychotic, with allowances for periods in the repair shop called breakdowns.
Im not saying that there are not psychotic people or people who have breakdowns. I
am saying that those people are not as strange to the rest of us as the nosologists would
have you believe. My point is that we are not strangers to psychotic processes in our
everyday lives, families, groups, institutions and societies. There is a lot of it about
all the time - not just the wars and conflicts we see all around us, particularly at the
moment. I refer also to what happens in psychotherapeutic and psychoanalytic training
organisations - also particularly at the moment when a paranoid atmosphere has been
generated by the divisive behaviour of a small number of elitists who, in my opinion and
that of some eminent psychoanalysts, have destructively sought to undermine the United
Kingdom Standing Conference on Psychotherapy. But this is not unusual. What is surprising
is that this sort of behaviouroccurs in and between psychotherapeutic, psychoanalytic and
group relations institutions - the cradles of the very psychodynamic enlightenment which I
have been trying to lay before you. But thats not surprising, either. It is true in
the churches, academic institutions and charities, the schools, asylums and major
corporations, monasteries and nunneries, orphanages and sports teams, political parties
and communes. I am not listing institutions for completeness sake. I have in mind
quite specific incidents and histories. Not all the time but in all institutions. We are
all partly psychotic all of the time and all of us psychotic part of the time. Bion
insists that the move into basic assumption functioning is involuntary, automatic and
inevitable (Bion, 1955, p. 458).
Having objects into which to project is the sine qua non of
mental well-being. But we do so in a vulnerable space, on one side of which is nameless
dread and a black hole and on the other the intense projections of outgrouping, racism and
virulent nationalism. All of us become humans by learning to project and members of groups
by being socialised into their projective identifications, some good, some very nasty
(Young, forthcoming, chs.6 and 7). The same is true of professions, even and especially
helping professions like nursing, medicine, psychiatry and psychotherapy.
I recall that eminent Freudian, Joseph Sandler, describing
psychotherapy as a process of making friends with the unacceptable parts of ourselves.
Just as Bion said we had to delve deeper than Freud to get at the ultimate sources of all
group behaviour, I think we have to grant that the ubiquity of psychotic anxieties means
that we are up against much more in ourselves that we are inclined to believe. So there
are even more unacceptable parts to be befriended or neutralised or repressed by the thin
veneer of civilisation. To deny their ubiquity or to overestimate the strength of that
veneer strikes me as ostrich-like and to tempt us to hide our eyes from the lessons of the
nursery, the family, society and international relations. I think this blinkered attitude
helps to explain why psychiatrists and psychotherapists try to restrict the range of their
obligations, the people with whom they work and the issues upon which they reflect.
We split off these feelings and try to confine them to scapegoats
called psychotics. I suggest that much official psychopathology and
classification serve defensive purposes and protect us from psychotic anxieties. These are
forms of control which - like the banishment of purposes and goals in scientific
explanation - sequester existential risk and politics and drive underground the legitimate
angst of suffering people. The official healers in society do their jobs humanely but get
turned into minders. While I was still writing this paper I saw a film about the huge oil
spill of the Exxon Veldeez in Alaska, in which phalanxes of reasonably conscientious
officials never got into a hands-on tactile relationship with the millions of gallons of
sludge or the fatal coating their ways of working and their blinkered notion of energy had
allowed to stifle life. It struck me as a metaphor for the urgency of the
reconceptualisation I am proposing.
I think Freud pointed the way in the concluding passage in his
presciently realistic though pessimistic essay - Civilization and Its Discontents (1930).
He wrote that the history of civilisation is 'the struggle between Eros and Death,
between the instinct of life and the instinct of destruction, as it works itself out in
the human species. This struggle is what all life essentially consists of... And it is
this battle of the giants that our nurse-maids try to appease with their lullaby about
Heaven' (Freud.,1930, p. 122).
Paper presented to international conference on Psychosis:
Understanding and Treatment, University of Essex, Colchester September 1992, to
appear in Jane Ellwood, ed, Psychosis: Understanding and Treatment. London: Jessica
Kingsley, 1995, pp. 34-53.
REFERENCES (Place of publication is London unless
otherwise specified.)
Amacher, P. (1965) Freuds Neurological Education and Its
Influence on Psychoanalytic Theory, Psychol. Issues, 4, no. 4, Monograph 16.
APA - American Psychiatric Association (1987) Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (Third Edition - Revised). Washington, DC:
American Psychiatric Association.
Barham, P. (1984) Schizophrenia and Human Value. Blackwell.
______ (1992) Closing the Asylum: The Mental Patient in Modern
Society. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Bernfield, S. (1944) Freuds Earliest Theories and the
School of Helmholtz, Psychoanal. Quart. 13:341-62
______ (1949) Freuds Scientific Beginnings, Am.
Imago 6:3-36.
______ (1951) Sigmund Freud, M.D., 1881-1885, Int. J.
Psycho-anal. 32:204-17.
Berrios, G. E. (1991) British Psychopathology since the Early
20th Century, in G. E. Berrios and H. Freeman, eds., 150 Years of British
Psychiatry 1841-1991. Gaskell, pp. 232-44.
Bion, W. R. (1955) Group Dynamics: a Re-view, in M. Klein
et al., eds. (1955), pp. 440-77.
______ (1961) Experiences in Groups and Other Papers.. Tavistock.
______ (1967) Second Thoughts: Selected Papers on Psycho-Analysis. Heinemann; reprinted Maresfield, 1984.
Boyers, R. and Orrill, R., eds. (1972) Laing and Anti-Psychiatry. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Cooper, D. (1972) The Death of the Family. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Feuchstersleben, E. F. von (1847) The Principles of Medical
Psychology.
Sydenham Society.
Figlio, K. (1978) 'Chlorosis and Chronic Disease in Nineteenth-Century
Britain: the Social Constitution of Somatic Illness in a Capitalist Society', Internat.
J. Health Services 8:589-617.
______ (1979) 'Sinister Medicine: A Critique of Left Approaches to
Medicine', Radical Science J. 9:14-68.
______ (1985) 'Medical Diagnosis, Class Dynamics, Social Stability, in
L. Levidow and R.M. Young, eds., Science, Technology and the Labour Process: Marxist
Studies, Vol. 2., pp. 129-65.
______(1990) ,'The Environment: Topographies of the Internal and
External Worlds', talk delivered to the Centre for Psycho-analytic Studies, University of
Kent.
Foucault, M. (1967) Madness and
Civilisation: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. Tavistock.
Freud, S. (1953-73) The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, 24 vols. Hogarth. (S. E.)
______ (1891) On Aphasia: A Clinical Study. New York:
International Universities Press, 1953.
______ (1900) The Interpretation of Dreams., S. E. 4.
______ (1911) Formulation on the Two Principles of Mental
Functioning, S. E., pp. 218-26.
_____ (1930) Civilization and Its Discontents., S.E. 21,
pp. 59-145.
______ (1933) New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis. S. E. 22,
pp. 3-182.
Gedo, J. E. (1986) Conceptual Issues in Psychoanalysis: Essays in
History and Method. New York: Analytic Press.
Haraway, D. (1989) Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the
World of Modern Science. Routledge.
______ 1990) Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. Free
Association Books.
Holland, Sir H. (1852) Chapters on Mental Physiology. Longman,
Brown, Green and Longmans.
Ingleby, D., ed. (1981) Critical Psychiatry: The Politics of Mental
Health. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Isaacs, S. (1952) 'The Nature and Function of Phantasy', in Klein et
al. (1952), pp. 67-121.
Jaques, E. (1955) 'Social Systems as Defence against Persecutory and
Depressive Anxiety', in Klein et al., eds. (1955), pp. 478-98.
Klein, M. (1975) The Writings of Melanie Klein, 4 vols. Hogarth.
______ (1935) A Contribution to the Psychogenesis of
Manic-Depressive States, in Klein (1975), vol. 1, pp. 262-89.
______ (1946) Notes on Some Schizoid Mechanisms, in Klein
(1975), vol. 3, pp. 1-24.
______ et al. (1952) Developments in Psycho-Analysis. Hogarth;
reprinted Karnac, 1989.
______ et al., eds. (1955) New Directions in Psycho-Analysis: The
Significance of Infant Conflict in the Patterns of Adult Behaviour. Tavistock;
reprinted Maresfield Library, 1977.
Klein, S. (1980) 'Autistic Phenomena in Neurotic Patients', Int. J.
Psycho-Anal. 61:395-402.
Laing, R.D. (1960) The Divided Self.: An Existential Study in Sanity
and Madness. Tavistock; reprinted Penguin, 1965..
______ and Esterson, A. (1970) Sanity, Madness and the Family:
Families of Schizophrenics. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Langs, R. and Searles, H. F. (1980) Intrapsychic and Interpersonal
Dimensions of Treatment: A Clinical Dialogue. Aronson.
Lukács, G. (1923) History and Class Consciousness: Studies in
Marxist Dialectics. Merlin, 1971.
Lyth, I. M. (1959) The Functioning of Social Systems as a Defence
against Anxiety Human Relations 13:95-121; reprinted in Containing Anxieties in
Institutions: Selected Essays. Free Association Books, 1988, pp. 43-88.
Maudsley, H. (1867) The Physiology and Pathology of Mind. Macmillan.
MacIntyre, A. (1977) Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative
and the Philosophy of Science, The Monist 60:453-72.
______ (1981) After Virtue. Duckworth
Mayo, T. (1838) Elements of the Pathology of the Human Mind. Murray.
Meltzer, D. (1978) The Kleinian Development. Clunie.
______ (1992) The Claustrum: An Investigation of Claustrophobic
Phenomena. Clunie
______ et al. (1975). Explorations in Autism: A
Psycho-Analytic Study. Clunie.
Rattansi, P. M. (1973) Some Evaluations of Reason in Sixteenth-
and Seventeenth-Century Natural Philosophy, in M. Teich and R. M. Young, eds., Changing Perspectioves in the History of Science. Heinemann, pp. 148-66.
Rey, H. (forthcoming) Kleinian Psychoanalysis in Theory and
Practice: Selected Papers (provisional title). Free Association Books.
Riese, W. (1958) Freudian Concepts of Brain Function and Brain
Disease, J. Nerv. Ment. Dis. 127:287-307.
Riviere, J. (1952) 'General Introduction', in Klein et al. (1952), pp.
1-36.
______ (1952) 'On the Genesis of Psychical Conflict in Early Infancy',
in Klein et al. (1952), pp. 37-66.
Rorty, R. (1980) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.. Oxford: Blackwell.
______ (1982) Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-80). Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
______ (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge University Press.
Rosenfeld, H. (1965) Psychotic States: a Psychoanalytic Approach. Hogarth;
reprinted Maresfield, 1982.
______ (1987) Impasse and Interpretation: Therapeutic and
Anti-Therapeutic Factors in Psychoanalytic Treatment of Psychotic, Borderline, and
Neurotic Patients. Routledge.
Searles, H. F. (1960) The Nonhuman Environment: In Normal
Development and in Schizophrenia. Madison, CT., International Universities Press.
______(1965) Collected Papers on Schizophrenia and Related Subjects. Hogarth; reprinted Karnac, 1986.
______ (1979) Countertransference and Related Subjects. Madison,
CT.: International Universities Press.
______(1986) My Work with Borderline Patients. Aronson.
Segal, H. (1981) The Work of Hanna Segal: A Kleinian Approach to
Clinical Practice. Aronson; reprinted Free Association Books/ Maresfield Library, 1986
Silver, D. and Rosenbleuth, M. (1992) Handbook of Borderline
Disorders. Madison, CT: International Universities Press.
Spillius, E. B. (1988 Melanie Klein Today, 2 vols. Routledge
Stengel. E. A. (1954) A Re-evaluation of Freuds Book On
Aphasia : Its Significance for Psychoanalysis, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 35:85-89.
Tarnopolsky, A. (1992) The Validity of the Borderline Personality
Disorder, in Silver and Rosenbleuth, eds. (1992), pp.29-52.
Tustin, F. (1986) Autistic Barriers in Neurotic Patients. Karnac.
Webster, C. (1982) From Paracelsus to Newton: Magic and the Making
of Modern Science. Cambridge.
Young, R. M. (1970) Mind, Brain and Adaptation in the Nineteenth
Century : Cerebral Localization and Its Biological Context from Gall to Ferrier.
Oxford: Clarendon Press; reprinted Oxford University Press, 1990.
______ (1971) Evolutionary Biology and Ideology: Then and
Now Science Studies 1:177-206.
______ (1973) 'The Human Limits of Nature', in J. Benthall, ed., The
Limits of Human Nature. Allen Lane, pp. 235-74.
______ (1977) 'Science is Social Relations', Radical Sci. J. 5:65-131.
.______ (1985) Darwin's Metaphor: Nature's Place in Victorian
Culture. Cambridge University Press
______ (1986) 'Freud: Scientist and/or Humanist', Free Assns. 6:7-35,1986.
______ (1989) 'Persons, Organisms... and Primary Qualities', in J.
Moore, ed., History, Humanity and Evolution: Essays for John C. Greene Cambridge
University Press, 1989, pp. 375-401.
______ (1990) 'The Mind-Body Problem', in R. C. Olby et al.,
eds., Companion to the History of Modern Science Routledge, 1990, pp. 702-11.
______ (1992) 'The Vicissitudes of Transference and
Countertransference: The Work of Harold Searles', J. Arbours Association, 9:24-58,1992.
______ (1992a) 'Science, Ideology and Donna Haraway', Sci. as
Culture (no.15) 3:7-46.
______ (in press)) Darwins Metaphor and the Philosophy of
Science, Science as Culture, (no. 16) 3(3).
______ (forthcoming) Mental Space. Free Association Books.
______ and Postle, D. (1981) Behaving Ourselves, television
film in the series Crucible: Science in Society. Channel Four.
______ and Gold, M. (1982) A History of Nature, ibid.
Address for corresp0ondence: 26 Freegrove R.,
London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
© The Author
|
|