Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
REDUCTIONISM AND OVERDETERMINATION IN THE EXPLANATION OF HUMAN
NATURE
by Robert M. Young
It is of the essence of explanations that their proponents should seek
to make them account for all they can. Newton once said that the whole business of natural
philosophy was: from the phenomena of matter and motion to explain the other
phenomena. This is the locus classicus of materialist reductionism. It is the
warrant in the scientific revolution of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries for the
ambitions of molecular biologists as they get appointed to professorships of psychiatry
and speak in disparaging ways about psychodynamic explanations and applicants. At the
other extreme we find some speculations of Jürgen Habermas toward the end of his Knowledge
and Human Interests, where he suggested that psychoanalytic explanation might well be
the paradigm for all explanations and that explanations in physics might be the degenerate
case of an explanation just the opposite of the materialist reductionist pecking
order of explanations.
I cite these two examples to give you a sense of what I am here to
speak about. We have more candidates for explanations than we need. Each seeks to extend
its writ as far as it can. I shall argue that this is okay if we think about reductionism
and overdetermination in the right way. In the course of my argument I shall briefly
explore some ambitious forms of explanation and try to show how they can legitimately
claim vast areas while, at the same time, we want to claim much of that very same
territory for other explanations.
One of the reasons I began to explore this topic was that I was very
struck by a passage in Peter Barhams marvellous book, Schizophrenia and Human
Value. He says, quite simply, that he has never understood why the possibility that
schizophrenia might have a genetic component or be biochemically based in some other way,
should lead us to pay any less attention to the experiential dimension of mental illness.
Why, indeed?
I suppose that it would not be an exaggeration to say that I have spent
the better part of a decade each on four ambitious forms of explanation: Cartesian
dualism, Darwinism, Marxism and Freudianism. I have expressed them eponimously. Put
conceptually, as approaches to human nature, I mean philosophical analysis, biological
explanations, the analysis of ideology and the sociology of knowledge and, lastly, the
role of primitive processes and unconscious motivation in the inner world and their impact
on the behaviour of individuals and groups. If I was being properly autobiographical, I
would add a fifth determination: moral, including religious, discourse, but in doing so I
immediately plunge myself into the conundrums which I am attempting to illuminate. By this
I mean that it is part of my understanding of these matters that each seeks to encompass
and account for the others, so that, for example, Descartes characterised the mind-body
distinction as he did partly because of the place he wanted to maintain for responsibility
and free will in the explanatory scheme which was being elaborated in the scientific
revolution. Thats why he did not explain everything by recourse to extended
substances and retained a role for thinking substances, thus creating a conundrum which
has plagued modern thought: the problem of the relationship between mind and body.
Something similar can be said of the other three forms of explanation. Darwins
philosophy of nature drew heavily on Paleys natural theology and Malthus moral
strictures and his iron law of population. Marx stressed the role of economic and
ideological determinations of the categories of knowledge and the role of the
socio-economic base in conditioning what counts as an acceptable explanation in the
superstructure of intellectual life. This approach was based ultimately on a moral
critique of the capitalist mode of production. For me to say that, of course, is to take
sides in a debate within Marxism, since there is a faction which holds, on the contrary,
that Marx started life as a humanist but that his thinking underwent what is famously
called an epistemological break, after which he thought scientifically. I am
sketching these examples to make it clear that there are lots of explanations fighting
over turfs. The scientific claims to be deeper than the moral, and the moral can be seen
as deeper than the scientific.
Other systems of ideas drawing on the category of ideology can
legitimately be seen as muted forms of Marxism, e.g., Karl Mannheims discipline of
the sociology of knowledge, which pointed to the category of interest
as in special interests and special pleading the evaluative dimension in his
critique of knowledge. Mannheim was called a bourgeois Lukács, just as Weber
was called a bourgeois Marx. These quips point to the extent to which they
were thought to stop short of the full version of Marxism. Georg Lukács, in the period in
question, took the concept of ideology all the way to include nature. Mannheim was
equivocal about how far his sociological explanations extended and did not root them in a
Marxist view of the socio-economic. Indeed, he thought his sociologists of knowledge could
adopt a position called relationalism which was above the battle of interests,
a vantage point not envisaged in Marxism. Max Weber also stopped short of a full
socio-economic explanation with his notion of charismatic leadership.
Turning to Freud, it is well-known that the scientific aspect of his
views coexisted with a deeply moral theory (as delineated by Philip Rieff in Freud: The
Mind of the Moralist) and drew heavily on the Jewish tradition, about which he felt
overtly ambivalent (as delineated by David Bakan in Freud and the Jewish Mystical
Tradition).
Please take careful note of what I just did. I took one of the five
candidates for explaining human nature religion and morality and mentioned
the ways in which each of the others drew upon important aspects of it. A religious
fundamentalist, whether pre-Darwinian or current, would seek to subordinate all other explanations to the religious and moral dimensions. In a sense I would agree with
that view in that I believe that moral or evaluative discourse is more basic than any
other kind. However, although I was once told that certain dandy Lacanians and
postmodernists regard me as a fundamentalist (mind you, the reporter was a slavering
follower of whatever the latest fashion might be) although I have been so
described, I trust that I am not merely reverting to the Calvinism of my youth. What I am
doing is giving you a sketch of the first set of boxes in a matrix which, if I was clever
and articulate enough, would take each of the five modes of explanation and show how it
sought to account for the other four. This leads to a fulsome situation of
overdetermination. I am sure that you know this in an intuitive, if not systematic, way.
Here are some familiar examples. Psychoanalysis seeks to account for religion as a
projection of infantile feelings, particularly the punitive superego, onto the universe.
Marx sought to do something similar to religious thought, e.g., in the Theses on
Feuerbach, and other forms of bourgeois morality throughout the writings of Marx and
Engels. Freud mounted a critique of Marxism, which he claimed was incompatible with what
we know about human nature, in the last of his New Introductory Lectures, entitled
The Question of a Weltanschauung. Freud, displaying a perfect case of
what Marx would call false consciousness, believed himself to be free of a world view.
Let us dwell for a time on the Darwinian mode of explanation. I hasten
to say that much is said in the name of Darwin, as in the names of Marx and Freud and
Descartes, which would surprise and dismay the man himself. Darwin, for example, is often
characterised as the scourge of religious explanations. The fact is that he placed
religious quotations at the front of On the Origin of Species and ended the text
with a statement about life being breather into a few forms by the deity. It has been
argued, by me, among other Darwin scholars, that Darwinism absorbed science into a more
abstract deism and did not undermine religion at all. In case you think that is an
anachronistic reading of the Victorian conflict between science and religion, it is worth
recalling of Darwin, as it is of Newton, that his remains were buried in Westminster Abbey
and that one of the authors of an important pre-Darwinian tract which advocated the
uniformity of nature at the expense of the Biblical Flood, became Archbishop of
Canterbury.
Even so, these days, Darwinian tends to be used by
scientists who delight in sticking pins in religious and moral explanations and gleefully
argue that life and evolution are nothing but meaningless self-replication.
You might say that such people are meanies (or memes) and should not be
attended to, but the truth is that they are the chosen pundits in these matters and have
both scientific and cultural legitimacy. Lewis Wolpert is a Fellow of the Royal Society
and holds a distinguished professorship, and Richard Dawkins was a Reader at Oxford and a
Fellow of an Oxford College. He has recently been made a Professor of the Public
Understanding of Science. Both delight in attacking humanistic values and philosophies.
Dawkins likens religion to a virus and uses epidemiological rhetoric to write about it. He
is so zealous in this endeavour that he had to be persuaded not to characterise all of
culture in the same way. Wolpert is something of a Canute about social and conceptual
aspects of science. He believes that science has settled all important matters in the
theory of knowledge.
These men are, in my opinion, clowns, but make no mistake, they are
highly respected and frequently called upon for talks, lecture series and for radio and
television appearances. Theirs is the nothing but school of life and humanity.
Others trample on traditional values in the same mischievous schoolboy way, for example,
Francis Crick. One of his collaborators, Sydney Brenner (who helped discover the genetic
alphabet and has been knighted), played a similar role in my Cambridge college,
Kings. Once, when I introduced him to a distinguished philosopher of science at a
college feast, Brenner snarled, Philosophy of science, eh? I thought theyd
wound that up. When told this story, Wolpert exploded, He was quite
right!.
These people take the line that we must separate facts from values and
that the only certain knowledge is scientific knowledge. They are neo-positivists. There
is knowledge and there is emotion, about which no rationality is possible. (I have often
thought that this is why so many holders of this position have been philanderers, Alfred
Ayer, for example.) Their inner worlds are based on a massive split. In fact, both Wolpert
and Brenner have had serious psychological difficulties. Wolpert solved his
with drugs and lampooned psychotherapy, Brenner addressed his with Jungian analysis, which
he kept secret for a long time.
There is a school of students of biology and of animal and human
behaviour whose members are militant about the applicability of Darwinian ideas of
competitiveness to all sorts of phenomena. They tend to be conservative politically. At
the biological end we find an Oxford Professor of Genetics, the late C. D. Darlington,
who, in his comprehensive tome, The Evolution of Man and Society, explained all of
human history in terms of the survival of the fittest. Edward O. Wilson took the same line
in creating the discipline of sociobiology, in which he argued that ethics should be
handed over to the students of animal behaviour for a time to get a more realistic view of
what is possible in social life. Most recently, we find one of his protégés, Frank
Sulloway, arguing that all sorts of aspects of belief, innovation, political tendency and
social philosophy can be attributed to a single explanatory factor: birth order. He
conducts this argument as a militant refutation of all psychodynamic, particularly
psychoanalytic, explanations. He set about this project (for which a publisher has paid a
half a million dollars in advance royalties) after attempting to reduce Freud to a Biologist
of the Mind (the subtitle of his book) by the simple expedient of legislating away the
cultural half of Freuds theory. No Oedipus complex, no Interpretation of Dreams,
no distress about getting to Rome. All was explained through the lens of Freuds
relationship with Wilhelm Fliess and the (undoubtedly important but not all-encompassing)
influence of Darwinian thinking on Freud.
The history of investigation of human nature and society has always had
its biological reductionists, some academic, some popular, many with a foot in both camps.
I have in mind Konrad Lorentz, Nobel Laureate for his ethological work, who was also an
active Nazi. Or Lionel Tiger and Robin Fox, biologically reductionist anthropologists with
conservative social philosophies. Or Robert Ardrey, an amateur whose social Darwinist
books caused quite a stir. The person of this ilk who has had the greatest popular impact
is probably Desmond Morris, though I would argue that Richard Attenborough and Walt Disney
(particularly in his True Life Adventures) have had an even more widespread
influence in making it seem common sense that evolution and animal behaviour show us more
about competition then co-operation, more about the instinctual in humanity than the
civilised. While we take in the quaintness of Jane Goodalls gorillas, we are
probably not on our guard about the version of humanity which is being propagated in the
interstices of the perfectly legitimate story which links us to our evolutionary
ancestors.
Please do not mis-hear me. I would be the first to argue for
evolutionary continuity between humans and other animals. I could argue this both as a
scholar and as a man. I have a healthy respect and fondness for primitive impulses and
innate aggressiveness, as I do for erotic and dependent feelings and for erogenous zones.
I can tell as good a story as the next student of evolution about why we have dependent
children for as long as we do, why we dress as we do, care about the smells that we do,
have our eyes and hands and tongues drawn to the parts of the body that we do, and so on.
My purpose here is not to denigrate the animal or biological or evolutionary, much less
the sexual, but to point to the efforts made by some to make those explanations colonise
and dominate the territory of social and moral and political and ideological explanations.
I am drawing your attention to the dialectic between reductionisms and overdetermination.
I want to turn next to Freudian explanations. There is a man at the LSE
named Dilman who wants to make Freud into a biologist rather as Sulloway did. There is a
book by Ritvo on the influence of Darwin on Freud. I have written about the influence of
the British psychological evolutionist Herbert Spencer on Freud, and others have stressed
the importance of his period as a comparative neurophysiologist and neurologist under the
influence of John Hughlings Jackson, who thought of neurological symptomatology in terms
of evolution and dissolution. Then there is the libido theory, with its relatively fixed
developmental stages, linking erogenous zones and stages of sexual development pretty
strictly to age bands and linking various forms of psychopathology to failure to negotiate
the developmental tasks appropriate to those phases. I say all this to grant much to the
biological in Freud. He argued in Civilization and Its Discontents that the veneer
of civilization is thin and easily breached, that man is a wolf to other men and that only
guilt and sublimation could curb our otherwise rapacious and polymorphously perverse
sexual impulses. He also remained throughout his life a psychophysical parallelist and
argued that the neurophysiologists would come along one day and fill in the base clef, as
it were. My point for the moment is that Freud accepted a version of Cartesian dualism and
attributed a great deal to the instinctual and the biological level of explanation,
especially the neurological, which he appears to have thought would one day provide a more
basic level of explanation than he had.
However, and this is the important point for what I want to claim for
psychoanalytic explanation, he decided one day at the turn of the century to remain on
psychological ground. When he did so he came increasingly to feel that psychoanalysis was
sufficient for understanding humanity. He said at one point, For sociology too,
dealing as it does with the behaviour of people in society, cannot be anything but applied
psychology. Strictly speaking there are only two sciences: psychology, pure and applied,
and natural science' (p 179). No social psychology, no sociology, no economics, no
politics at least in the sense that none of these could, as he saw things, provide
resting places in explanation. Everything goes back to id, ego, superego and the Oedipus
complex. There is not a jot of exaggeration in what I am saying. Freud said of The
Future of an Illusion and Civilization and Its Discontents, 'I recognised ever
more clearly that the events of human history, the interactions between human nature,
cultural development, and the precipitates of primeval experience (as whose representative
religion pushes to the fore) are only the reflection of the dynamic conflicts among ego,
id, and superego, which psychoanalysis studies in the individual the same events
repeated on a wider stage' (quoted in Gay, p. 547). His biographer, Peter Gay, concludes,
'He could not have stated the essential unity of his thought any more forcefully' (Ibid.).
There is no place in Freud's thinking for what the social scientists
call 'the autonomy of the social', that is, for social causes operating at a different
level from the psychological and deriving from genuinely social forces, even though they
are mediated through the individual psyche. There is not even relative autonomy.
One might have hoped that his followers would correct this regrettable reductionism. On
the contrary, along came Klein and Bion, who made no move to bring in other explanatory
factors. Indeed, they went deeper into the unconscious for their ultimate explanations and
said that the real bottom line was primitive thought: psychotic anxieties and the defences
erected against them.
The difference between the worlds of Freud and Klein may be described
as one of level of explanation and of causality but this difference lies entirely
within psychoanalytic explanation and makes no reference to other causal factors. Bion put
the point clearly in the conclusion to his essay, 'Group Dynamics - A Re-view', He says,
'Freud's view of the dynamics of the group seems to me to require supplementing rather
than correction' (Bion, 1961, p. 187). He accepts Freud's claim that the family group is
the basis for all groups but adds that I would go further; I think that the central
position in group dynamics is occupied by the more primitive mechanisms that Melanie Klein
has described as peculiar to the paranoid-schizoid and depressive positions. In other
words, I feel... that it is not simply a matter of the incompleteness of the illumination
provided by Freud's discovery of the family group as the prototype of all groups, but the
fact that this incompleteness leaves out the source of the main emotional drives of the
group' (p. 188). He then summarises the notions of 'work group' and the 'basic
assumptions' that assail them 'dependence', 'pairing', 'fight-flight' and
suggests that these may have a common link or may be different aspects of each other.
'Further investigation shows that each basic assumption contains features that correspond
so closely with extremely primitive part objects that sooner or later psychotic anxiety,
appertaining to these primitive relationships, is released. These anxieties, and the
mechanisms peculiar to them, have already been displayed in psychoanalysis by Melanie
Klein, and her descriptions tally well with the emotional states' of the basic assumption
group. Such groups have aims 'far different either from the overt task of the group or
even from the tasks that would appear to be appropriate to Freud's view of the group as
based on the family group. But approached from the angle of psychotic anxiety, associated
with phantasies of primitive part object relationships... the basic assumption phenomena
appear far more to have the characteristics of defensive reactions to psychotic anxiety,
and to be not so much at variance with Freud's views as supplementary to them. In my view,
it is necessary to work through both the stresses that appertain to family patterns and
the still more primitive anxieties of part object relationships. In fact I consider the
latter to contain the ultimate sources of all group behaviour' (p. 189). In Bion's view,
then, what matters in individual and group behaviour is more primitive than the Freudian
level of explanation but it is the same kind of explanation. The ultimate sources of our
distress are psychotic anxieties, and much of what happens in individuals and groups is a
result of defences erected against psychotic anxieties, so that we do not have to
endure them consciously.
Now I have to say that I have come to agree with them, yet I do not
feel that I have disappeared up my own fundament. I have come to agree with them because
of my experiences in analysis, in groups and, most importantly, in my participation on
group relations events in this country and abroad. I believe that explanations at this
level of primitiveness are the only ones which can hope to account or how people behave in
war situations, in racism and as conquerors, i.e., in extremis. I am thinking of
stories from former Yugoslavia, from Argentina under the generals and of accounts of the
conquistadors in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. Does this mean that I agree with
Freud that only psychoanalytic explanations are valid? No, it does not. It leads me to the
concept of overdetermination. If I read a good psychobiography (and there are few), it
will combine deep insight into unconscious processes with familial, local, social,
economic, regional, national, anthropological and other relevant levels of explanation.
There are famous cases of psychoanalytic explanation which are reductionist, for example,
Erik Eriksons gripping book, Young Man Luther (which was made into an equally
gripping play starring the young Albert Finney), which seemed to give us the Reformation
from Luthers bowel troubles. Ragnells The Mind of Watergate, about
Nixons inner world, is not so sweeping, nor is Kakars exploration of the
emotional problems of F. W. Taylor, the founder of scientific management. These balanced
psychoanalytic biographies show that it can be done without succumbing to reductionism.
One way of conceptualising a good integration of psychoanalytic with other forms of
explanation is to look for the congruence between extrapsychic and intrapsychic factors,
as Caroline Garland does when she attributes the intractability of the trauma of disasters
to a homing missile relationship between aspects of the trauma with something in the
victims early experience.
Attempts have been made to achieve too much with psychoanalytic
explanations of large-scale events. That was the problem with Harold Lasswells Psychopathology
and Politics in 1930 and with the school of psychoanalytic political theory which he
created. The public became a rationalisation of the private without asking what social,
economic and cultural forces had sedimented into the unconscious so as to constitute the
private in the first place. There need be no reductionism if we look at the experiential
origins of the inner world, at what I have elsewhere called second nature. Second nature
is not biology; it is deeply embedded in the unconscious. I want to be able to look at the
psychological motivations of world leaders, torturers, people such as Adolf Eichmann,
Robert Maxwell, Howard Hughes, Henry Ford, Woodrow Wilson, Melanie Klein, Donald
Winnicott, Anna Freud, my colleagues, my children, figures in my training organisation, as
well as people I greatly admire such as Lincoln and Mandela, without feeling that I am
traducing their full humanity or removing them from history, culture and politics. I think
Victor Wolfenstein achieves this balanced overdetermination without succumbing to
reductionism at the theoretical level in his Psychoanalytic-Marxism and at the
level of the case study in his biography of Malcolm X, The Victims of Democracy, but
these are rare achievements, requiring profound research and insight. Wolfenstein may be
unique in being trained both as a political historian and as a psychoanalyst. He proves
that it can be done that reductionism can be avoided and that we need not be
swamped by overdetermination.
The danger of being overwhelmed by overdetermination is what I think
has led us to the cynicism of some forms of postmodernism. The subject was seen to be on
the receiving end nay constituted by so many determinations, so many
inscriptions, that there was no substance to have attributes. I think this is the bitter
end of an admirable tradition leading from the critique of ideology to the sociology of
knowledge to structuralism and deconstruction until as it was recently put in a
timely revival of a phrase from Marx all thats solid melts into
air. The original French Idéologues had the profound insight that as they
put it the ideas of science should be subjected to the science of ideas. You could
say that Cabanis and Destutt de Tracy were, early in the nineteenth century, having a
postmodernist insight that scientific discourse is not foundational and that it
should be accountable to philosophical analysis. However, their hegemony was short-lived,
because they, having proudly had Napoleon as a member of their class at the Institute,
fell out with their mentor, and ideology got a bad name from his mockery. You could say
that ideology thereby became ideological in the sense that it came to be felt that the
refraction of ideas through what came to be called interest, as in special
interests, motives of class and economics and latterly sexism, racism and most recently
heterosexism all these were seen to pollute. I remember an orthodox communist
attacking an early paper of mine on this topic, saying that science should be washed again
and again in Persil until it was whiter than white and free from any stain or taint of
ideology. She now embraces the ideas of Donna Haraway (of whom more anon) and still
doesnt have the faintest idea what this debate is about. What it is about is the
social constitution of the categories, valences and meanings of ideas. When Marx and
Engels said that the ruling ideas of a given epoch are the ideas of its ruling class, they
said something we all believe at one level, which is why we speak of Greek science, Renaissance thought, Victorian sexuality, Postmodernist architecture
or the Progressive Era. Things get tough is when you apply this analysis to
concepts which are thought to transcend historical specificity, e.g., scientific ideas or,
come to that, the theory of ideology itself.
However, when you do look at a scientific idea through the lenses of
the history of ideas and (usually separately, as it happens in practice) those of economic
and social determinations, you find that much is explained. In the history of science this
was a raging battle in from about 1930 when Nikolai Bukharin, Boris Hessen and others
brought this idea to London, where it was taken up by people like J. D. Bernal, Joseph
Needham J. G. Crowther and Stephen F. Mason. By the time I heard about this debate in the
1960s there was a conspiracy of silence, broken and then revived by debates around the
Vietnam War and the related cultural cold war. In the meantime, tame versions of the
Marxist thesis had found their way into the sociology of science in the work of Robert
Merton and other functionalist sociologists of science. However, they carefully separated
the context of discovery from the context of justification, something which allowed them
to remain on speaking terms with the Popperians. Ill unpack that. Certain Marxists
came to see science as ideological through and through. This, as the left-wing Marxists,
Lukács and Gramsci, saw very clearly, wreaks havoc with any idea of nature per se.
The concept of nature and all that follows from it in ideas in the science of an epoch, is
a societal category. Science is inside culture, therefore ideological. Lukács had the
touching belief that once we achieve communism, rather as the Bible promises we will no
longer see through a glass darkly and reification will be transcended, a position which
Gramsci and others lampooned. Merton and Co, on the other had, sought to explain the
social forces which led certain thinkers, e.g., Protestant ones in the early Royal
Society, to ask of nature what they did, though they carefully separated the understanding
of the origins of the questions from the validity of the answers (which is why the
Popperians did not eat them alive). In the 1960 and 1970s people like Habermas, Alvin
Gouldner, Paul Feyerabend and the members of the Radial Science Collective, drawing on the
ideas of the early Marx, Lukács, Gramsci and especially Herbert Marcuse, pushed the
ideological constitution of scientific ideas, including the context of justification, to
the limit and found no limit. This tradition has its apolitical side in the work of the
people around the journal Social Studies of Science, and is in alliance with the
anthropology of knowledge in the work of Mary Douglas and those inspired by her essays on
nature. Her book, Purity and Danger, which explores the concepts of pollution and
taboo has, along with Civilization and Its Discontents, been declared one of the
most important books in the world in this century
The Marxist strand has come together with social constructivism in the
history of science and has had its apotheosis in the writings of feminist historians of
science, pre-eminent among them Donna Haraway, whose masterpiece, Primate Visions:
Gender, Race and Nature in the World of Modern Science, is a paradigm case of balanced
overdetermination without reductionism. She has taken a scientific discipline, the study
of primates, and has shown how it was constituted by ideological determinations
through and through, in its categories, staff, institutions, patronage, and
findings. This approach is in perfect sympathy with postmodernist epistemology
exemplefied in the work of Richard Rorty, which asserts that truth is made, not found,
that nature is a societal category, that all facts are theory-laden and all theories are
value-laden and constituted within an ideology or world view. Putting this development in
other terms, the sociology of scientific knowledge went from the social construction of social reality to the social construction of all reality - especially nature, including, of
course, human nature.
I commend the work of Donna Haraway to you. I do so not only because we
agree about so much (this is not surprising, since we have been influencing each
others writings for a long time) but because she makes it clear that to go to the
depths of the ideological constitution of a research tradition is not to jettison the
other determinations, especially those which she respectfully calls scientific. That is,
you can be a good scientist and still understand the other determinations of your research
problems, institutionalisation and findings. There need be no stark choice between science
and ideology, between unconscious motivation and socio-political causation. (I should, to
be scrupulous, add that Haraway has an acknowledged blind spot where psychoanalytic
determinations are concerned. She is not opposed to them, just ignorant)
I have left Descartes until last. I have least to say about Cartesian
dualism as an exemplar of philosophical analysis. Philosophy is, of course, amenable to
all of the alternative forms of explanation biological, ideological and
psychoanalytic. I have just ordered Stephen Gaukrogers new biography of Descartes in
the hope of learning about some of them. In my experience, the distinction between mind
and body, between what Descartes called extended substances and thinking substances, is
one of the deepest ones in our world view, as refractory to transcendence as the related
one between subject and object. Organismic thinking and phenomenology have tried and tried
to go beyond ontological dualism, just as materialist reductionism has tried to abrogate
thinking substances or demote thought to an epiphenomenon or dissolve it into that
wonderful all-purpose solvent which tried to fuse biology and the human sciences
throughout the first half of this century - the wonderfully question-begging concept of
function. I dont think the effort to solve the mind-body problem has got
very far, but I confess to not yet having studied the wonderful solution which I am told
has been wrought as a result of the philosophical work of Donald Davidson. What I do know
is that minds and bodies and subjects and objects are pretty constant features of the
modern world view and that when we try to go beyond them, we find them reasserting
themselves. I think Peter Strawson showed that the concept of a person was ontologicaly
prior to those of mind and body and that to consider mind and body as the bottom line
ontologically was not a true reflection of our everyday metaphysics, yet we still operate
with those abstractions in ways which characterise our academic disciplines and concepts,
as well as our everyday speech. There are reductionists who say that one day the language
of information theory will make all this passé. I may be too old to get it.
What I do get, however, is two thoughts. The first is the one with
which I began: that we have more explanations than we need and that we should learn to
live with overdetermination. Dont think I believe that will bring peace, since
fighting over which explanation legitimately occupies a given space gives us the most
acute debates in the allocation of resources. Should the money go on drugs, community care
or psychotherapy? Should we imprison people or re-house them? Should this vacant post go
to a biologist or a social scientist or a hermeneuticist (a question only asked in our
centre, I believe)? I mentioned Peter Barham at the beginning. He says that no matter what
causes schizophrenia, the experiences of people who suffer from it are meaningful and
should be attended to, just as we must become clear that they are not de-mented but
rather relatively incapacitated but still people needing psychological and social succour
with the most precise determination about what they can and cannot manage at the moment.
That is, they must remain subjects, with stories to tell and rights to protect. Biologism
has the besetting side-effect of reifying people.
This takes me to my last point. It is about whats wrong with
reductionism. It is amoral and therefore immoral. Whats wrong with all the
reductionisms I have sketched biological and materialist, psychological and
unconscious, ideological and socio-economic is that they filter out praxis and
replace it with process. They take the relations between people and treat them as if they
were relations between things. This was Marxs definition of fetishism and became
Lukács definition of reification. (If you are wondering how this definition squares with
the psychoanalytic concept of reification, it does so by being a part-object relationship,
treating the partner as an object of repetition-compulsion rather than an object of
affection, a whole object.) Lets look at each reductionism in turn. Biological
reductionism is the easiest. since its advocates simply say that survival of the fittest
is natures way. We usually say that scientific explanations separate facts from
value, but to say that is to misunderstand what happened in the scientific revolution. The
official story is that three out of the four causal factors in the Aristotelian scheme of
explanation the material and efficient and formal causes were retained by
the scientific revolution and that the fourth one, the final cause the telos,
purpose, goal, use - was banished into the realm of mind of man and God. Animals, on the
Cartesian scheme, were pure machines; people were machines with minds. (Descartes would
not have made it in Britain; here animals are given human attributes while people are not
thought to have them.) But I following my great mentors, A. N. Whitehead and E. A.
Burtt do not believe the official story of what happened in the scientific
revolution. I think they made a botch of it with the doctrine of primary and secondary
qualities, the banishment of final causes and the separation of subject and object. I
think they left values, purposes, goals floating about, slipped in here and there, tacit,
implicit, not open to inspection or contestation. What I think putative reductionist
explanations do is to seek to achieve what I have called the naturalisation of value
systems. They say, in effect, there are only my values or those of my class,
gender, caste, nation, race. My values are natures values. Queen Isabella said the
Conquistadors could enslave the natives of the West Indies because they were of a
different order of humanity and, having enslaved them, the Europeans could save their
souls. Hitler could call the Jews subhuman, just as the Americans could so designate the
Gooks in Vietnam. Rockefeller could defend his monopolistic practices as the way to
produce the best way to get and transport oil or produce the American Beauty rose. Various
right wing ideologues can appeal to biology for their social theories which defend
inequalitiy, neatly forgetting as they pull the rabbit out that they stuffed it into the
hat in the first place. So-called scientific Marxists can justify genocide and the Gulag
or the killing fields in the same way - the scientistic necessity for
successful revolution. They call it scientific Marxism. So-called Darwinian psychologists
can do likewise with their theories of sibling rivalry, their courtship rituals, their
food chains, their Malthusian notion of society which makes welfare a mistaken charity,
much as the people about whom Dickens wrote thought, much as the architects of the Great
Famine in Ireland and similar genocide in the Soviet Union when the farms were
collectivised said, much as the modern business man says that it is logical or
even rational when they mean that they are about to cheat you.
The dangers of psychoanalytic reductionism are not so easy to represent
so that their reifying features are clear. In my experience, it is of course essential to
suspend moralism in clinical work. But I also feel that moral categories and discourse
must be re-admitted as the splits are coming to be healed. Otherwise, the mixture which
constitutes the depressive position has no parameters, and depressive guilt has no object,
the pain of existence where we bear lifes vicissitudes has no basis for giving
dignity to suffering. Life would be hedonic, not meaningful.
As I near my conclusion, I want to tell you a story about a group
relations conference I attended where this issue became very stark. For those of you who
have no experience of such conferences, I will mention some of the features as I go along.
The purpose of these events is to create a space where one can think under fire, that is,
think about psychotic anxieties while they are upon one, or, at least, soon thereafter.
Anxieties are deliberately evoked by the ambiguities of certain tasks which are set for
the large group. One is told a task and left to pursue it in such a way that people
exhibit the sorts of basic assumption phenomena which Bion and others have characterised
as paradigmatic of group processes. In the conference in question there was the usual mix
of members some psychotherapists, some from business, some doctors, teachers,
clerics, etc. But there was also a group of South African Christians, and it emerged that
they were from a fundamentalist Protestant sect which had not renounced apartheid (all
this occurred while Mandela was still in prison and the future was exquisitely unclear)
and that one and only one among them was black. There is much I could tell you about this
conference, including the fact that the conference director was a South African, but the
fact on which I want to concentrate is that the conference could not deal with this
situation.
The black, a young woman, was pretty tough and clear about herself. She
got into an alliance with another person who was put off by some of the bullshit rhetoric
and false bonhomie of the large group. It so happens that this person was a white American
Southerner: me. The difference between me and her colleagues who were also her
patrons and bosses and employers was that I had renounced the racism of my
upbringing (which is not the same as being free from racism; in fact it lead to a form of
inverted racism). This woman picked up a cohort of friends, but the main dynamic was one
predicted by Bion: she and I paired and were paired by the groups unconscious
collusion. Some of her new-found friends were Scandinavians who had never known a black
woman and were curious and determined to behave well. Another was also an American but one
who had moved to Germany and had become a psychoanalyst and also had reasons to be seen as
not a racist. Another, with whom I was also in a more intimate alliance was an American
black woman. I am not impugning any these peoples motives, just showing that they
were mixed. We formed a feared group and at one stage provocatively called ourselves
the master race, only to find other groupings calling themselves, Jews,
Gypsies, etc.
What happened in the conference was that all interpretations which bore
on this womans position were kept strictly and anxiously at the level of unconscious
motivation. The real world issues of apartheid and of her position in this fundamentalist
sect simply could not be addressed in any sustained adult way. Nor could she speak her
mind or anyone do so on her behalf for the obvious reason that her livelihood was at
stake. What the conference did was to elect her a sort of idealised mascot of the whole
group whose impossible task was to act on behalf of us all. Just as she was supposed to
embark on this task, there was a violent scene in which a German member of staff was set
upon by a screaming bunch of self-styled anti-Nazis until an Israeli woman started sobbing
and shouting, Not again!.
I could speak much more about this set of events. The conclusion I drew
from extensive discussions with her and from ruminations after the conference was that the
setting of group relations conferences is one which cannot take on board the working
through of social, economic, racial or other real world issues but reduces them all to
unconscious dynamics and idealised, rather tableau gestures and acting out of primitive
phantasies. The liberal values held by practically everyone there could not be drawn upon
and instanced, because we were regressed and in a reductionist space. You could say that
learning from such an experience is the point of a group relations conference, but I would
have liked the group to have been able to have behaved better under fire.
Another example of the explanatory blinkers sometimes worn by
psychoanalysts was a letter written to the press by some eminent analysts and
psychotherapists a few days before the hostilities began in the Gulf War. They cited some
unconscious mechanisms, notably ones involving splitting and projection, and urged the
nations not to succumb to them. In some ways this was a touching gesture, but its
causal analysis left rather a lot to be desired, as far as geopolitical factors such as
oil were concerned. Yet, of course, there are psychoanalytic things to be said
about how we think about Saddam Hussein, Hitler, Idi Amin, Mrs Thatcher, General Pinochet
and Genghis Khan, just as there are about our treatment of Mother Teresa and Nelson
Mandela.
If there was time, I would canvass the burgeoning literature about
other reductionisms, notably that which seeks to deploy Darwinism as a universal
explanation, extending to evolutionary epistemology and, just recently in the hands of
Daniel Dennett, to the point, as he explicitly puts it, of being a universal solvent.
Nothing can contain it. This is the central thesis of his book, Darwins Dangerous
Idea (1995). This book is part of a rapidly-growing genre. A few days after I
wrote about Dennetts book, I saw a message on the internet, referring to a
forty-page bibliography (Cziko and Campbell, 1990), whose co-author described himself in
the following terms: I am a proponent of what I call "universal selection
theory" which makes the claim that ALL forms of adapted complexity from
organisms and their antibodies to scientific theories and technological innovations
emerge from a processes involving blind variation and selective retention. The
occasion of this self-description was an updated version of the bibliography, containing
1100 items, which is available on the internet at
http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/facstaff/g-cziko/stb/
with hypertext links to quotations and other sources on the world wide
web at
http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/facstaff/g-cziko/stb/quotes.html
This way of thinking has grown dramatically since Donald T. Campbell
coined the term evolutionary epistemology in 1974.
Note carefully that a scientific theory is being offered as the basis
for the theory of knowledge.
We have had such ambitious claims on behalf of evolution as an
all-inclusive principle at least since the English evolutionist, Herbert Spencer, wrote
about The Development Hypothesis in 1852 and The Social Organism
in 1860. Indeed, his universal evolutionary formula became a wonderfully vacuous
generalisation: Evolution is an integration of matter and a concomitant dissipation
of motion; during which the matter passes from a relatively indefinite, incoherent
homogeneity to a relatively definite heterogeneity; and during which the contained motion
undergoes a parallel transformation. This was rightly lampooned as gobbledygook, but
Spencer was also given credit in the Dictionary of National Biography in 1912 for
having put together the best synthesis of the knowledge of his times (RMY in Victorian
Values). Two decades later, the American functionalist sociologist, Talcott Parsons,
who was himself no mean purveyor of biological analogies, could ask, Who now reads
Herbert Spencer? I offer this as my last example to show the likely fate of
over-ambitious reductionisms.
I said near the beginning that If I was smart enough I could draw up a
matrix in which each reductionism could claim to explain all of the others, leading to
five complete sets of explanations of any phenomenon. I dont have a very visual
imagination, but perhaps there would be twenty-five boxes with five colours. Each would
seek to colour all the others, in turn, or all at once. I think each should be allowed to
have a go at doing so, while each should be required to get back into its cage at the end
of the exercise. We are all biologically driven, unconsciously motivated, ideologically
constituted, caught up in the categories of philosophical assumptions and born with both
loving and destructive impulses, with the lifes task of trying to bear these
mixtures and make reparation for our destructiveness and achieve depressive guilt and
concern for the object all at the same time.
Two final thoughts about ways of thinking which might help us in
reflecting on these matters. First, I dare say that many of you perked up when I started
to tell a story. It is becoming increasingly clear that story-telling may be the human
matrix within which determinations should appropriately find their due weightings.
Reductionisms dont make good yarns. Second, it has been pointed out to me that one
way of accommodating multiple causation is to think dialectically. I agree, but I confess
that I have seen more programmatic statements about dialectical explanations than I have
seen worked through examples. Both of these modes of accounting for things provide
frameworks for complexity and multi-level causation.
Paper delivered to Centre for Psychotherapeutic Studies, University of
Sheffield, 10 November 1995.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Cziko, Gary A., & Campbell, Donald T. (1990). Comprehensive Evolutionary
Epistemology Bibliography, J. Social and Biological Sciences, 13(1): 41-81.
Rest of bibliography to be added..
© The Author
Address for correspondence 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
email: robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|