Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
THE NATURALIZATION OF VALUE SYSTEMS IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES
by Robert M. Young
Preface
This essay is the result of more than one transformation. I had for
some years intended to write an essay on the functionalist tradition in the human
sciences. I had prepared a draft and amended it a number of times, when I received an
invitation from the Course Team of an Open University course on Science and Belief:
From Darwin to Einstein to contribute a course unit. I set out to adapt my ideas to
this context, but it was not an easy fit. In this re-publication of the essay I have not
deleted the materials strictly relevant to the course rubric and the Self-Assessment
Questions (SAQ) which I found anathema at the time. (I made an attempt to re-absorb
the points I made in them into the text but found that at this distance in time I could
not do so without clumsiness and loss of flow.) I have also not modified the
explaining mode of discourse. Although this material was originally inserted
for pedagogical reasons, it provides a useful way of conveying my historiographic
argument. When I address the student directly, I might just as well be addressing my
professional colleagues in the history of science and of culture.It is very difficult even to begin to cover the relevant issues in the
space allotted to this topic. This means that I will have to sketch some matters and leave
out lots of others in order to focus on some key examples and their interconnections. I
have made the problem worse by persuading the Course Team that my original brief was too
narrow. I was asked to write on 'Religion and the Sciences of Mind' and to include
psychological theories from Darwin to about 1940. I replied that 'religion' should be
broadened to 'values', since the religious response to the problem of meaning and values
in life and nature was being challenged by other approaches, some of which, in turn,
purported to explain religion itself by reference to psychological, social and other
forces. I also argued that 'sciences of mind' was too restricted, since one of the most
striking features of the period is that those 'other approaches' included a wide range of
disciplines which were challenging the claims of religion to provide the most convincing
and satisfying grounding for value systems. These now make up what is called 'the human
sciences' and include in addition to psychology sociology, anthropology,
social psychology, psychoanalysis, psychiatry and numerous sub-disciplines. Behind this argument for a reformulation of the unit was the position
that, as I see it, 'science and belief' becomes a progressively inappropriate way of
framing the developments in the post-Darwinian period. This is the sort of issue which
historians differ over, as do scientists reflecting on their own disciplines. Until
recently, most historians of science have been trained in, and have written on, the
history of the physico-chemical sciences. I would like you to consider the issues in a
different way by reassessing the role of the biological, medical and human sciences in the
foundation of our most basic beliefs. Putting the matter very crudely, the approach to
these issues which was based on the relationship between an individual's religious beliefs
and a Newtonian cosmology and which was accepted in the late-eighteenth and the
early-nineteenth centuries, was being replaced between Darwin's time and the 1930s by a
more social approach rooted in a progressive biological order. As a result of my arguing for a much wider brief it was agreed that I
should treat both secularization and the broad stream of approaches under the title 'The
Naturalization of Value Systems in the Human Sciences', i.e. the process by which other
frameworks were sought to replace spiritual, 'other-worldly', religious explanations of
nature, life and humanity with respect to fundamental values. Before attempting to carry
out that brief, however, I want to reflect a bit more on the rubric of the course. I am
doing this because I think it is important to make you aware of the issues embedded in how
the units have been conceived: the writing of history, like the investigation of nature
and society, involves choices among conflicting values. In different units are
intermingled arguments which stress demarcations between science and belief and others
which point out interactions between them. 'Belief' is also used in senses which are
sometimes ambiguous in their social, political, ethical and religious meanings. This is
not a result of carelessness or muddle but of the compromises involved in writing history
as a group with differing approaches to the relations between science and belief/values.
You, as students, are having to deal with two sorts of unstable basis: in the period with
which the course is concerned, the basis for what is meant by 'belief' was changing; at
the same time, some of those who are contributing to the course tend to think of belief in
primarily religious terms, while others (including me) do not. You will have to thread
your own way in this historical and historiographical labyrinth.
Introduction
I think that at a very deep level the sciences are predicated on value
systems and that they serve particular class interests. This approach isn't merely a quirk
of my historiography or politics. The problem of the source and basis for values is also a
key question, both in the period and in scholarship about the period. The
impact of science on the human sphere earth, life, 'man' (the contemporary term was
characteristically sexist, and it would be anachronistic to alter it), and society
was such that the domains of fact and value became manifestly entangled. How the principal
figures in the history of the debate and the scholars who study it sort out the issues, is
itself part of the problem. As I have said, I cannot thread this labyrinth for you, but I
do want you to know that I know that I am in it, too. Where I think I am is at the point
of view which criticizes scientists and scholars who (more or less self-consciously) have
sought to root their values in the laws of nature. I would prefer to debate values in
terms of the kind of society we want to bring into being and to approach nature as a
complex manifold (i.e., 'having various forms, features, applications' Shorter O.E.D.)
that we labour to shape in our efforts to convert our vision into reality. I'll start by summarizing some of my earlier writings on the subject,
since they form the basis of my approach to the unit. At the beginning of the period we
are considering, the debate about science and belief was occurring at two levels. There
certainly was a conflict between the claims of science and those of religion. My reading
of the literature has led me, however, to the interpretation that the explicit conflict
between science and religion was, and remained, part of a more popular culture, one
which we associate with polemicists on both sides, e.g., T. H. Huxley and Bishop
Wilberforce in 1860; Clarence Darrow and William Jennings Brian in 1925. At another
level, however, there was a subtle accommodation among the intellectual elite, with
enlightened theologians more or less gracefully handing over to the custodians of the laws
of nature the fundamental bases for social order and progress. This is what I argued in an
essay on 'The impact of Darwin on conventional thought' (Young, 1970a). After rehearsing
the 'Darwin v the Bible' version, I pointed out that it is significant that both
Lyell and Darwin were buried with great honour in Westminster Abbey, while one of Darwin's
earliest theological sympathizers, Frederick Temple, became Archbishop of Canterbury. In another essay, 'Natural theology, Victorian periodicals and the
fragmentation of a common context' (Young, 1969) I tried to explore and reflect on the
integrative role which natural theology (investigating the existence and attributes of the
Deity through the study of the phenomena of nature 'the Book of God's Works')
played in the early decades of the nineteenth century. There is evidence in the
periodicals which were read by the Victorian intelligentsia, that natural theology
provided a matrix which kept the issues of nature, life, mind and society in a single
common context of intellectual and cultural life in which science was not separated from
fundamental values. I suggested that one of the concomitants of the development of
evolutionary theory was the break-up of this common intellectual culture and the
fragmentation of the relevant issues into separate disciplines. These, in turn, took up
different aspects of the problem of nature and the place of humanity in it. Clearly, there
were other forces leading to the professionalization of the people who specialized in the
topics which got hived off from the common context. Most historians of science who have
written about these historical changes have treated them largely within intellectual
history. To attempt to relate them to wider socio-economic forces in the decades around
the turn of the twentieth century would use up space at a prodigious rate, and there is no
reliable secondary literature to make the connections for us between, say, the
professionalization of anthropology and the needs of colonial administrators in Britain
(see Stauder, 1974; Gough, 1969; Weber, 1974) or the rise of professional sociology and
the development of a relatively stable industrial democracy in America (see Gedicks, 1975;
Schwendinger and Schwendinger, 1974; Lynch, 1977). Looking at the intellectual changes
from the inside, all I felt able to say in the essay I'm summarizing is that the sorts of
learned disputations across a wide set of issues, which appeared in the most prominent
periodicals and which were kept together for a time in the debates of that remarkable
forum, The Metaphysical Society (see Hutton, 1885) in the post-Darwinian period (1869-80),
ceased to be part of a common context. There are three interpretations which form the basis for my approach in
this essay. First, that issues formerly treated in the domain of natural theology came
progressively to be treated as part of the domain of science. Theological bases for such
debates, where they remained, became increasingly less explicit. This, I take it, is the
meaning of R. H. Hutton's remark on behalf of the theological party in the Metaphysical
Society: 'The uniformity of Nature is the veil behind which, in these latter days, God is
hidden from us. Secondly, that the maintenance and reproduction of the values of the
society as expressed in the periodical literature passed from a common
culture to a set of particular disciplines, each with its own topic and periodical (these
are actual titles of periodicals launched in the period which are still in print): Mind,
Brain, Nature, Man (anthropology). Increasingly specialized writers worked more and
more within developing academic disciplines. The broad issue of 'man's place in nature'
was, for example, particularized in the editorial statement of the first issue of Mind (1876)
as follows: 'MIND intends to procure a decision of this question as to the scientific
standing of psychology' (quoted in Secondary Anthology, 2.2 p. 95). This fragmentation of
topics was occurring in an era of growing professionalization. To make my third basic interpretative point I have to go back before
Darwin, because it would be very misleading to allow you to think that the problems I've
been sketching were kept within theology, geology and general biology until Darwin; that
then came On the Origin of Species, followed by the growth of the human sciences on
a Darwinian foundation. It wasn't that way at all. In 'The role of psychology in the nineteenth-century evolutionary
debate' (Secondary Anthology, 3.2) I tried to show how psychology and other approaches
which we would now include among the human sciences were already providing many of the
materials for the foundation of evolutionary theory itself. An analogous case has been
made about sociology and anthropology by John Burrow in his fine book, Evolution and
Society: A Study in Mid-Victorian Social Theory (1966). He mounts a convincing
argument that Darwin 'was certainly not the father of evolutionary anthropology, but
possibly its wealthy uncle', and he was 'far away while the cradle of evolutionary social
theory was being prepared' on the basis of other intellectual traditions (Burrow, 1966,
pp. 100, 114). Burrow has been criticized for setting Darwinian and other traditions too
starkly in competition and thereby under-estimating their common sources (Young, 1967a).
His main point, however, remains unchallenged: evolutionary human and social science did
not spring directly from the rock of Darwin's theory. Underlying and preceding the
biological conceptions, which many took to provide the foundations of the human sciences,
there were conceptions from psychology and social theory already in place. Instead of a
train of influences like this: ideas from geology,
the study of domestication of animals,
biological taxonomy (classification)
together led to the theory of evolution by natural selection,
which, in turn,
led to evolutionary psychology and social sciences;
instead of this, we have
various theories about mind, brain and society:
Malthusianism,
phrenology,
utilitarianism,
associationism,
neurophysiology,
positivism, statistics,
anthropology
and sociology. These interact with studies of the history of nature and other versions
of evolutionism to produce support for the evolutionism of Chambers (1844), Spencer
(1852), Darwin/Wallace (1858), from which extrapolations were made to humanity and
society.The net result is a more convincing foundation for the human sciences,
but it can hardly be called an independent foundation laid on the bedrock of the
natural sciences as opposed to earlier versions of the human sciences. This is the point to recall that the furore around the theory of
organic evolution was, at bottom, largely about the special places of 'man', the planet
Earth and the history of life. There was a very good reason for being nervous about the
impact of science on religion: it might undermine the foundations of values the
doctrines of transcendent free will, responsibility and the basis for goodness (these were
just the fears expressed by Adam Sedgwick on reading Chambers; see Unit 12, Section 3.1).
The issue is far from being sorted out today. Whence come the values which we set against
the way things are? Religious people say that they come from God, are sustained by
religious institutions, beliefs and practices, are propagated by teachers and are attested
in holy writings. Secularists argue that they come from the hopes generated out of
suffering and from visions of a better life within society itself, and that they are
sustained by ethical beliefs, practices and writings. Radicals and revolutionaries believe
that they are generated from the conflicts and contradictions inherent in the structures
of ownership and social relations, which are basic to class societies, and are sustained
by collective struggle against the existing order. It is worth noting that the Christians
who oppose the absorption of the domain of transcendent values have something in common
with secularists, radicals and revolutionaries: all want questions of values
whether they be seen as God's commandments, ethics or politics to be considered as
such. All prefer to treat evaluative questions directly rather than wrapping them up
in another language or reducing them to problems in science or medicine. Considering an
act sinful, wrong or reactionary, saintly, right or progressive is preferred to using
scientific terms such as correct or incorrect, adaptive or maladaptive, normal or
pathological. The dubious extrapolation of the categories of science into other
fields of knowledge is called scientism (such extrapolations from biology give rise
to biologism). But when we speak of extrapolation from science into other domains,
we also have to ask how the evaluative conceptions got into conceptions about nature in
the first place. When values are taken out of the domain of religion we say that they are secularized. When they are then embedded in conceptions of nature and in scientific concepts, they
are being naturalized. When they are then extrapolated from nature to humanity and
society, the process is scientism. The philosophical position which lends
legitimacy to the process of extrapolating values from the domain of facts (while
obscuring the fact that evaluative conceptions had previously been embedded in the natural
conceptions) is positivism. Positivism claims to separate facts from values and to
treat facts independently from their contexts and meanings and values, but the overall
effect is to sequester the values from open controversy by presenting them as legitimate
extrapolations from the facts. Its contradictory, but there you are...Secularists, radicals, revolutionaries and Christians want to hold out
for a basis for values which is to some degree separate from the existing order of nature
and society. In differing ways and for differing reasons, they want to maintain a
transcendent basis for values, bringing them to nature and society in order to criticize
and change what is. The alternative approach is to argue that the source of order,
progress and goodness is embedded in the laws of nature, life and society, without
granting that that embedding was a process of human interpretation of the richness and
complexity of nature to serve particular interests. The traditions in the human sciences which I shall be sketching adopted
this scientistic strategy on a scale which is so grand that it has become common sense for
most people. Don't be surprised if you often feel lost in the theories and confused about
what is going on. When this happens, read on to my interpretation or stop and return to
the above list of definitions and try to work out which process is going on. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 1 Summarize the main points of the Introduction so far in regard to the
following: (i) How did the role of natural theology change in the nineteenth
century? (ii) How were psychological and social theories related to Darwin's
theory of evolution ? (iii) What were the main changes in the 'human sciences'? (iv) What two strategies were there for determining values? (i) There was a decline in the role of natural theology in maintaining
a sense of the coherence and order of nature and society. (ii) Psychological and social theories played a very significant part
in providing the foundations for evolutionary theory which, in turn, provided firmer
scientific legitimation for the human sciences. (iii) The main changes were: fragmentation of the issues surrounding
human nature and society, concomitant with an increasingly professional treatment by
academic experts working in demarcated disciplines with specialist periodicals.(iv) There was a choice of strategies for determining values: treating
them as transcendent and basing them in religion, ethics, politics; or extrapolating them
from the laws of nature via evolutionary social theory, biological or medical
analogies to apply to human nature and society, uniting secularism, naturalization,
scientism and positivism. ___________________________________________________________
It would be easy to say, after we have canvassed the history of the
naturalization of values in the human sciences, that the story adds up to a considerable
scandal a massive confidence trick. That is exactly how a close observer of
Victorian science, Frederick Engels, described its early stages in 1875:
The whole Darwinist teaching of the struggle for existence is simply a
transference from society to living nature of Hobbes's doctrine of bellum omnium contra
omnes [a war of all against all] and of the bourgeois-economic doctrine of competition
together with Malthus's theory of population. When this conjuror's trick has been
performed (and I question its absolute permissibility... particularly as far as the
Malthusian theory is concerned), and the same theories are transferred back again from
organic nature into history it is now claimed that their validity as eternal laws of human
society has been proved. The puerility of this procedure is so obvious that not a word
need be said about it [Marx and Engels, 1965, p. 302].
That is all very well and salutary, but we are left with the problems
of explaining how so many intelligent people could be so colossally duped for so long and
of how to undo all the harm. However, the issue is not as simple as Engels implies. Although flat
rejection of the theory of organic evolution has lived on into the twentieth century, it
is unlikely that many university students in institutions other than those based on
fundamentalist religious doctrines would reject the theory of evolution outright. I can't
say how many would reject its application to human history and social change. We are left
with a problem of agonizing complexity and of the greatest importance: how to treat values
in a post Darwinian world. That is, now that 'man and all his works' can be treated as
ultimately the product of random mutation and natural selection, what basis is there for
values which cannot be reduced to immutable laws of nature the very slide from
value to fact (or 'ought' to 'is') about which Engels was protesting, leading to the
fatalistic conclusion that 'whatever is, is right'? We want to explain that which it is
appropriate to explain in biological terms but not to become resigned and reductionist
about human purposes, values and struggles for a better world. It is not merely silly or 'puerile' to try to explain human matters in
scientific especially biological terms. It is, however, a very vexed
question to decide when, if at all, it is and when it is not appropriate to do so. This
question is unresolved today, for example, in the wake of the discoveries of molecular
biology about the mechanisms of biological inheritance. The view propagated by that
discipline, of life as 'information', and by sociobiology (with its bid to take over
ethics) leaves the question as open as it was in the immediate wake of Darwinism. I do not
want anything in this essay to be taken to prejudge this question, but I will be trying
very hard to show the consequences of the main forms of the naturalization of value
systems which were, and remain, in vogue. A suggestion about how to approach the disciplines, people and
quotations that follow: I recommend that you make a habit of taking note of terms from the
sciences as you come across them. Here are some of the ones to look for:
adaptive/maladaptive, normal/pathological, adjusted/maladjusted, deviant, abnormal,
psychopathology, social pathology, equilibrium, system, structure, function, organism,
statics, dynamics, survival, fittest, process, morphology. I am sure you will find more.
In conducting this exercise I think you will be struck by the pervasiveness of the
reduction of transcendent ethical, social and political values to scientific concepts. I have chosen to concentrate on those aspects of the human sciences
after Darwin which most dramatically illustrate the attempt to make into natural laws the
values of the prevailing social and political order and rationalize its changing needs.
The main thread of my exposition runs from preparing the ground with a discussion of the
ideas of Herbert Spencer to tracing the development of functionalism in psychology,
anthropology and sociology, along with certain related developments, for example,
behaviourism. Important assumptions which were very influential in the functionalist
social sciences were worked out on the Continent in the work of Max Weber and Emile
Durkheim, whom I discuss briefly. For the most part, however, I am tracing functionalist
thought in Britain and America, where the tradition has been more important. At the end I
have included a very brief section on the applications of this approach in industry and
elsewhere in scientific management, and a section on psychoanalysis and psychotherapy. I
have done this in order to show just how far functionalist thought has penetrated into
applied spheres.Where relevant, I have drawn attention to how the main figures in these
disciplines treat religion, so that my exposition includes descriptions of their ways both
of explaining and of replacing religion. It is important to emphasize that I make no
mention of the traditions in the human sciences which have attempted to avoid the
explanation of psychological and social phenomena in biological, medical or other terms
drawn from science. Anti-scientistic points of view in the study of humankind are not free
from some of the ethical and political criticisms I make of the functionalist and related
positions, but at least they do not seek to end debate by appealing to the laws of nature.
Among the traditions I do not consider are phenomenology, Gestalt theory, existential
psychology, ethnomethodology, symbolic interactionism, and humanistic psychology (McNall
and Johnson, 1975; Attewell, 1974). There are other, more recent developments in the human
sciences which make scientific claims but which do not make the same lavish use of
biomedical and other scientific analogies and reductions. I make no mention of these,
either, for example, structuralism, linguistics, discourse analysis (nor do I define, here
or elsewhere in the unit, terms which I do not propose to discuss). ___________________________________________________________SAQ 2Let me remind you of the point I made in the Preface and earlier in
this Introduction that the problem of the source and basis for values is a key question in
the scholarship about the period, and that I am and you are involved in this
problem. Read through the Introduction again and list what you think are the assumptions
which indicate my position on the question of values. Here is how I would describe my assumptions: (i) that values are transcendent: we bring them to our interpretations
of nature, human nature and society and that it is important to be as open about that as
we can manage to be; (ii) that the wholesale application of biological theories to human
society has had, on the whole, a conservative influence; (iii) that naturalistic ethics are fatalistic, prejudging and severely
limiting our sense of the potential for social change; (iv) that the extrapolation of the categories of science in general to
other domains (scientism) is bad and sequesters from controversy the value systems
embedded in the choice of scientific concepts; (v) that the history of efforts to draw a line between facts and values
has obscured the real values being propagated and that we need to find a different way of
approaching the interpretation and transformation of nature. (This assumption is very much
between the lines. It is not made more explicit here, because the terms of reference of
the course do not invite explicit presentation of unit authors' own views.) (See Young,
1977; Radical Science Journal Collective, 1978; Young 1979, 1979a, 1979b, 1979c, 1979d;
London Labour Process/Left Strategy Group 1979.) ___________________________________________________________
Spencer's social evolutionism
Let's plunge in with a sharp juxtaposition. In spite of Engels's remark
'that not a word need be said' about social Darwinism, he goes on (in the same
letter of 1875 to the Russian sociologist, P. L. Lavrov) to expound an alternative view
demarcating the domain of the human from that of the animal:
The essential difference between human and animal society consists in
the fact that animals at most collect while men produce. This sole but
cardinal difference alone makes it impossible simply to transfer laws of animal societies
to human societies. It makes it possible, as you properly remark, "for man to
struggle not only for existence but also for pleasures and for the increase of his
pleasures, . . . to be ready to renounce his lower pleasures for the highest
pleasure". Without disputing your further conclusions from this I would, proceeding
from my premises, make the following inferences: at a certain stage the production of man
thus attains such a high level that not only necessaries but also luxuries, at first, true
enough, only for a minority, are produced. The struggle for existence if we permit
this category for the moment to be valid is thus transformed into a struggle for
pleasures, no longer for mere means of subsistence but for means of development,
socially produced means of development, and to this stage the categories derived from
the animal kingdom are no longer applicable {Marx and Engels, 1965, p. 303].
As Engels sees it, the self-conscious purposiveness of human production
as a social activity, creating goods beyond those required for animal subsistence, leads
to activities which transcend the categories of the animal kingdom.At the other extreme from Engels's sharp demarcation between the animal
and the human, lies the work of the most influential Victorian social thinker, Herbert
Spencer, whose work stressed that the cosmic and ethical processes are one. In his first
book, published in 1851, with the scientistic title Social Statics, Spencer wrote
the following passages:
We commonly enough compare a nation to a living organism. We speak of
"the body politic", of the functions of its several parts, of its growth, and of
its diseases, as though it were a creature. But we usually employ these expressions as
metaphors, little suspecting how close is the analogy, and how far it will bear carrying
out. So completely, however, is a society organized upon the same system as an individual
being, that we may almost say there is something more than analogy between them. [Spencer,
1851, p. 448] A FUNCTION to each organ, and each organ to its own function, is the
law of all organization. To do its work well, an apparatus must possess special fitness
for that work; and this will amount to unfitness for any other work. The lungs cannot
digest, the heart cannot respire, the stomach cannot propel blood. Each muscle and each
gland must have its own particular nerve. There is not a fibre in the body but what has a
channel to bring it food, a channel to take its food away, an agency for causing it to
assimilate nutriment, an agency for stimulating it to perform its peculiar duty, and a
mechanism to take away effete matter; not one of which can be dispensed with. Between
creatures of the lowest type, and creatures of the highest, we similarly find the
essential difference to be, that in the one the vital actions are severally decomposed
into their component parts, and each of these parts has an agent to itself. In
organizations of another order the same principle is apparent. [Spencer 1851, p. 274] Similarly then as the experiences of all people in all times
experiences that are embodied in maxims, proverbs, and moral precepts, and that are
illustrated in biographies and histories, go to prove that organs, faculties, powers,
capacities, or whatever else we call them, grow by use and diminish from disuse, it is
inferred that they will continue to do so. And if this inference is unquestionable, there
is the one above deduced from it that humanity must in the end become completely
adapted to its conditions unquestionable also.
Progress, therefore, is not an accident, but a necessity. Instead of
civilization being artificial, it is part of nature; all of a piece with the development
of the embryo or the unfolding of a flower. The modifications mankind have undergone, and
are still undergoing, result from a law underlying the whole organic creation; and
provided the human race continues, and the constitution of things remains the same, those
modifications must end in completeness. As surely as the tree becomes bulky when it stands
alone, and slender if one of a group; as surely as the same creature assumes the different
forms of cart-horse and race-horse, according as its habits demand strength or speed; as
surely as a blacksmith's arm grows large, and the skin of a labourer's hands thick; as
surely as the eye tends to become long-sighted in the sailor, and short-sighted in the
student; as surely as the blind man attains a more delicate sense of touch; as surely as a
clerk acquires rapidity in writing and calculation; as surely as the musician learns to
detect an error of a semitone amidst what seems to others a very babel of sounds; as
surely as a passion grows by indulgence and diminishes when restrained; as surely as there
is any efficacy in educational culture, or any meaning in such terms as habit, custom,
practice; so surely must the human faculties be moulded into complete fitness for
the social state; so surely must the things we call evil and immorality disappear; so
surely must man become perfect. [Spencer, 1851, pp. 64-65]
___________________________________________________________SAQ 3List the metaphors, analogies and allusions Spencer uses (or underline
them). What does he think they prove? On reading those passages especially the last you may
well (as I do) feel beaten into submission by the wealth and range of his allusions.
Notice that the first passage occurs nearer the end of the book than the others,
suggesting a move from metaphor and analogy while, in fact, the passages I quoted next
actually occur earlier in Spencer's book and display an orgy of identification of the
human with the biological and physiological. He also slides neatly from learning to
progress, to a remarkably sanguine doctrine of human perfectibility all based on
the theory of the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Evolution is habit writ large. ___________________________________________________________The date of Social Statics is important seven years
before the announcement of natural selection theory in the joint Darwin-Wallace paper of
1858. Of course, Robert Chambers's Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation (see
Unit 12, Section 3.1) and the furore surrounding its evolutionism and the extending of it
to human history had been in the public domain for seven years before Spencer's book
appeared. In 1852. Spencer was to advocate evolution in an essay on 'The Development
Hypothesis' in The Leader, and in 1855 he used the idea of the mechanism of
learning by the repeated association of experiences and extended it (in a less sketchy way
than in Social Statics) from the individual to the race, to account for both
individual development and evolution of species by the inheritance of acquired
characteristics. By 1860 there was no coyness about analogies or metaphors. He discussed
'The Social Organism' in evolutionary terms, freely mixing biological and social language:
Societies slowly augment in mass; they progress in complexity of
structure, at the same time their parts become more mutually dependent, their living units
are removed and replaced without destroying their integrity; and the extents these
peculiarities are proportionate to their vital activities.
These are traits that societies have in common with organic bodies. And
these traits in which they agree with organic bodies and disagree with all other things,
entirely subordinate the minor distinctions: such distinctions being scarcely greater than
those which separate one half of the organic kingdom from the other. The principles of organization are the same and the differences are simply differences of application
[Spencer, 1860, p. 206].
Having established the common principles, Spencer feels able to
pronounce with confidence on social and economic forms particularly the ones which
were in greatest need of justification because of the effects of the industrial revolution
on jobs and the social order:
The doctrine of the progressive division of labour, to which we are
here introduced, is familiar to all readers. And further, the analogy between the
economical division of labour and the "physiological division of labour", is so
striking as long since to have drawn the attention of scientific naturalists: so striking,
indeed, that the expression "physiological division of labour", has been
suggested by it. It is not needful, therefore, to treat this part of the subject in great
detail. We shall content ourselves with noting a few general and significant facts, not
manifest on a first inspection. [Spencer, 1860, pp. 211-12]
___________________________________________________________SAQ 4 What is the interaction between social and biological concepts in the
above passage ? The social concept of the division of labour conjures up the image of a
factory where one person does one operation, another person the next, dividing up work
formerly done by a craftsman into a number of tasks which require much less skill and give
much less satisfaction to the worker. Spencer treats the social concept of division of
labour as the source of the biological conception whereby different parts of the body
perform different physiological functions. The physiological version can then be used as a
scientific anchor and justification for further social applications. ___________________________________________________________Spencer proceeds to develop elaborate analogies between physiological
functions and economic production in which greater division of labour produces superior
commodities which circulate in society, 'just as the circulating mass of nutritive
materials' becomes progressively differentiated and improved in a highly evolved organism
(Spencer, 1860, p. 220). Although Spencer saw his writings as championing the individual against
interference by others or by bureaucracies, his view of life and society was, in the end,
purely adjustive. He defined life itself as 'the continuous adjustment of internal
relations to external relations'. Life, adaptation, the hierarchical division of labour,
progress and evolution became essentially equivalent concepts. His secular, evolutionary
theodicy became: whatever is, is right or will be in due course as the result of
evolution. I am, of course, using 'theodicy' in a metaphorical sense: instead of
justifying the ways of God to man, Spencer is showing the essential harmony between his
highest values and nature (see Unit 1, Section 3.3.2). Once again, as you saw in Unit 2
(Section 2.2.4), Spencer believed in the unity of the ethical and cosmic processes. Much
of his grand, multi-volume Synthetic Philosophy, embracing science, psychology and
ethology (the 'science of' ethics), was aimed at convincing the weary reader that
biological adaptation assured that individualism and the general good were becoming
progressively harmonized by universal including social evolution. Therefore,
legislative, bureaucratic, institutional and state interference were not only unnecessary
but positively harmful, since they might interfere with society's otherwise inevitable
progress. This laissez-faire faith extended to opposing most of the public health and
other warnings to the public which we now take for granted, such as the pure-food laws,
standards of advertising, as well as compulsory education. It is tempting to go on from Spencer to discuss the influence of the
concepts of evolution and survival of the fittest, in their mixed economic and biological
forms, on popular notions of progress and competition. It was taken up in the (misnamed)
movement of 'social Darwinism' and used as an ideological justification of the most
rapacious 'robber barons' in the high tide of individualistic capitalism around the turn
of the twentieth century. The Course Team has decided, however, that it is too large a
topic to handle properly, and that we should not pretend that we can do it any justice in
a small space (see Unit 12, Section 7; Hofstadter, 1955; Josephson, 1934; Semmel, 1960;
Bannister, 1979). Something must be said here, however, about the socio-economic and
intellectual forces which were at work between the period of Spencer's work and the
development of functionalist thinking, since it was social Darwinism which functionalism
was supplanting. The American financiers, Andrew Carnegie of the steel industry and John
D. Rockefeller of the oil industry, were enthusiastic exponents of the application of the
doctrine of 'the survival of the fittest': that open competition favoured the most
deserving. 'Only through pruning', Rockefeller told a Sunday School class, 'could the
American Beauty rose have been developed' (Collier and Horowitz, 1976, p. 887; see also
Hofstadter, 1955, p.45, Bannister, 1979, pp. 134, 268-70, reports that this was, in fact,
said by Rockefellers son, John D., Jr.). This approach was not confined, however, to
popular rationalizations of monopolies and huge fortunes. 'Social Darwinism' is a
misnomer, because it was Spencer's influence, not Darwin's, which played the leading part
in spreading the doctrine. This does not mean, however, that Darwin avoided extrapolations
from his theory to society. Whole sections of The Descent of Man (1871; 2nd
edition, 1874) were straightforward applications of evolutionism to explain, for example,
'superior' and 'inferior' races and individuals. (See chapters 3-6, especially pp. l33-43
and A309 Conflict and Stability in the Development of Modern Europe, 1789-1970, Block
II, Part 1, 'Varieties of social Darwinism'.) Spencers books sold half a million copies in America and his
influence on the founders of academic sociology in that country was enormous. One of them,
Charles H. Cooley, said, 'I imagine that all of us who took up sociology between 1870,
say, and 1890 did so at the instigation of Spencer'. Lester Ward, the first important
American critic of Spencer, observed as late as 1898 that most American sociologists were
'virtually disciples of Spencer' (Gedicks, 1975, p.28; Schwendinger and Schwendinger,
1974, p. 108). Here are some examples of his widespread influence and of the influence of
evolutionism in a wider sense. William Graham Sumner (1840-1910), a disciple of Spencer
who was very prominent in American academic life, was professor of political and social
science at Yale and was most influential in the 1880s. His theory of social evolution
departed in some respects from Spencer's but he consistently appealed to evolutionary
naturalism for its basis. L. T. Hobhouse (1864-1929) was the founder of academic sociology
in Britain and sought to ground in evolutionary theory a belief in progress in the service
of individualism. On the Continent, two Germans used evolutionism as a putative basis for
versions of socialism. Eduard Bernstein (1850-1932) argued that it supported
non-revolutionary, i.e., 'evolutionary socialism', an approach which was influential in
the development of social democracy associated with British Fabianism and the current
Labour Party. Karl Kautsky (1854-1938) drew on Darwinism for the version of 'scientific
socialism' which provided the foundations for the German Communist Party. To complete this
short-list of uses to which evolutionism was put in the political sphere, I should mention
the gentle anarchism of Prince Peter Kropotkin (1842-1921) who interpreted Darwinism as a
basis for co-operation in society (on these figures, see Arato, 1973; Lichtheim, 1961;
Steenson, 1979; Sumner, 1963; Bernstein, 1961; Gay, 1952; Kropotkin, 1902; Woodcock and
Avakumovic, 1950). It is not an exaggeration, therefore, to claim that evolution was taken
up as a rationalization for all sorts of popular movements from anarchism to fascism.
Apart from space limitations, the reason I am not pursuing any of those paths is that I
want to consider the influence of biological ideas in that tradition in the human sciences
which has been most important in twentieth-century Britain and America. What I hope to
have conveyed is not a single, consistent extrapolation from evolutionism but a wide
variety of appeals to nature for ethical, social and political doctrines. If we were
making a detailed study, we would go into the nuances; for example, that Spencer ceased to
believe that perfection would be reached, only constantly approximated, and that Sumner
became increasingly pessimistic about the tendencies of evolution toward degradation. (See
Bannister (1979) chapter 5 for the nuances of Sumner's departure from aspects of and his
growing pessimism.)Most people who were influenced by some version of social Darwinism
were not very careful or precise in their rendering of the issues. They found 'survival of
the fittest' a phrase of Spencer's which Darwin took up useful in making
sense of their world. Many also put an optimistic interpretation on the phrase. For
example, Andrew Carnegies motto was: All is well, since all grows better
(Bannister, 1979, p. 80). This general lumping together of the issues also
found its way into popular expositions of science in the period. In the article on
'Biology' in Chambers Encyclopedia (1882), we find:
For the place vacated by Paley's theological and metaphysical
explanation has simply been occupied by that suggested to Darwin and Wallace by Malthus in
terms of the prevalent severity of industrial competition and these phenomena of the
struggle for existence . . . have thus come to be temporarily exalted into a complete
explanation of organic progress. [Quoted in Bannister, 1979, p. 14]
Before we leave social Darwinism it is worth noting that it is a social
philosophy which is far from dead. An editorial in Computer Weekly (24 Jan. 1980),
for example, comments on the dominant role of IBM as follows: 'The problem of trying to
regulate IBM is that what is good for IBM is in general good for the user, and as the
company becomes more innovative and more competitive that becomes increasingly true. IBM
is an inevitable product of the capitalist system in which survival of the fittest must
always tend toward monopoly.' One more point before we move on to the history of functionalism in the
human sciences. This sort of careless jumbling of issues and rampant extrapolation was
vigorously opposed from within the scientific community by people who were as close to the
development and dissemination of evolutionism as T. H. Huxley and A. R. Wallace. Huxley's
essay on 'Administrative Nihilism' (1871) and his Romanes Lecture on 'Evolution and
Ethics' (1893) were aimed directly at Spencer's ideas. Wallace's writings contained many
essays on the limits of natural selection as applied to man. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 5Review the section on Huxley in Unit 2 (Section 2.3) and that on
Wallace in Unit 12 (Section 5) and make sure you are clear about the bases of their
objections to making extrapolations from organic evolution to society. I won't try to repeat issues which were reviewed in those units. What I
want to stress, however, is that both considered that the basis of values and ethics was
independent of natural selection. Huxley considered them transcendent and part of an
effort to combat the socially harmful effects of the struggle for existence. Wallace
argued that evolution could not account for important mental attributes, and he ended up
with spiritualist elements in his explanation of the sources of values. Huxley was a
liberal, Wallace a socialist. But they were agreed that, as one writer in the Westminster
Review put it in 1886: 'there shall, in spite of Nature, be equal conditions'
(quoted in Young, 1971a, p. 224). ___________________________________________________________Instead of pursuing the public debate on the use of evolutionism in
rather loose ways, I want to turn now to its use in pure and applied fields of academic
disciplines. Evolutionary concepts were combined with others from thermodynamics, physics,
chemistry and medicine and were employed in laying the foundations of the behavioural and
human sciences, which are currently the most reputable and pervasive expressions of belief
in a stable, progressive social order. These developments, it seems to me, led to the
institutionalization of the change from a natural theology to a secular, biologically
based sense of the structure of nature and society from justifying the ways of God
to man to relying on the evolving order of nature, including human nature. At the same
time (and in close relationship with changes in the structure of industry) these
developments were concomitant with a shift from individualistic 'survival of the fittest'
doctrines of social Darwinism to conceptions suited to a less rapidly changing and
rapacious society in the early twentieth century. The earlier period saw the construction
of an industrial base which involved intense competition. After the turn of the century,
the era of managerial capitalism was being established. Technocratic and meritocratic
controls replaced brute force. Power came to be exercised through experts who gained their
positions 'on merit' in a competitive educational system and job market. Social life was
experienced less as a jungle and more as an integrated network of careers. These
developments parallel changes in social theory and social science which I shall outline. Here is how a historian of the changing assumptions of sociology of the
period describes the change:
In the face of severe economic depressions and labour rebellions of
unprecedented scope and violence [in the United States], the ideology of Social Darwinism
and laissez-faire gave way to a new ideology which acknowledged the need for the social
regulation of economic life. The social carriers of this new ideology were
intellectuals, humanitarians, social workers and Protestant clergymen who saw the
possibility of all out class warfare in the growing combinations of capital in the trusts
and monopolies and the growing militance of labour unions and socialist movements. It was
out of this technocratic reform movement that the new discipline of sociology took shape.
[Gedicks, 1975, p. 29]
A new and important group was emerging which has come to be called the
'professional-managerial class' or the 'service class' and which now makes up about a
quarter of the working populations. As radicals see it, the role of this group of experts
is to smooth out, to negotiate, 'to mediate the basic class conflict of capitalist
society and create a "rational", reproducible social order' (Ehrenreich and
Ehrenreich, 1979, p. 19). If space permitted I should also want to look at the development of
primatology, sex research, family studies, and related disciplines in the human sciences
which Donna Haraway has shown to be closely integrated with functionalism under the
guidance and patronage of the Rockefeller Foundation charities. The work of a central
figure in many of these developments, Robert M. Yerkes, links the charitable foundations,
universities, neurophysiology, endocrinology, personnel management, psychopathology,
educational testing, personality studies, and social and sexual hygiene. Yerkes 'saw
himself and his scientific peers working to foster a rational society based on science and
preserved from the old ignorance, embodied especially in religion and politics' (Haraway,
1978, pp. 28, 28n, 40 -41). In an important complementary study, she presents an overview
of the embodiment of value systems in 'The biological enterprise: sex, mind and profit
from human engineering to sociobiology' (Haraway, 1979).
4 Functional psychology and behaviourism
The influence of evolutionism on academic psychology occurred primarily
through the functional school, which was most prominent in America. Before defining the
functionalist approach, I want to say something about its origins, which owed more to
Spencer than to Darwin.___________________________________________________________SAQ 6Look back at Unit 12 to the passages from Darwin's Notebooks (Section
4). Which of his speculations can be said to refer to psychology? Most of them; but the range of his interests in mental and behavioural
phenomena is clear in extracts i, ii, vi, x, xv, xix, where he indulges in bold assertions
of the importance of his theory to metaphysics, comparative psychology and the sources of
intellect. He even speculated at one point that thought could be treated as a secretion of
the brain, just as gravity is treated as a property of matter. This is quoted in 'The role
of psychology in the nineteenth-century evolutionary debate', where it is also pointed out
that Darwin did not pursue these implications very far (Secondary Anthology, 3.2). You
will recall from Unit 12, Section 4 that On the Origin of Species had only one,
cryptic sentence on man. It is preceded by a sentence on psychology which he modified in
later editions to read, Psychology will be securely based on the foundation already
laid by Mr. Herbert Spencer, that of the necessary acquirement of each mental power and
capacity by gradation' (Darwin, 1895, p. 402). ___________________________________________________________Darwin, then, deferred to Spencer in matters of psychology. The
development of functional psychology has other sources as well. It can be traced
indirectly to the use of the concept of 'function' in a psychological (rather than in a
strictly physiological) sense by the phrenologists (see TV 07 Skull). Among direct
influences, Spencer's work was the most important, but it was reinforced by that of
contemporaries who treated mental activity in biological terms (especially Alexander Bain
and G. H. Lewes in Britain; see Young, 1970, chapters 3 and 5). These ideas were taken up
in Cambridge, Massachusetts, in the early 1870s in a discussion group not unlike London's
Metaphysical Society. The difference was that the Cambridge group, the Metaphysical Club,
were much less reserved and sceptical about evolution and even less troubled by
theological issues. They were enthusiastically applying evolutionary ideas to all sorts of
spheres philosophy, social and political theory, jurisprudence, and especially
psychology. The resulting theories were to become pervasive in American intellectual life.
(There is a full discussion of this group and its influence in Wiener, 1949; cf.
Russett, 1976, chapter 3.) They form a loose family under the name 'pragmatism', with
'practice' as the key test of validity or truth. Pragmatists emphasized learning through
doing, adaptation, and a biological version of the 'principle of utility': organisms seek
pleasure and avoid pain. Beliefs and the consequences of actions could be treated as a
generalized version of this basic rule, so that ethics could use as a test the greatest
good of the greatest number. Consequences as experienced, i.e., what happened in practice,
was, once again, the acid test. Functionalism was, in effect, pragmatist psychology. The
philosophical and psychological ideas of the most eminent member of the Metaphysical Club,
William James (1842-1910), were particularly influential in developing pragmatism and
applying it in the psychological sphere. His ideas led John Dewey (1859-1952) to modify
his earlier idealism (see Unit 1, Section 2.2.1) towards a biological view of mind. It was
partly through Dewey's influence on leading psychologists at Chicago, Columbia and Yale
Universities that an explicitly functional psychology came into being. Its identity as a
'school' was developed through debates with the 'structuralist' point of view which was
then prevalent. Structuralism grew out of the European tradition in psychology and was
preoccupied with sensation, perception, intellectual processes. The 'structuralist' point
of view was associated with the German psychologist Wilhelm Wundt ('the father of
experimental psychology') and his Anglo-American disciple, E. B. Titchener. (For details,
see Boring, 1950, chapters 16 and 18.) Structuralist psychologists stressed mental contents and structures at the expense of mental acts and what people and other
organisms do. The polarity, then, was between structure and functions. An idea can
be treated as a mental content in the mental structure called 'intellect'. A structuralist
would be keen to trace the path from sensation to idea. In contrast, 'willing' or
'wishing' is an active process, which a functionalist would be keen to relate to
adaptation to the environment.The influence of James's Principles of Psychology (1890 and
still available in paperback) was decisive in the American debate in propagating an
adaptive and environmentalist approach to psychology. Instead of concentrating on how we
experience sensations, perceptions, conceptions and how we think, the functionalists
concentrated on how we act in our surroundings. As James says in stressing the influence
of Spencer, 'to have brought in the environment as vital was a masterstroke' (quoted in
Young, 1970, p. 195). One sign of how this approach to mental life bore on the
naturalization of values was a further volume by James in which he explores, as a sort of
'natural history' by a psychologist, The Varieties of Religious Experience (1902).
James's study is completely sympathetic and unpolemical, but it is not about the truth of
beliefs; rather, it is about the psychology of belief. Inspired by James's work, Dewey went on to develop a functionalist
psychology which attracted a wide following. He wrote prolifically across a broad spectrum
on education, social psychology, philosophy and industrial democracy. Although he was a
less original thinker than James, he was very effective in getting pragmatism and
functionalist psychology institutionalized in research and teaching, where a whole
philosophy of education came to be based on his ideas of capturing the pupil's interest
and building on that. His ideas are often (I think unfairly) blamed for declining
intellectual standards in American education, for example, the substitution of home
economies and learning to drive a car, for the three 'Rs'. He advocated that once one had
captured the student's interest they should be lured toward difficult subjects. Less
gifted disciples interpreted his ideas of adaptation as 'give 'em what they want; anything
to keep them interested'. (There is a good discussion of this in the section on
Education in a Democracy in Hofstadter, 1963, where the difficulty of applying
the idea of life adjustment is critically examined.) The leading exponent of functional psychology in its narrower sense was
James R. Angell (1869-1949), who went on to become President of Yale. In his essay
delineating 'The Province of a Functional Psychology' (his Presidential Address before the
American Psychological Association in 1906), he traced its ancestry to Aristotle and its
modern expressions to Spencer and Darwin, noting its common roots with pragmatism. Its
approach to mental activity was
... as part of a larger stream of biological forces which are daily and
hourly at work before our eyes and are constitutive of the most important and most
absorbing part of our world. The psychologist of this stripe is wont to take his cue from
the basal conception of the evolutionary movement, i.e., that for the most part organic
structures and functions possess their present characteristics by virtue of the efficiency
with which they fit into the extant conditions of life broadly designated the environment.
With this conception in mind he proceeds to attempt some understanding of the manner in
which the psychical contributes to the sum total of organic activities, not alone the
psychical in its entirety, but especially the psychical in its particularities mind
as judging, mind as feeling, etc. This is the point of view which instantly brings the psychologist cheek
by jowl with the general biologist....
We find nowadays both psychologists and biologists who treat
consciousness as substantially synonymous with adaptive reactions to novel situations.
[Angell, 1907, pp. 444-5, 447]
It is easy to see functional psychologists moving away from the study
of intellect to the consideration of the organism in its environment. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 7 What is this position likely to mean when applied to people's lives? In the case of people, functionalism turned out to mean the study of
fitting in with and succeeding in the family, society and work. The influence of the
functional point of view reflected both the biological and the wider sense of the adaptive
aspect of its assumptions. It led to research in comparative and physiological psychology
and to contacts with general biology. When applied to humans it promoted work in applied
and social psychology and connections with industry, advertising, counselling and
psychotherapy, i.e., various ways of fitting people into jobs, getting them to consume
certain products and promoting psychological and social adjustment. Functional
psychologists were evolutionists in a very broad sense, studying and attempting to develop
techniques for promoting harmony between organisms, including humans, and their
environments. ___________________________________________________________Functionalism did not maintain a separate identity as a school of
thought after 1930. Less than a decade after Angell's manifesto, functionalism was
challenged in an aggressive methodological claim from J. B. Watson (1878-1958), who
asserted that the study of mental functions could not be scientific, because they were not
accessible to controlled scientific experimentation. There is strict continuity in this
tradition: Watson studied under Angell, who, in turn, had been James's pupil and Dewey's
colleague. Watson's first statement of 'Psychology as the behaviorist views it' (1913) was
characteristically forthright and laid the foundations of the 'Behaviourism' of the next
decade, henceforth the dominant American school until the 1960s. Watson began:
Psychology as the behaviorist views it is a purely objective
experimental branch of natural science. Its theoretical goal is the prediction and control
of behavior. Introspection forms no essential part of its methods, nor is the scientific
value of its data dependent upon the readiness with which they lend themselves to
interpretation in terms of consciousness. The behaviorist, in his efforts to get a unitary
scheme of animal response, recognizes no dividing line between man and brute. The behavior
of man, with all its refinement and complexity, forms only a part of the behaviorist's
total scheme of investigation. [Watson 1913, p. 547]
Behaviourism, then, is positivism applied to psychology (see Unit 1,
Section 2.3.1). Just as Watson found it easy to jettison consciousness, he had no place
for instinct. Both mental and the biological centres of humans and other organisms became
irrelevant to the project of conditioning organisms to the requirements of the
environment. Watson's intellectual influence was great, and his methodological innovations
were applied across a wide range of disciplines, such as, 'Don't interpret voters'
attitudes in political science; study their 'voting behaviour". His own academic
career, however, was cut short by a sexual scandal, and he was forced to earn his living
outside the universities. He turned to advertising, and we owe many of the sophisticated
techniques of modern adverts to his application of behaviourist techniques to selling
products (and election candidates) in the media, e.g., the assertive, rapid-fire
repetition of the product's name, coupled with instructions in the imperative mode. He
also lectured from public (non-academic) platforms and wrote in women's magazines. He was
belatedly fêted by the American Psychological Association in 1957, the year before he
died. Watson's most famous claim appears in a course of lectures, published
as Behaviorism (1924):
Give me a dozen healthy infants, well-formed, and my own specified
world to bring them up in and I'll guarantee to take any one at random and train him to
become any type of specialist I might select doctor, lawyer, artist,
merchant-chief and, yes, even beggar-man and thief, regardless of his talents, penchants,
tendencies, abilities, vocations, and race of his ancestors. [Watson, 1924, p. 104]
In one century biologism had moved from the 'innate' talents and
propensities of phrenology (see TV 07) to the pure environmentalism of behaviourism. In
phrenology practically all that matters is the innate mental faculties; in behaviourism,
however, it is the conditioned experience of the organism: one extreme refers all to
biological inheritance, the other to lived experience in the environment. The spirit of Watson's project was carried on inside academic
psychology by B. F. Skinner (1904- ), the psychologist at Harvard who developed techniques
of 'operant conditioning' (especially as a result of rewarding pigeons for performing
desired tasks). He went on to argue that he could 'shape' any behaviour by carefully
building up its elements and arranging the appropriate rewards. Out of this behavioural
technology there have been developed techniques for conditioning mental patients with
token rewards, of treating 'sexual deviation' by aversive (painful) conditioning, and of
teaching by machines. The American Central Intelligence Agency has also funded a
considerable amount of research, including some of Skinner's, for its own purposes.
(Marks, 1979, p. 160. Funding of work by other eminent researchers in the human sciences
is discussed on pp. 147-8, 157, 159 - Eysenck; 160, 187, 188 of Marks's study of CIA
research in behavioural control.)Skinner carried his approach to human relations into the realm of
social engineering by writing a fictional account of a utopian community, Walden Two (1948),
a book in which the question remains unresolved as to what values and what way of life
should be implemented by the behavioural technologists, i.e., who shall programme the
programmers of the community. The question is not entirely hypothetical, since several
communities have been set up on Skinner's model. He took the issue up again two decades
later, and in Beyond Freedom and Dignity (1971) faced head-on the humanistic
objections which had been made to his earlier argument. Rather as Watson had 'solved' the
problems of mind and of innate endowment by jettisoning the concepts, Skinner 'solves' the
problem of freedom and dignity by declaring that these are futile objectives which should
be replaced by 'a technology of behavior', which he believes will eliminate the social
diseases of want, war and illness. Technique is all, and the problem of the basis for
transcendent values remains outside disciplined discourse: 'how' is science; 'why' is
nowhere. Indeed, some of the most striking findings in recent psychology have
come from the work of Stanley Milgram, whose research on Obedience and Authority (1974)
shows that experimental subjects, placed in the right environment in which the authority
of experts is emphasized, will press a button which they believe may deliver a fatal
electrical shock to another subject. The sole reward is the knowledge that they have
faithfully followed the instructions of the scientific expert. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 8How does this research connect with the issues of scientism and the
naturalization of value systems ? Behaviourism has moved from its parent tradition, functionalism. In so
doing it has elevated adjustment into an imperative. The work of Skinner and Milgram
concentrates on the technology of inducing obedience. By means of the biological concept
of adaptation, the social one of adjustment gains legitimacy, and by an easy slide, the
problem becomes one of 'engineering' obedience. Once naturalized, this goal pushes out
others, and scientism generalizes it to make it the goal of social engineering. Other
goals and the debates on them are left with no place in the scientific endeavour. ___________________________________________________________
5 Foundations of functionalist social science: Weber and Durkheim
The theories outlined above pragmatist philosophy, functional
psychology and behaviourist methodology all concentrate on the direct, practical
consequences of what organisms, including human ones, do. They all trace their inspiration
to evolutionism, largely as popularized by Spencerians in the United States. The
experience of the organism-environment interaction is seen by all of these approaches as
the key to learning and progress. These approaches have also been very influential in the
development of Anglo-American social science, especially sociology and social
anthropology. However, the two theorists whose work played the largest role in laying the
foundations of functionalist social science were a German and a Frenchman, Max Weber
(1864-1920) and Emile Durkheim (1858-1917). Their influences extend far beyond their
impact on British and American functionalism, so the story I shall tell here is a very
incomplete one.Weber's work developed in constant interaction with the Marxist
tradition so much so that he has been called 'the bourgeois Marx' to emphasize his
efforts to offer satisfactory explanations within the existing social order of the
phenomena which Marx stresses in his critique of capitalism. Where Marx emphasized the
dependence of the consciousness and values of people on the contradictions in their
socio-economic circumstances, Weber saw intellectual culture as a relatively autonomous
sphere in social life. (For a very clear comparison of Marx and Weber on capitalism, see
Birnbaum, 1953; for a lucid contrast of Marx and Durkheim see Lukes, 1967; for an overview
of Marx, Durkheim and Weber see Giddens, 1971). Weber's position has been most influential in the form of his theory of
the motivating role of the religious ideology of Protestantism in the early development of
capitalism, in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (1905). Like
William James, he treated religion as a topic in the study of motivation and historical
causation and not as a set of beliefs that he was advocating. Where Spencer concentrated
on tracing a natural basis for values and opposed their institutionalization in
bureaucracies, Weber stressed the social aspect of beliefs and saw the bureaucratic
state as a precondition for capitalism. That is, he thought that the sorts of guarantees
Spencer sought in organic processes should properly be referred to the very social
institutions Spencer anathematized. Although Weber was explicitly opposed to explaining
social phenomena in biological terms, his theories nevertheless became potent tools in the
hands of those who interpreted societies in terms of organic analogies. His position had
the same effect as the one examined above under behaviourism, since it sequestered the
basis for values from the problem of how to maintain the social order, a problem which he
treated in technical terms. Weber was taking this line in reaction to positions which were
in vogue when he wrote: the conservative derivation of political norms from history by the
organicists of the 'Younger Historical School' in Germany, on the one hand, and the
Marxist view that historical analysis and social values are causally related, on the
other. He argued that the expertise of the social scientist and government bureaucrat
could and should be separated from politics. He believed that values could not be
rationally derived, but once arrived at by irrational processes, their implementation
becomes a technical issue requiring value-neutral experts. The 'rationality' of social
engineering was thus divorced from the goals and the basic structure of society as a whole
and reduced to a much narrower sort of thinking, a 'technological rationality'. In Weber's
theory, science is concerned with the analysis, and bureaucracy with the implementation,
of values and goals which are given by the system and which are not themselves subject to
critical analysis. While the biological reductionists had removed critical evaluations
from the analysis of the social system by rooting them in biological evolutionism, Weber
considered values irrational and beyond the reach of analysis. He turned instead to the
supposedly neutral role of the experts who both study the system and run it. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 9If biological scientism is extrapolation from supposedly biologically
given values, how can Weber's separation of the technical roles of experts from
values be scientism as well? Both take the values as given and so protect them from critical debate.
In both cases the values are given in the social system, and the social scientist
is only concerned about their maintenance. Weber's scientism was at a different level from
that of organic analogies, but it is scientism none the less. ___________________________________________________________Weber's emphasis on the subjective and irrational aspects of social
life, the conscious intentions of people which embody the social values or goals of the
society, and the apparent separation of fact from value were all taken up by later
functionalists in the service of a theory of social integration and equilibrium based on
'empirically' given norms.In an important critique of the theories of 'Industrialism and
Capitalism in the Work of Max Weber', the Marxist social critic Herbert Marcuse writes,
'His theory of the intrinsic value-freedom, or ethical neutrality, of science reveals
itself as that which it is in practice: an attempt to make science "free" to
accept obligatory valuations that are imposed on it from the outside' (Marcuse, 1968, p.
202). In the applied sphere, the Weberian concept of civil service played an important
part (among many other factors) in giving legitimacy to the image of the obedient,
unassuming, conscientious servant of the state. It is just this willingness for a
bureaucrat to separate the technique and efficiency with which a job is done, from
questions of humanity, responsibility and guilt, which were at the centre of the war
crimes trials at the end of World War II. The most notorious (belated) trial was that of
Adolph Eichmann, who organized the transportation of Jews and others to the Nazi
concentration camps where more than six million people were systematically killed or
worked to death. Eichmann admitted that he did the work but insisted that he was 'not
guilty'. He had done his job conscientiously, he argued, and it was not for him to
question the underlying ethical and humanitarian issues. Indeed, he said he had always
done his best to behave in humane ways and that the guilt belonged to those who had
authority over him, his superiors. (This position is the object of the reflections of the
social philosopher Hannah Arendt in Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of
Evil - Arendt, 1963). I cite this example to emphasize how important the issue
is. The submerging of values from the surface of social decisions can have the gravest
consequences.The other person who was, along with Spencer and Weber, most
influential in the development of functionalist sociology was Emile Durkheim. Like Weber,
he was opposed to Spencer's biological reductionism, but he shared Spencer's concern for
the basis of social integration or solidarity. Another contrast is that Durkheim was a
socialist, whereas Spencer was a radical individualist. Durkheim shared Weber's emphasis
on the role of social norms and causes rather than referring to another,
biological, level to explain human behaviour. He went further and argued for the autonomy
of 'social facts', which he advocated treating as a different level of nature, one which
could not be reduced to individual psychological or biological explanations. But in
rejecting biological reductionism, Durkheim did more than any other academic sociologist
in the functionalist tradition to establish the centrality of biological analogies. His
theories involved a move from the biological concepts of 'adaptive' and 'maladaptive' to
the biomedical ones of 'normal' and 'pathological' along with a crucial conflation of the
concepts of 'norm' and 'normal' (explained in the quotation below). Normative categories
thereby become scientized. In this assumption, that there can be a science of ethics,
Durkheim was in a common tradition with Spencer and with more recent ideas in ethology and
sociobiology. For example, E. O. Wilson, proponent of a biological approach to the human
sciences, writes, 'Scientists and humanists should consider together the possibility that
the time has come for ethics to be removed temporarily from the hands of philosophers and
biologicized' (Wilson, 1975, p. 562; for a collection of readings on the current debate,
see Caplan (1978). Here are some representative passages from Durkheim's The Rules of
Sociological Method (1895) in which his biomedical concepts are apparent:
Briefly, for societies, as for individuals, health is good and
desirable; disease on the contrary, is bad and to be avoided. If, then, we can find an
objective criterion, inherent in the facts themselves, which enables us to
distinguish scientifically between health and morbidity in the various orders of social
phenomena, science will be in a position to throw light on practical problems and still
remain faithful to its own method. [Durkheim, 1895, p. 49] We shall call 'normal' these social conditions that are the most
generally distributed, and the others 'morbid' or 'pathological'. If we designate as
'average type' that hypothetical being that is constructed by assembling in the same
individual, the most frequent forms, one may say that the normal type merges with the
average type, and that every deviation from this standard of health is a morbid
phenomenon.... It is the function of the average organism that the physiologist studies;
and the sociologist does the same. [Ibid., pp. 55-6] The healthy constitutes the norm par excellence and can
consequently be in no way abnormal. [Ibid., p. 58] Now, it is important, from the very beginning of research, to be able
to classify facts as normal and abnormal, save for the few exceptional cases, so that the
proper domains can be assigned to physiology and pathology, respectively. [Ibid., p. 63] The various principles we have established up to the present are, then,
closely interconnected. In order that sociology may be a true science of things, the
generality of phenomena must be taken as a criterion of their normality. [Ibid., pp.
74-75]
...health is something that is defined as inherent in things. For then
the object of our efforts is both given and defined at the same time. It is no longer a
matter of pursuing desperately an object that retreats as one advances but of working with
steady perseverance to maintain the normal state, of re-establishing it if it is
threatened, and of rediscovering its conditions if they have changed. The duty of the
statesman is no longer to push society toward an ideal that seems attractive to him, but
his role is that of the physician: he prevents the outbreak of illnesses by good hygiene,
and he seeks to cure them when they have appeared. [Ibid., p. 75]
___________________________________________________________SAQ 10Underline the biological and medical terms in the above passages. What
do you think happens to political disagreements and non-conformists in this schema?Durkheim candidly translates ethically and politically contested issues
into ones of maintaining status quo, which is taken to be normal if average.
Extreme political dissidence and non-conformity become the object of the physician's
'curative' ministrations. There is, alas, a growing literature on various forms of this
practice, East and West. (See Medvedev, 1971; Goffman, 1968; Kesey, 1972; Fireside, 1980).
His biographer concedes that this approach 'blinded Durkheim to the possibility of real
historical alternatives at any given stage of development' (Lukes, 1973, p. 30). ___________________________________________________________Durkheim saw himself as heir to earlier French advocates of a
biologically based social science, Henri Saint-Simon and Auguste Comte, whose work we
cannot consider here. Saint-Simon (1760-1825) was an extremely important early theorist of
a biological approach to the human sciences, while Comte (1798-1857) was the founder of
positivism. (See the essays on them in Raison, 1969, for a quick introduction. For the
purpose of relating their work to this unit, see Greene, 1959; Manuel, 1956, 1972; Haines,
1978). Although Durkheim was in constant conflict with aspects of Spencer's sociology, at
a deeper level he adopted many of the fundamental concepts which Spencer shared with
Saint-Simon and Comte. The line between biological analogies and biological reductionism
is hard to maintain in the face of page after page of biological terms. The net effect is
to experience the elements and relationships in social relations as pre-given by a
framework which is not open to challenge. Durkheim was a consistently sociological functionalist,
but his concepts at the level of the social were still biological ones. He says, for
example, 'The function of a social fact ought always to be sought in its relation to some
social end' (Durkheim, 1895, p. 111) at the same time that he whole heartedly embraced the
(albeit social) 'struggle for existence'. He concentrated on the contribution of the part
to the whole in maintaining the stability or equilibrium, in explaining The Division of
Labour in Society (1893), a feature which he considered the key to social solidarity.
Primitive societies, he said, were characterized by homogeneity, involving less division
of labour and exhibiting a rougher, mechanical solidarity. Population pressure and
competition led progressively to heterogeneity and greater division of labour in societies
which increasingly exhibited truly integrated, organic solidarity. Homogeneity and
heterogeneity, as you may recall from Unit 2, are familiar terms from Spencer's
'Law of Evolution'. His ideas are retained but expressed in purely social terms:
No doubt the current formula, which defines social life as a
correspondence between the internal and the external milieu, is only an approximation;
however, it is in general true. Consequently, to explain a social fact it is not enough to
show the cause on which it depends; we must also, at least in most cases, show its
function in the establishment of the social order. [Durkheim, 1895, p. 97]
But the language in which social functions get discussed is redolent of
biologism (i.e., scientism using biological concepts):
There are a number of circumstances where different functions enter
into competition. Thus, in the individual organism, during a long fast, the nervous system
is nourished at the expense of the other organs, and the same phenomenon is produced if
cerebral activity develops too considerably. It is the same in society. In time of famine
or economic crisis, the vital functions are obliged, in order to maintain themselves, to
support themselves at the expense of less essential functions. [Durkheim, 1895, p. 271]
___________________________________________________________SAQ 11What's slippery in that analogy?In a famine it is understandable that the body preserves the delicate
brain tissue at the expense of, say, stored fat or the bulk of muscles. Is it so
uncontroversial that, in the analogy, the landowners, factory owners and government (the
'vital functions') should remain well-fed while the peasants and workers (the 'less
essential functions') starve? It is a matter of social and political priorities to define
the 'vital functions' and the 'less essential functions' in a society. Why not share the
food out equally? Then, perhaps, take a poll as to what action to take when supplies run
shorter.___________________________________________________________Biological language is pervasive in Durkheim's writings. Sociology was
concerned with the study of 'social morphology' (forms or structures); the 'pathology' of
the division of labour; and individual anomie (normlessness, cutting one off from
solidarity and likely to lead to suicide, the subject of one of his major works). His
arguments are characteristically conducted in terms of the sort of detailed biological
analogy quoted above. This remained true, even as his views became more traditional and
idealistic. As he moved away from seeing society as a system of organs and functions, his
emphasis on the role of morality and religion and on society as 'a focus of moral life'
remained functionalist: 'Its true function is to create the ideal' (Peyre, 1960, p. 25;
Lukes, 1973, p. 5). Durkheim's last book reflected this increasing emphasis on the role of
ritual in cementing the existing social order. In The Elementary Forms of Religious
Life (1912), he set out to explain religion as a social product which expressed the
character of the social totality. The same thing has to be said of this book as has been
said of those of James and Weber on religion: they are studying it and attempting to
explain religious practices, experiences and influences. The extent to which the claims of
believers may or may not be true is not important to the enquiry in the way that it would
matter to believers. Durkheim considers various 'primitive' forms of worship
animism, naturism, totemism, and the ideas of soul, spirit and gods, along with attitudes
to ritual. In doing so, however sympathetically, he was treating the transcendent as
merely social and was silent about whether or not it could have a divine basis as well. He
was himself a non-believer and was born a Jew. His treatment of religion could be said to
be so tolerant as to be positively harmful:
The most barbarous and the most fantastic rites and the strangest myths
translate some human need, some aspect of life, either individual or social. The reasons
with which the faithful justify them may be, and generally are, erroneous; but the true
reasons do not cease to exist, and it is the duty of science to discover them.
In reality, then, there are no religions which are false. All are true
in their own fashion; all answer, though in different ways, to the given conditions of
human existence. [Durkheim, 1912, pp. 14-15]
Similarly, he in no way foresees the demise of religion. This is not
because of doubts about its eternal truth but because of his view of its social function:
Thus there is something eternal in religion which is destined to
survive all the particular symbols in which religious thought has progressively enveloped
itself. There can be no
society which does not feel the need of upholding and reaffirming at
regular intervals the collective sentiments and the collective ideas which make its unity
and its personality. [Ibid., pp. 474-75]
(Doesn't this remind you of Spencer in Unit 2? A further passage with
Durkheim's views on the relationship between science and religion appears in the Primary
Anthology, item 6j.) Although Durkheim's work was concerned with the social level of
integration and stressed the need for positive norms in individual and social life, he was
accepting the fundamental features of society and only setting out to explain the
contributions of particular social phenomena to the maintenance of the whole. Organic
analogies helped to create a conception of sociology which justified the increasing
division of labour and opposed radical structural change. Spencer had taken for granted
mid-Victorian laissez-faire. Weber's liberalism, in effect, supported the bureaucratic
Prussian state. In his turn, Durkheim was attempting to strengthen the moral solidarity of
the unstable French Third Republic (1870-1909). It was from these highly ideologically
committed sources that the major orientations and assumptions of 'value-free' social
science were selected and, in some cases, reinterpreted. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 12Using examples from the discussion of Weber and the passages quoted
from Weber and Durkheim, find examples of (i) naturalization of values; (ii) scientism;
(iii) positivism. Use the definitions given above (three paragraphs before SAQ 1). What
criticisms have I made of these ways of dealing with values? I have been criticizing, first, the covert packing of values into
social theories by the choice of biological concepts which favour stability, equilibrium,
slow change, and the use of the results to justify particular ethical and social beliefs;
and second, the alleged separation of facts from values, when the values are already part
of the facts. You may or may not agree with the values being propagated (I don't), but it
is important to notice that we are being prevented from having that debate by the way the
issues are formulated. ___________________________________________________________
6 Functionalist anthropology
From the 1920s, Durkheim's work was the single most important
intellectual influence on the originators of functionalist anthropology in Great Britain,
Bronislaw Malinowski and A. R. Radcliffe-Brown. They turned to his theories in reaction
against the dominant late nineteenth-century conception of anthropology (discussed in Unit
12). By the 1920s there was a very strong reaction against the use of biological analogies
to explain away exotic customs. An important concomitant of this abandonment of the
'doctrine of survivals' was the fact that anthropologists began to leave their studies,
their books and their collections of anecdotal evidence and to undertake field trips
involving intensive study of contemporary 'primitive' societies. Three important
theoretical consequences of this fieldwork were: (i) A shift from a licence to explain away, to a passionate desire to
make sense of, and the politico-economic need to control more closely, the relations
between social phenomena in colonial societies (for substantiation see Stauder, 1974;
Bonte, 1974-5; the journal Review of African Political Economy). This led
anthropologists to seek to understand and explain the contribution of apparently exotic
customs to the social system and involved a theoretical revolution away from the doctrine
of survivals and towards functionalism;(ii) The abandonment of the historical dimension of anthropological
explanation which (in different ways) had been central to the work of Spencer, Weber,
Durkheim and the usually unmentioned alternative position Marx and Engels.
Historical explanations had acquired a very bad reputation by the 1920s as a result of
their speculative use by nineteenth-century evolutionist anthropologists, such as E. B.
Tylor and L. H. Morgan; they were replaced by meticulous ethnographic fieldwork among
existing tribal societies;(iii) The consequent need to abandon a unitary model of the history and
structure of humankind and to retreat into a cultural relativism which has only lately
been challenged by anthropologists. They have sought to re-emphasize unity among the
varieties of humankind by moving to a deeper, structural level of analysis of cultural
practices and symbols. Malinowski (1884-1942) was a Pole who spent most of his academic career
at the London School of Economics. It has been argued that the epistemological foundations
of his functionalism were indebted to the pragmatist philosophical writings of C. S.
Peirce and William James (Leach, 1957), but although there are important affinities among
their ideas, Malinowski's most explicit acknowledgements are to Durkheim.Radcliffe-Brown (1881-1955), who was British, had a peripatetic career
until he became Professor of Anthropology at Oxford (1939-48). He traced his own
fundamental conceptions to Montesquieu ('social system'), Comte ('statics' versus
'dynamics'), Spencer (social evolution via diversification and adaptation), and, above
all, to Durkheim (the central concept of 'function'). Malinowski became increasingly concerned with the relations between
social functions and the basic psychological and biological needs of individuals, needs
which he considered to give rise to secondary, instrumental social and cultural
institutions. He was thus, contra Durkheim, reducing the social to the individual
and the individual to biological need. Radcliffe-Brown's analyses continued to emphasize
the role of strictly social elements in maintaining the overall functional unity of highly
structured social systems. He never departed from the Durkheimian conception of the
autonomy of the social from the biological. With these different emphases, Malinowski and
Radcliffe Brown worked out the basic functionalist approach which came to dominate the
British School of social anthropology in the 1940s and 1950s. Together they made
'functionalism' a fighting term (rather as Watson had made 'behaviourism' one in American
psychology) and insisted that studies of contemporary societies conducted according to
this approach could achieve far more than could the simple collection and analysis of
ethnographic facts. Hitherto unnoticed relationships in cultures could help reveal the
integrative character of societies.Malinowski described himself as the 'arch-functionalist' and arrogated
to himself (only half jokingly) the title of 'Founder of the Functionalist School of
Anthropology'. He said that 'the magnificent title of the Functional School of
Anthropology has been bestowed by myself, in a way on myself, and to a large extent out of
my own sense of irresponsibility' (Firth, 1957, p. 11). Those who have rejected
Malinowski's theoretical pretensions have continued to admire his detailed descriptions
and analyses, especially the standards he set for the technique of intensive fieldwork.The most full-blown statement of anthropological functionalism is an
essay by Radcliffe-Brown, 'On the concept of function in social science' (1935), which
appears in the Prlmary Anthology (item 6i) and which you should now read with the
following question in mind. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 13Write down a list of the physical, biological and medical terms
Radcliffe-Brown uses so promiscuously. What is their cumulative effect? If one considers what sorts of terms might go in their place, it is
easy to see how they propagate a particular model of society as stable, without
contradictions and without its priorities and values amenable to public contestation and
collective action for change. The central concepts of 'process', 'structure' and
'function' are applied without any sense of past or future. ___________________________________________________________It would be difficult to overestimate the influence of this approach
over the past half century. The collection in which the essay currently appears is a basic
text for all anthropology students. I bought my copy a decade before writing this unit,
and it was the seventh reprint of the paperback edition. By the mid-1950s it was argued
that all British social anthropology was functionalist, and functionalists held all the
major chairs in the country. Although Radcliffe-Brown said that 'functional unity' was
only an hypothesis and a matter of degree, it increasingly became an assumption which
equated 'is' and 'ought' and begged evaluative and political questions just as neatly (and
circularly) as natural theology and Spencer had done: whatever is, is best. 'How manifold
are thy works, O Lord. In wisdom hast thou made them all', says the Psalmist. It could be
argued, for example, that suicide is functional, because it reduces conflict between the
individual and society. Indeed, Audrey Richards reports that
...the belief in the importance of every institution within a culture
to the continued existence of that culture led to the charge, often made by [colonial]
administrators, that functional anthropologists were not prepared to allow for any change
in the tribes they were studying. Field-workers were even suspected of supporting ritual
murders or cannibalism on the ground that in some way or other they contributed to
"tribal integration". [Richards, 1957, p. 19]
When working with colonial administrators, anthropologists could help
to rationalize policy and provide advice for, and in some cases work directly in, the
organization of economic exploitation and counter-insurgency (See Horowitz, 1967; Asad,
l973; Hymes, 1974, especially Part III: 'Studying Dominated Cultures'). Much of the criticism of functional anthropology has been directed at
its almost exclusive concentration on 'integration', 'dynamic equilibrium' and 'organismic
holism' concepts which stress the coherence, stability and balance of social
forces. Its followers have paid relatively little attention to change, conflict and to the
contradictions inherent in social life and at the interface between socio-economic orders,
for example, when a tribal culture undergoes urbanization and industrialization. This
approach to society is variously attributed to the unintended consequences ('latent
functions' in functionalist jargon; 'false consciousness' in Marxist terms); to the use of
organic analogies in intensive, often myopic studies of small-scale societies, and/or to
deep ideological commitments (see Mills, 1970; Demerath and Peterson, 1967 a very
useful collection; Gouldner, 1971; Goddard, 1972).
7 Functionalist sociology
There have been important interactions between British
functionalist anthropology and American functionalist sociology, but the origins of the
latter can be traced rather precisely to a small group of scholars at Harvard in the
1930s. (The traditional distinctions between 'anthropology' and 'sociology' is that
anthropologists study exotic, 'primitive' societies, while sociologists study 'modern'
ones. In recent times the distinction has broken down, for example, when anthropologists
study modern urban settings.) There is a remarkable account of it by Barbara Heyl in the
Secondary Anthology (3.1) 'The Harvard "Pareto Circle" (the article is not
a set text, but it is highly recommended). Here is my gloss on her story.The members of the group were heirs to the pragmatist tradition and
were influenced by Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown, but the main catalytic influence on
their work was the charismatic personality of an eminent biologist, L. J. Henderson
(1878-1942), who formed a circle of young scholars around himself (my approach to
Henderson is very different from the one taken in Unit 11). He was consciously attempting
to formulate a social theory which could rebut the prevailing liberal and Marxist analyses
of society which were gaining adherents in the depths of the Great Depression of the
1930s. For his main weapon in this battle he chose the writings of the aristocratic and
profoundly anti-democratic French-Italian sociologist, Vilfredo Pareto (1848-1923), whose
theories provided much of the intellectual basis of Italian Fascism. Pareto saw society as
a system of mutually interacting particles which move from one state of equilibrium to
another. Henderson's disciples later recalled that he used Pareto to cast doubt on belief
in any real goodness in people or any validity for liberal, much less socialist, ideas and
traditions. Henderson added a number of thermodynamic, physico-chemical and biomedical
analogies to Pareto's formulations so that the concepts of 'system' and 'equilibrium'
acquired a wide range of allusion. He also wrote sympathetically about nineteenth-century
natural theology as a useful model for studying both biological and physico-chemical
systems in a remarkable book on The Fitness of the Environment (1913).Members of Henderson's circle went on to attain eminence in key
positions and to give the 'right' direction to the growing influence of American social
science. From their beginnings in the avowedly anti-radical 'Pareto Circle' they and their
followers and students have propagated functionalism under the guise of value-free
analysis throughout the social sciences and liberal arts in America. A historian of the
movement claimed (in 1959) that functionalism was synonymous with sociological method. A
decade later it was argued that functionalism was simply a synonym for explicit scientific
analysis in general. We have to grant that its wealth of scientific terms, concepts and
models makes this all too plausible. Functional analyses have been offered to explain all
aspects of society and culture, including the reductio ad absurdum of so describing
social conflict in Lewis Coser's The Function of Social Conflict (1956) and even Revolutionary
Change in Chalmers Johnson's (1966) book of that title. For example, chapter 4 is
entitled 'The Disequilibrated Social System' and chapter 6, 'Measuring Disequilibrium'.
Here is a sample:
Social science can contribute to the avoidance of revolution by
identifying in advance probable future instances of dissynchronization between value
structures and patterns of environmental adaptationthat is, conditions requiring
either politically-sanctioned change or revolutionary change. [Johnson, 1966 p.166]
(For an overview, written from within the disciplines, of the strengths
and weaknesses of functionalism in the human sciences, see Martindale, 1965. For strong
claims on behalf of functionalism, see Davis, 1959.)The work of Robert K. Merton (b.1910 and a member of the 'Pareto
Circle') has been most influential in developing and refining the conceptual aspects of
functionalism and its application to science itself as a topic in sociology. In his
best-known essay, 'Manifest and Latent Functions' (1949), he draws heavily on the
theoretical work of Weber, Durkheim, Radcliffe-Brown and members of the 'Pareto Circle'
(especially Talcott Parsons and Clyde Kluckholn) and buttresses this with lavish
references to analogies from contemporary physiology and biology of internal balance of
'homeostasis' (Cannon). There is hardly any room for the text on the pages where he
appeals to this literature in the footnotes of his book, Social Theory and Social
Structures. I reproduce here two pages of his article::This much is the text of his page 100:
(100) SOCIAL THEORY AND SOCIAL STRUCTUREneutral to their contents, and may serve equally well as containers for
ideological poison or for ideological nectar. THE LOGIC OF PROCEDUREPrevalence of the Functional Orientation
The functional orientation is of course neither new nor confined to
the social sciences. It came, in fact, relatively late on the sociological scene, if one
may judge by its earlier and extended use in a great variety of other disciplines. [fn49]
The central orientation of functionalism expressed
Now there is a line across the page, and the rest of the page
about nine tenths is footnote:___________________________________________________________The footnote begins with two quotations:
"The intensity of the exertions evoked by the national danger far
exceeded ordinary capacities of human beings. All were geared up to an abnormal pitch. Once
the supreme incentive had dis-appeared, everyone became conscious of the severity of the
strain. A vast and general relaxation and descent to the standards of ordinary life was
imminent. No community could have gone on using up treasure and life energy at such a
pace. Most of all was the strain apparent in the higher ranks of the brain workers. They
had carried on uplifted by the psychological stimulus which was now to be removed. 'I can work until I drop' was sufficient while the
cannon thundered and armies marched. But now it was peace: and on every side
exhaustion, nervous and physical, unfelt or unheeded before, became evident."
"In all revolutions there comes a the period of inertia
when the fatigue of the effort compels a pause in the process of innovation. That
period is bound to come with the cessation of hostilities. After a life on the heights
the human constitution seems to demand tranquillity and relaxation. To insist,
in the period of pause that we gird up our loins for a new and difficult journey, above
all for a journey into the unknown, is to ask the impossible.... When hostilities against
Nazism cease, men will want, more than anything, a routine of thought and habit which
does not compel the painful adaptation of their minds to disturbing excitement."
Merton comments (still in the footnote to page 100):
The Gibbonesque passages in the first [quotation] are, of course, by
Churchill, the Winston Churchill between the Great Wars, writing in retrospect about the
aftermath of the first of these: The World Crisis: Volume 4, The Aftermath, (London:
Thornton Butterworth, 1928), 30, 31, 33. The observations in the second [quotation] are
those of Harold Laski, writing during the Second Great War to say that it is the policy of
Mr. Churchill to make "the conscious postponement of any issue deemed 'controversial'
until the victory is won [and] this means . . . that the relations of production are to
remain unchanged until peace comes, and that, accordingly, none of the instruments for
social change on a large scale, will be at the national disposal for agreed
purposes." Revolution of our Time, (New York: Viking Press, 1943), 185, 187,
193, 227-8, 309. Unless Churchill had forgotten his analysis of the aftermath of the first
war, it is plain that he and Laski were agreed on the diagnosis that significant
and deliberately enacted social change was unlikely in the immediate post-war era. The
difference clearly lay in the appraisal of the desiralbility of instituting designating
changes at all. (The italics in both [quotations] were by neither author.)
It may be noted, in passing, that the very expectation on which both
Churchill and Laski were agreed i.e. that the post-war period in England
would be one of mass lethargy and indifference to planned institutional change was
not altogether borne out by the actual course of events. England after the second great
war did not exactly repudiate the notion of planned change.
Now we have another line followed (still on p. 100) four lines of
footnote 49:__________
49. The currency of a functionalist outlook has been repeatedly noted.
Forex ample: "The fact that in all fields of thinking the same tendency is
noticeable, proves that there is now a general trend toward interpreting the world in
terms of interconnection of operation rather than in terms of separate substantial units.
Albert
Now there are a few lines of text on page 101:MANIFEST AND LATENT FUNCTIONS (101) in the practice of interpreting data by establishing their consequences
for larger structures in which they are implicated has been found in virtually all
the sciences of man biology and physiology, psychology, economics and law,
anthropology and sociology. [fn 50] The prevalence of the Another line across the page, and the text of footnote 49 continues,
followed by footnote 50. Please note that this scholarly apparatus of citation and
notation threatens to squeeze the text off the page. It is there to shore up his
sociological functionalism by appealing to the authority of (and famous authorities in)
other disciplines in the physical, biological, medical and social sciences, along with
philosophy of science. Methinks he protests too much: it is rampant scientism, reaching
for the authority of nature to support what are, after, political and social doctrines
which do not have the authority of science as a part of their foundations. This is a
striking example of the naturalization. of value systems.___________________________________________________________[fn 49 contd:]Einstein in physics, Claude Bernard in physiology, Alexis Carrel in
biology, Frank Lloyd Wright in architecture, A. N. Whitehead in philosophy, W. Koehler in
psychology, Theodor Litt in sociology, Hermann Heller in political science, B. Cardozo in
law: these are men representing different cultures, different countries, different aspects
of human life and the human spirit, and yet all approaching their problems with a sense of
'reality' which is looking not to material substance but to functional interaction for a
comprehension of phenomena." C. Niemeyer, Law Without Force, (Princeton
University Press, 1941), 300. This motley company suggests anew that agreement on the
functional outlook need not imply identity of political or social philosophy. [Now we get footnote 50, stuffed to overflowing with authoritative
citations:]50. The literature commenting on the trend toward functionalism is
almost as large and considerably more sprawling than the diverse scientific literatures
exemplifying the trend. Limitations of space and concern for immediate relevance limit the
number of such references which must here take the place of an extended review and
discussion of these collateral developments in scientific thought.For biology, a general, now classical, source is J. H. Woodger, Biological
Principles: A Critical Study, (New York: Harcourt Brace and Co., 1929), esp. 327ff.
For correlative materials, at least the following are indicated: Bertalanffy, Modern
Theories of Development, op. cit., particularly 1-46, 64 ff., 179 ff.; E. S. Russell, The
Interpretation of Development and Heredity: A Study in Biological Method, (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1930), esp. 166-280. Foreshadowing discussions will be found in the less
instructive writings of W. E. Ritter, E. B. Wilson, E. Ungerer, J. Schaxel, J. von
Uexküll, etc. The papers of J. Needham e.g., "Thoughts on the problem
of biological organization," Scientia, August 1932, 84-92 can be
consulted with profit.For physiology, consider the writings of C. S. Sherrington, W.
B. Cannon, G. E. Coghill, Joseph Barcroft, and especially the following: C. S.
Sherrington, The Integrative Action of the Nervous System, (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1923); W. B. Cannon, Bodily Changes in Pain, Hunger, Fear and Rage, chapter
12, and The Wisdom of the Body, (New York: W. W. Norton, 1932), all but the unhappy
epilogue on "social homeostasis"; G. E. Coghill, Anatomy and the Problem of
Behavior, (Cambridge University Press, 1929); Joseph Barcroft, Features in the
Architecture of Physiological Function, (Cambridge University Press, 1934).For psychology, virtually any of the basic contributions to
dynamic psychology are in point. It would not only be low wit but entirely true to say
that Freudian conceptions are instinct with functionalism, since the major concepts are
invariably referred to a functional (or dysfunctional) framework. For a different order of
conception, see Harvey Carr, "Functionalism," in Carl Murchison, ed. Psychologies
of 1930, (Clark University Press, 1930); and as one among many articles dealing with
substantially this set of conceptions, see J. M. Fletcher, "Homeostasis as an
explanatory principle in psychology," Psychological Review, 1942, 49, 80-87.
For a statement of application of the functional approach to personality, see chapter I in
Clyde Kluckhohn and Henry A. Murray, ed. Personality in Nature, Society and Culture, (New
York: A. A. Knopf, 1948), 3-32. The important respects in which the Lewin group is
oriented toward functionalism have been widely recognized. For law, see the critical paper by Felix S. Cohen,
"Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach," Columbia Law Review, 1935,
XXXV, 809-849, and the numerous annotated references therein.For sociology and anthropology, see the brief sampling of
references throughout this chapter. The volume edited by Robert Redfield provides a useful
bridge across the chasm too often separating the biological from the social sciences.
Levels of Integration in Biological and Social Systems, Biological Symposia, 1943,
VIII. For an important effort to set out the conceptual framework of functional analysis,
see Talcott Parsons, The Social System, (Glencoe, Illinois: Free Press, ]951). Thats the end of the example of Robert K. Mertons use of
argument from scientistic authority.Merton's approach remains the most influential in the sociology
and the historical sociology of science. I hope I have shown that the result is a
form of scientism stands in the stead of a critique of the conception of science held by
its practitioners: a scientistic sociology of science. Another member of the 'Pareto Circle', Talcott Parsons (1902-79) was
pre-eminent in developing the implications of functionalism for general theory in
sociology. He acknowledged fundamental debts to our familiar, growing list: Spencer,
Malinowski, Pareto and Henderson, but centres (as does Merton) on the aspects of the
conceptions of Weber and Durkheim which place the concepts of 'norm' and 'system' at the
heart of the problem of social order. Historical and economic factors practically
disappear in his analyses, while systems of subjective values and norms come to the
forefront. In his later work his social analyses were merged with an adjustive
interpretation of unconscious motivation drawn from psychoanalysis (see below, Section 9)
which he subsequently brought back into the context of a biological concept of social
evolution in Societies: Evolutionary and Comparative Perspectives (1966). Notice
the familiar naturalization: from social norms to terms based in psychology and then to
those of evolutionary biology. He employed psychoanalysis as a theory for explaining the
internalization of social controls, the process by which people learn to conform to the
prevailing norms of society. Social evolutionism was promoted from an implicit to an
explicit model to answer the charge that his grand theory of The Social System (1951)
could not deal with social change. The result is that society becomes 'one giant moving
equilibrium'. The study of the mechanics of social integration became the definition of
sociology, and social scientists developed closer and closer links with industry and
government. Following Weber, Parsonian functionalism substitutes the intentions of people,
called 'the actor-situation frame of reference', for the Spencerian 'organism-environment'
one. Here is a sample of the result:
The "dynamic motivational process" of goal-oriented,
role-playing actors interacting in culturally patterned situations which constitute
the independent variables of the system are located in the structural setting, and
the test of their significance is their functional relevance for the maintenance or change
of the system. [Buckley, 1957, p. 25; see also Parsons, 1951, pp. 19-22 and Parsons, 1970
an autobiographical reflection.]
Any departure from established social norms, including radical or
ultra-conservative political activity, is stigmatized as 'deviance', and the labelling of
deviants and the advertisement of their violations of social boundaries is importantly
functional, that is, it helps in 'boundary maintenance'. Actions which challenge the
prevailing norms are, in a crucial conflation, 'abnormal', examples of psychopathology or,
if group behaviour, Social Pathology (Lemert, 1951). Following the Weberian
separation of fact and value, Parsonian theory indulges in such 'descriptions', yet at the
same time does not anywhere bring the prevailing values under critical scrutiny. Many
issues simply never arise. As one critic pointed out,
Conspicuously absent in Parsonian society, or relegated to minor
significance, are violence, coercion, domination, exploitation, scarcity, misery,
contradiction, and irreconcilable conflict.... The very features which Parsons banished
from society... are reasserting themselves with a vengeance. These new developments can
hardly be ignored nor can they be incorporated by Parsonian Theory. [Therborn, 1980, p.
11. See Baritz, 1960; Erikson, 1964; Lemert, 1951; Wootton, 1959]
By the end of the 1950s the second-generation advocates of the
functional point of view felt that they could declare 'the end of ideology' in an era of
consensus politics in America and to a lesser extent in other advanced capitalist
countries in the West. I am referring, particularly, to the American sociologists Edward
Shils. Seymour Lipset and Daniel Bell. (For literature on the 'end of ideology' debate,
see Bell, 1960; Lipset, 1960, chapter 13; MacIntyre, 1971; Young, 1971, pp. 198-201;
Waxman, 1968; Rejai, 1971). It would be worth considering this debate with care, since the
claim that ideologies are passé is another way of claiming that the prevailing value
system is naturalized and no longer amenable to contestation. The heritage of the apologetics of Comte, Spencer, Weber and Durkheim
was declared to be neutral, objective, positive science. Social science was defined as a
combination of problem-solving and social engineering, with no role in making a critique
of existing institutions, practices and values. Its rationalizations were complemented and
generalized in new versions of equilibrium and systems models in cybernetics, operational
research and general systems theory abstract disciplines concerned with
organizational aspects of communication and the control of any phenomena, from gunnery to
stock control in a supermarket, to allocation of world resources or weapons systems. When
science is the basis, the model, the method and the technique, the values of the existing
order of society are veritably naturalized. No perspective is left from which to mount a
critical evaluation. The entire space of reasonable discourse is appropriated.I am no longer surprised to receive this sort of advert for a book
for Edward Goldsmith's The Stable Society: Its Structure and
ControlTowards a Social Cybernetics. 'Today we live in a disintegrating society.
In this thought-provoking book Edward Goldsmith examines a traditional, stable human
society and the social controls which help to maintain its stability. From his examination
a model emerges, complex yet intensely logical. The book is in four parts, based on papers
that have appeared in The Ecologist from 1974-6: 1. Society as a System. 2. The
Family Basis of Social Structure. 3. The Religion of a Stable Society. 4. Science and
Social Control' (The Ecologist Catalogue, 1979).You might think I made all that up in order to knit together all the
issues I've been discussing, but I didn't. My neighbour gave it to me, thinking it might
be just the book for me. If you have found the argument of this unit at all persuasive,
you won't be in a rush to accept the book's approach, except, perhaps as a rationalization
for a prematurely stable social order a case study of functionalism in the human
sciences. Another exponent of this way of thinking, Stafford Beer, argues that the
problems which face humanity are not political or economic but cybernetic (Athanasiou,
1980, p. 31). ___________________________________________________________SAQ 14Where do you think this leaves us in our efforts to find a foundation
in science for social science for what is realistic as a social order to strive for? I think it leaves us much deceived, because it allows us to believe
that we can rest our perplexities on a firm foundation when we are, in fact, on shifting
sands. There is, I would argue, no haven from the open clash of values and interests to be
found in method, rhetoric, analogies, or derivations from biological, medical and
physico-chemical conceptions. Values can neither be put aside or left to speak for
themselves when embedded in naturalized language. They have to be made explicit and spoken
for as such. When it is alleged that facts and values can be separated, close scrutiny
often finds values lurking on the 'fact' side of the fact-value divide. When it is alleged
that values can be derived from natural laws or analogies, we find the pre-existing value
systems have been packed into the very conception of nature which is offered as the
reliable bedrock. Biological models tend to convert contradictions into conflicts,
conflicts into maladaptations or maladjustments, leaving the clear implication that some
process such as therapy or counselling should lead to adaptation or adjustment. This view
of society certainly deserves a hearing, but as long as it is expressed in terms of
'structures', 'functions', 'social organisms', 'equilibrium', its basis in a consensus
model rather than one stressing conflict or contradictions, the real question of what sort
of society one wants to live in never gets raised. The question is somehow 'against
nature', since the existing order is so effectively naturalized. If we can only see it in
those terms, how can we conceive it otherwise and set about changing it? ___________________________________________________________That would be a tidy place to end, but there are two topics which I
think should be considered before concluding. They are dangling here, not because I think
them less important than the ones already considered, but because I could not think of a
way offitting them into the tightly woven set of connections from Spencer to
Parsons. It may be a good thing for them to come at the end, though, since they help to
show how the very general ideas discussed above enter directly into the lives of
individuals at work and when they are troubled enough to seek psychological help. The
first topic is concerned with the application of the human sciences to industry but has
been generalized into a form of social engineering for all settings. The second began in
the clinical sphere as a technique for ameliorating neuroses, but has been extended to the
philosophy of civilization. In the short sections following I can only hint at the sort of
critique a longer presentation would allow.
Taylorism: scientific management
Biologistic ideas of the division of labour have been carried into
the interpretation and organization of factory work in the period around the turn of the
twentieth century in which the products of the first industrial revolution were being
transformed into a more efficient, highly integrated moving assembly. Jobs were analysed
and fragmented in the name of creating structures and functions which contributed to the
smooth physiology of the overall organism. What Spencer had described metaphorically was
put into practice in the re-designing of the purposive movements, handling of raw
materials and use of means of production which make up the labour process of workers.
Conceptions of 'adjustment', 'integration', and 'equilibrium' became the basic assumptions
of research on improving 'efficiency' (itself a concept borrowed from physics) in the
factory. The process began in steel making but was quickly applied to the operation of
machine tools, making armaments and, most productively, in automobile assembly.The father of the application of the assumptions and methods of
functionalist science to the labour process of workers was Frederick W. Taylor
(1865-l915). He was the first 'efficiency expert' and invented the systematic study of
work processes, workers' movements, special tools and precise timing by stop-watch
(perhaps better known as 'time-and-motion' studies).I reproduce here two pages (1426-27) from his classic paper, Shop
Management, published in the Transactions of the American Society of Mechanical
Engineers in 1903:___________________________________________________________
it, one, two or three watches, whose stop and start movements can be
operated by pressing with the fingers of 'he left hand upon the proper portion of the
cover of the note-book without * [see below for asterix footnote] the knowledge of the
workman who is being observed. The frame is bound in a leather case resembling a pocket
note-book, and has a place for the note sheets described. A sketch of this
watch-book is shown in fig. 294. [There is a drawing of an open book with hollowed-out
places for two stop watches.] The operation selected for illustration on the note sheet is
the excavation of earth with wheelbarrows, and the values given are fair averages of
actual contract work where the wheelbarrow man fills his own barrow. It is obvious that
similar methods of analyzing and recording may be applied to ________________________________________________________[This is Taylors (somewhat disingenuous) asterix footnote:]* The writer does not believe at all in the policy of spying upon the
workman when taking time observations for the purpose of time study. If the men observed
are to be ultimately affected by the results of these observations it is generally best to
came out openly, and let them know that they are being timed and what the object of the
timing is. There are many cases, however, in which telling the workman that he was being
timed in a minute way would only result in a row, and in defeating the whole object of the
timing; particularly when only a few time units are to be studied on one mans work
and when this man will not be personally affected by the results of the observations. In
these cases the watch book of Mr. Thompson, holding the watches in the cover, is
especially useful. A good deal of judgment is required to know when to time
openly, or the reverse.
[Now to page 1427:]
work ranging from unloading coal to skilled labor on fine machine
tools.333. The method of using the note sheets for timing a work man is as
follows:After entering the necessary descriptive matter at the top of the
sheet, divide the operation to be timed into its elementary units, and write these units
one after another under the heading "Detail Operations." (If the job is long and
complicated, it may be analyzed while the timing is going on, and the elementary units
entered then instead of beforehand.) In wheelbarrow work as illustrated in the example
shown on the note sheet (Fig. 293), the elementary units consist of "filling
barrow," "starting" (which includes throwing down shovel and lifting
handles of barrow), "wheeling full," etc. These units might have been further
subdivided the first one into time for loading one shovelful, or still further into
the time for filling and the time for emptying each shovelful.334. The letters a, b, c, etc., which are printed, are simply for
convenience in designating the elements.
335. We are now ready for the stop watch, which, to save clerical work,
should be provided with a decimal dial similar to that shown in fig. 295. The method of
using this and of recording the times depends upon the character of the time
observations. In all cases, however, the stop watch times are recorded in the
columns headed "Time" at the top of the right-hand half of the note sheet. These
columns are the only place on the face of the sheet where stop-watch readings are to be
entered. If more
___________________________________________________________Taylor worked in America as a mechanical engineer and was very
influential between 1890 and 1920, by which time his methods were used throughout
industry. His admirers said that his introduction of the stop-watch to the study and
control of the labour process of the industrial worker was 'the greatest economicevent of the nineteenth century'. He was compared with Darwin, and
indeed, he drew heavily on social Darwinist ideas. He saw the factory as an organism and
made the division of labour into a general principle. He broke the task down into the
smallest possible units and separated the mental from the manual aspects, with the
'functional foreman' in charge of the mental aspects and the worker following minutely
detailed instructions for every movement. He demanded complete obedience from workers,
measured their output in tenths of seconds and in terms of horsepower. In return he
delivered considerably higher wages (though they did not rise as much as productivity, so
that profits were proportionately increased more than wages). There was serious resistance to the loss of autonomy and craft skills
which Taylorism (as it came to be called) entailed, but the gains in efficiency, control
over the labour process and wages won out in the long run. This occurred only after much
struggle and even Congressional hearings in Washington over the efficacy of the system and
the conflicts it evoked. Taylor's Principles of Scientific Management (1911) became
the model for the management of other social activities and were applied to the home, to
farms, churches, educational institutions and government. Later versions were applied to
the organization of office work and large bureaucracies, and these 'management sciences'
were also brought in to reorganize British local government and the National Health
Service. 'Efficiency' became the watchword for all spheres of life and work, with
'conception' increasingly separated, and worked out in different departments from
'execution'. Taylor was considered a blunt, tactless man, and his methods reflected
this approach. The next generation of efficiency experts turned to psychology and
sociology and devoted attention to the attitudes of workers. The ideology of scientific
management had to be modified to induce workers to produce willingly, to give up what was
called (by management) 'artificial restriction of output', to achieve in the psychological
realm what Taylor had advocated in the area of manual operations. The problem of
convincing the workers to identify their interests with those of the firm should have a
familiar ring: it is a problem in applied functionalism 'fitting in'. It was a
member of the Harvard 'Pareto Circle', a disciple of Henderson, Elton Mayo (1880-1949),
who did the pioneering research on 'the human and social problems of an industrial
civilization' (these words are in the titles of his books), sorting out the kinds of
praise, understanding, group dynamics and other alterations of the work situation which
would yield greater output. In the decades since the 'human factor' was added to Taylor's
scientific control of movements, there has been an increasing refinement of ways of
achieving 'job satisfaction'. Industrial management came progressively to be based on an
adjustive model drawn from psychotherapy. Mayo led the way in introducing this approach in
an attempt to eliminate the conflicts associated with trade union organization and
resistance. Taylor had allowed no place for trade unionism; Mayo and his successors
learned to live with the unions and elicit their co-operation. Industrial unrest is
treated as a form of maladaptation to the organism of industry. As one consultant put it,
'The industrial labourer does not know that he is emotionally maladjusted, so he
mistakenly attributes his dissatisfaction to his job.' Another pointed out the need to
eliminate the monotony of repetitive, specialized tasks and described socialist or even
anarchist beliefs as 'symptoms' which can arise if this is not done. These examples are
drawn from the literature of the social sciences in industry. The industrial counsellor has the task of discussing with the workers
their 'attitudes towards problems, not the problems themselves'. One consultant put it
this way:
At least half of the grievances of the average employee can be relieved
merely by giving him an opportunity to "talk them out". It may not even be
necessary to take any action on them. All that they require is a patient and courteous
hearing, supplemented, when necessary, by an explanation of why nothing can be
done.... It is not always necessary to yield to the worker's requests in order to satisfy
them. [Baritz, 1960, p. 201]
This is an unusually sanguine expression of a general phenomenon: the
development of various techniques for manipulating people by 'scientifically' manipulating
their motives. It is called 'breaking through the attitude barrier' by increasing 'job
satisfaction', or 'job enrichment' by means of 'worker participation', 'consultation',
'staff councils'. The more workers participate in decisions affecting their welfare, the
more happy and productive they are supposed to become. As one employer, enlightened by the
latest methods of motivational research and personnel management said, 'I don't want you
to do it my way because I say, "Do it my way". I want you to do it my way
because you feel deeply that my way is the best way.' Scientific management and the management sciences are the applied
aspect of the naturalization of value systems in the human sciences. The books available
to all on industrial psychology and industrial relations are explicitly based on the
functionalist human sciences. ___________________________________________________________SAQ 15How does the biological analogy apply in scientific management? The norms and goals laid down by management, and the industrial
conditions on the job are seen as the 'environment' to which the worker has to adapt.
Every task, however routine and subjectively unrewarding, is represented as a part of the
division of labour, and the worker is supposed to be persuaded that it is rewarding to be
making a small but significant contribution to the whole. Rejection of management's
prerogatives militancy, working to rule, strikes and other aspects of worker
resistance finds no constructive place in the functionalist version of the social
organism of the workplace. ___________________________________________________________There are numerous manuals and paperback series spelling out the
procedures for obtaining worker co-operation, for bringing about their consent without the
use of force and without making the real relations of power explicit. The connections
between these manuals and the wider movement of functionalist social science are well
attested.* The ways of representing social relations which were traced in earlier sections
of this unit from Darwin and Spencer through functionalist psychology, anthropology and
sociology are currently being experienced as very material forces throughout contemporary
work and life, since they, literally, lead to the designation of the actions and attitudes
which make up people's work. *There is not space to spell out these connections. For a brief
overview, see Young (1972). More detailed studies are Baritz (1960), Haber (1964). Bendix
(1956), Child (1969), Rose (1975), Braverman (1974), Young (1976), Aronowitz (1978),
Cockburn (1977). On the history of Taylorism, see Taylor (1911, 1947), Kakar (1970),
Nadworny (1955), Aitken (1960), Urwick and Brech (1945, 1946, 1948), Palmer (1975), Mayo
(1933, 1949), Callahan (1962). There are many, many books available in paperback editions
on the station platform book- stalls from which managers commute to the metropolises,
which summarize and apply functionalist management ideas. For example, see Herzberg
(1966), Davis and Taylor (1972), Thomas and Bennis (1972), Warr and Wall (1975). Finally,
there is a very useful, one-volume selection of articles and readings covering these
developments from Taylor to recent times: Tillett, Kempner and Wills (1970).
9 Freud and psychoanalysis
Along with industrial psychology and the social sciences, the most
influential sphere in which biological theories have been employed to provide the basis
for secular theories of human nature and society, is that of psychoanalysis and
psychoanalytic psychotherapy. The origins, assumptions, different schools and
ramifications of psychoanalysis involve an extremely complex set of issues and historical
forces. For our purposes, however, a small number of aspects are most relevant. First,
psychoanalysis was founded, and dominated until his death, by Sigmund Freud (1856-1939)
who spent all but the first four and last two years of his life in Vienna. His training
and approach to the problems of neurotic patients came from Darwinism, clinical medicine,
and physicalist physiology (an approach to bodily functions which was strictly
experimental and was closely allied to conceptions drawn from physics). Freud spent many years in neurophysiological research in the very
successful laboratories of the 'Helmholtz School'. He was inspired by evolutionism (see
Sulloway, 1979), approached the mind in physiological terms drawn from his laboratory
research and went to work as a clinician specializing in the problems of people whose
early life experiences especially in the intense emotional interactions of the
family had led them to have psychological or psychosomatic symptoms for which no
organic cause could be found, yet which were not of the kind which led to a diagnosis of
insanity. Some examples of these symptoms are: severe feelings of inferiority, obsessions,
compulsions, impotence, frigidity, 'hysterical' blindness or paralysis, depression. Freud
combined a long-established theory of psychological functioning, the 'association of
ideas', with an emphasis on the most primitive impulses and conflicts. His technique was
to uncover the underlying sources of the symptoms by requiring the patient to say to a
trained psychoanalyst exactly what came into his/her mind 'free association'.
Strong feelings which reflected important childhood conflicts were projected onto the
psychoanalyst. This process occurred for fifty minutes, several times a week over several
months or years. The aim of this 'talking cure' was to uncover and work through painful
memories which were not normally available to efforts of recall, but which were active in
influencing behaviour and repressed in 'the unconscious', a region of the mind which
contained the most primitive, painful and dangerous impulses, forces and memories. Key elements in Freud's view of the mind and in his therapeutic
approach were: the existence of the unconscious as a repository for primitive and
repressed material; the assumption of mental determinism; the existence and importance of
sexual impulses and conflicts in infancy; and the efficacy of free association with the
psychoanalyst as the person with whom one interacted in working through neurotic
conflicts. He based his approach to psychology on a biological instinct theory which
ultimately came down to two basic forces which he called (i) Eros producing
libido or life enhancing energy, especially including infantile sexuality, and (ii) Thanatos
an aggressive, destructive impulse and a need to return to a state of inertia
or quiescence, which he eventually equated with a death instinct (or 'Thanatos') an
equation which most of his followers have not accepted. Psychoanalysis and the therapies related to it have been very
influential and have alleviated much suffering. My aim is not to pursue those matters but
to consider the two aspects of Freud's thought which are most relevant to the
naturalization of value systems: his pessimism and his views on religion. A third topic is
not about Freud's own work but concerns palliative versions of psychotherapy which have
become a substitute for religion for many people. Freud believed that the progress of
civilization occurred through the control and channelling of Eros by guilt:
...the sense of guilt is an expression of the conflict due to
ambivalence, of the eternal struggle between Eros and the instinct of destruction or
death. This conflict is set going as soon as men are faced with the task of living
together. So long as the community assumes no other form than that of the family, the
conflict is bound to express itself in the Oedipus complex [whereby the child is in
fundamental conflict with the parent of the opposite sex and with the authority of the
father; the resolution of this conflict lays the foundations for the adult conscience], to
establish the conscience and to create the first sense of guilt. When an attempt is made
to widen the community, the same conflict is continued in forms which are dependent on the
past; and it is strengthened and results in a further intensification of the sense of
guilt. Since civilization obeys an internal erotic impulsion which causes human beings to
unite in a closely-knit group, it can only achieve this aim through an ever-increasing
reinforcement of the sense of guilt. What began in relation to the father is completed in
relation to the group. If civilization is a necessary course of development from the
family to humanity as a whole, then as a result of the inborn conflict arising from
ambivalence, of the eternal struggle between the trends of love and death there is
inextricably bound up with it an increase of the sense of guilt, which will perhaps reach
heights which the individual finds hard to tolerate. [Freud, 1930, pp. 132-3]
Freud considers the 'sense of guilt as the most important problem in
the development of civilization' and seeks 'to show that the price we pay for our advance
in civilization is a loss of happiness through the heightening of the sense of guilt'
(ibid., p. 134). He considers the value of civilization an open question and is not put
off by
...the critic who is of the opinion that when one surveys the aims of
cultural endeavour and the means it employs, one is bound to come to the conclusion that
the whole effort is not worth the trouble, and that the outcome of it can only be a state
of affairs which the individual will be unable to tolerate.
...The fateful question for the human species seems to me to be whether
and to what extent their cultural development will succeed in mastering the disturbance of
their communal life by the human instinct of aggression and self-destruction. [Ibid., pp.
144-45]
It is in the light of this weary pessimism that we should see Freud's
views on religion, which he treated as a general version of our deepest hopes, fears and
prohibitions. He was not himself a religious man; nor was he polemically anti-religious.
Rather, in a series of exploratory and reflective essays he considered the psychological
and social sources of religion: Totem and Taboo (1912-13), The Future of an
Illusion (1927), Civilization and Its Discontents (1930), and Moses and
Monotheism (1937). His own view, according to his biographer, was that 'such beliefs
could be fully accounted for by the psychological and historical factors he had
investigated, so that he personally could see no reason for adding to them an external
supernatural one' (Jones, 1957, p. 361). His historical speculations on the origins of
Judaism and, to some extent, of Christianity have not stood up to scholarly scrutiny, but
his psychological analysis has been widely influential. Freud wrote in an early essay, 'I believe that a great part of the
mythological view of the world, which reaches into the most modern religions, is nothing
other than psychological processes projected into the outer world (Freud, 1904;
his emphasis; quoted in Jones, 1957, pp. 352-3). He later wrote, 'Religion is an attempt
to get control over the sensory world, in which we are placed, by means of the wish-world,
which we have developed within as a result of biological and psychological necessities'
(ibid., p. 359). The root of the need for religion lay in the Oedipal, or father, complex
through which every child goes. He traced religion, civilization, law, morality, and the
beginnings of community life to this single source. The tremendous power of religious
feelings lay, he argued, in the 'return of the repressed', powerful emotional conflicts
which were symbolically re-enacted in religious rituals. God is seen as a generalized
representation of the prohibitions and ideals which are gradually internalized as the
child's conscience. This generalization is also related to the individual's helplessness
before nature and culture:
. . . man makes the forces of nature not simply into persons with whom
he can associate as he would with his equals that would not do justice to the
overpowering impression which those forces make on him but he gives them the
character of a father. He turns them into gods, following in this, as I have tried to
show, not only an infantile prototype but a phylogenetic one. [Freud, 1927, p. 17]
Similarly, the precepts of civilization
. . . were credited with a divine origin; they were elevated beyond
human society and were extended to nature and the universe.
And thus a store of ideas is created, born from man's need to make his
helplessness tolerable and built up from the material of memories of the helplessness of
his own childhood and the childhood of the human race. It can clearly be seen that the
possession of these ideas protects him in two directions against the dangers of
nature and Fate, and against the injuries that threaten him from human society itself.
[Ibid., p. l8]
Freud was as eloquent about the psychological origins of, and need for,
religion as Durkheim had been about its social sources and functions:
These, which are given out as teachings, are not precipitates of
experience or end results of thinking: they are illusions, fulfilments of the oldest,
strongest and most urgent wishes of mankind. The secret of their strength lies in the
strength of those wishes. As we already know, the terrifying impression of helplessness in
childhood aroused the need for protection for protection through love which
was provided by the father; and the recognition that this helplessness lasts throughout
life made it necessary to cling to the existence of a father, but this time a more
powerful one. Thus the benevolent rule of a divine Providence allays our fear of the
dangers of life; the establishment of a moral world-order ensures the fulfilment of the
demands of justice, which have so often remained unfulfilled in human civilization; and
the prolongation of earthly existence in a future life provides the local and temporal
framework in which these wish-fulfilments shall take place. Answers to the riddles that
tempt the curiosity of man, such as how the universe began or what the relation is between
body and mind, are developed in conformity with the underlying assumptions of this system.
It is an enormous relief to the individual psyche if the conflicts of its childhood
arising from the father-complex conflicts which it has never wholly overcome
are removed from it and brought to a solution which is universally accepted. [Ibid., p.
30]
___________________________________________________________SAQ 16How does this interpretation of religion relate to the naturalization
of value systems in the human sciences ? Freud is offering a psychological explanation of the security offered
by religious belief in the face of the forces of nature and society as mediated through
the individual's own helplessness in infancy in the family. His language in these passages
is blissfully free from biological reductionism, but notice the evolutionary link in the
above passage ending, 'not only an infantile prototype but a phylogenetic one' (phylogeny
is the evolutionary history of a species). Although not much evidence has been given here,
it is true that Freud rooted his explanations in physiological and biological assumptions
and used the resulting theories to argue that, for example, socialism was a very unlikely
prospect for humankind (Freud, Standard Edition, Vol. 22, pp. 67, 151, 180).
Even so, of the theorists discussed in this unit, Freud was the least inclined to use
biomedical analogies to justify the status quo in society. ___________________________________________________________Within the history of the psychoanalytic movement and related
psychotherapies there have been three main tendencies. The orthodox one following on from
and developing Freud's approach has interpreted civilization as the product of instinctual
renunciation (roughly, 'self-control' and discipline) and treats this as the price of
progress. A second tendency has gone to the other extreme and argues for the removal of
repression as the key to a better world. This approach has led to a tremendous
proliferation of therapies in recent years, loosely referred to as the 'Growth Movement'.
What characterizes them for present purposes is that they have taken on the attributes of
a secular, psychologistic religion and have been described as 'a positive, American form
of Eastern religion' (Kovel, 1978, p. 171). Many ex-radicals from the political movements
of the 1960s have made a way of life out of these therapies, seeking in them the
fulfilment which in former times would be sought in political or religious commitment. For
example, Jerry Rubin, a prominent American protester of the 1960s, says, 'In five years
from 1971 to 1975, I directly experienced est, Gestalt therapy, bio-energetics, rolfing,
massage, jogging, health foods, tai chi, Esalen, hypnotism, modern dance, meditation,
Silva Mind Control, Africa, acupuncture, sex therapy, Reichian therapy, and More House
a smorgasbord course in New Consciousness' (quoted in Lasch, 1979, p. 14). Never
mind the specifics; notice the length and breadth of the list.The third tendency has been the progressive accommodation of
psychoanalysis to the functionalist social sciences discussed in other sections of this
unit. Under the heading of 'ego psychology' or 'the adaptive point of view',
psychoanalysts (mostly in America in the 1940s and 1950s) have taken the edge off Freud's
pessimism, and the fundamental sense of conflict out of his view of human nature. They
have converted his insights into tools for adjustment, a domestication which has earned
them the ire of critics who see in psychoanalysis real promise of contributing to the
revival of a critical debate on conflicting values without mystifying them as laws of
nature (see Marcuse, 1969, especially the Epilogue: 'Critique of Neo-Freudian
Revisionism'; Jacoby, 1977; Schneider, 1975; Rosen, 1978).
10 Conclusion
I have sketched the process of secularization and naturalization of
value systems in the human sciences in three main spheres: (i) grand theory in psychology,
anthropology and sociology and in an even more sketchy, truncated way, (ii) the applied
sphere of industrial psychology and management, and (iii) psychoanalysis and
psychotherapy. In all of these, metaphysical belief, in its religious sense, has been
replaced by a set of scientistic concepts, analogies and reductions which, in turn, are
employed to explain religious belief itself. The sources of transcendent values have
become objects of scrutiny for the sociology of religion, the anthropology of belief
systems and the psychology of faith. In most cases the more personally challenging aspect
of the demands made by ethical beliefs has been replaced by the efforts of the apologists
for a socio-economic order to palliate conflict and head off rebellion and the possibility
of revolutionary change. Religious belief is treated in terms of instinctual and infantile
needs, family dynamics and social cohesion and control. The conclusion I want to draw complements recent work which challenges
the 'conflict thesis' about religion and science (as in AMST 283 Science and Belief:
from Copernicus to Darwin, Unit 1). In the developments I have been discussing, it
could be argued that as science advanced, religion receded. This is true but, as has been
argued in a number of recent writings, only at a superficial level (Young, 1970a; 1973b;
Moore, 1979). There is a deeper continuity. The process of secularization, the development
of a biologistic justification for the status quo, replacing theodicy and altering its
imagery when required for adaptation to a new phase, supports the values of conformity,
adjustment and acceptance in a more fundamental way. The structures and roles of the
existing order of society become embedded in the laws of life, mind and society, and
provide an explanation of belief itself. Not all societies have succeeded in convincing
their populace that the existing regime is synonymous with order, progress and science.
Some of the most turbulent and repressive regimes have failed to achieve congruence
between the official line and the consciousness of the people. For example, the positivist
slogan Ordem e Progresso is the legend on the flag of Brazil (emblazoned on
a banner stretching around the globe); the ruling party in Mexico in the era of Zapata's
peasant rebellion called themselves scientificos; there was a parallel movement in
China, inspired by Spencer and other Western advocates of an optimistic 'science' of
social progress. Yet none of those countries leaps to mind as a model of tranquil
progress. On the whole, however, the social and psychological theories which have
become predominant in the major Western societies have been very successful in propagating
the naturalization of the value system of a rather less rapacious version of the
capitalist mode of production the phase of the socio-economic order of Europe and
North America which replaced social Darwinism in the twentieth century. The change from
'nature red in tooth and claw', to social Darwinism, and on to the domestication of
contradictions into conflicts, and conflicts into maladjustments has not been much
contested in the human sciences. In the teeth of all this at least in North America, Britain,
France, Germany and Italy there have recently emerged a number of attempts to break
out of the biomedical and 'systems' frameworks. Some of these involve a return to an older
and more basic, evangelical religion within a modified framework of pre-Darwinian natural
theology; some turn to mystical and occult practices; others, as I have indicated, make a
religion of expressive therapies. All are signs of serious resistance to the prevailing
palliative nature of the human sciences. The same is true of the revival of political
critiques of, and resistance to, the hegemony of current values and the existing
socio-economic order. It is a problem for the future to grant the place which legitimately
belongs to biological and other scientific explanations of human evolution and of
individual and social development, while at the same time retaining the integrity of moral
and political discourse, the basis for transcendent values and hopes, and the husbanding
of human decency.
References
Publications marked with an asterisk are recommended for further
reading. AITKEN, H. G. J. (1960) Taylorism at Watertown Arsenal, Cambridge,
Mass., Harvard University Press. ANGELL, J. R. (1903) 'The relations of structural and functional
psychology to philosophy', Psychological Review, Vol. 12, pp. 243-71. ANGELL, J. (1907) 'The province of functional psychology, Psychological
Review, Vol. 14 pp. 61-91 (reprinted in Wayne Dennis, 1948, pp. 439-56). ANON. (1876) 'Prefatory Words', Mind, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 1-6.ANON. (1980) 'Trying to control IBM', Computer Weekly, 24
January, p. 2.ARATO, A. (1973-4) 'The Second International: a re-examination', Telos, No. 18, pp. 2-52 (re: Kautsky and scientistic socialism). ARENDT, H. (1963) Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of
Evil, New York, Viking (revised and enlarged edition, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1976). *ARONOWITZ, S. (1978) 'Marx, Braverman and the logic of capital', Insurgent
Sociologist, Vol. 8, Nos. 2 and 3 (Essays on the Social Relations of Work and
Labour) pp. 126-46. ASAD, T. (ed.) (1973) Anthropology and the Colonial Encounter, London,
Ithaca Press. ATHANASIOU, T. (1980) 'The liberty machine', Undercurrents, No.
38 (Feb./Mar.), pp. 28-31. ATTEWELL, P. (1974) 'Ethnomethodology since Garfinkel', Theory and
Society, Vol. 1, No. 2, pp. 179-210. BANNISTER, R. C. (1979) Social Darwinism: Science and Myth in
Anglo-American Social Thought, Philadelphia, Temple University Press. *BARITZ, L. (1960) The Servants of Power: A History of the Use of
Social Science in American Industry, Middletown, Conn., Wesleyan University Press
(reissued New York, Wiley, 1965). BARNES, H. E. (1925) 'Representative biological theories of society', Sociological
Review, Vol. 17, pp. 120-31, 182-95, 294-300. BECKER, H. S. (1963) Outsiders: Studies in the Sociology of
Deviance, London, Collier Macmillan. BECKER, H. S. (ed.) (1964) The Other Side: Perspectives on Deviance, London, Collier Macmillan. BELL, D. (1960) The End of Ideology: On the Exhaustion of Political
Ideas in the Fifties London, Collier-Macmillan. BELL, D. (1976) The Coming of Post-Industrial Society: A Venture in
Social Forecasting, Harmondsworth, Penguin. BENDIX, R. (1956) Work and Authority in Industry: Ideologies of
Management in the Course of Industrialization, New York, Wiley (reissued London,
University of California Press 1974) BERGMANN, G. (1956) 'The contribution of J. B. Watson', Psychological
Review, Vol. 63, pp. 265-76. BERNFIELD, S. (1944) 'Freud's earliest theories and the school of
Helmholtz', International Journal of Psycho-analysis, Vol. 13, pp. 341-62. BERNSTEIN, E. (1961) Evolutionary Socialism: A Criticism and
Affirmation (1899), New York, Schocken Books. *BIRNBAUM, N. (1953) 'Conflicting interpretations of the rise of
capitalism: Marx and Weber', British Journal of Sociology, Vol. 4, pp. 125-41. BONTE, P. (1974-5) 'From ethnology to anthropology: on critical
approaches in the human sciences', Critique of Anthropology, No. 2, 36-67; No. 3,
pp. 1-26. BORING, E. G. (1950) A History of Experimental Psychology, 2nd
edition, New York, Appleton-Century-Crofts. BOWEN, F. (1879) 'Malthusianism, Darwinism and pessimism', North
American Review, Vol. 129, pp. 447-72. *BRAVERMAN, H. (1974) Labour and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation
of Work in the Twentieth Century, London, Monthly Review Press. BROWN, A. W. (1947) The Metaphysical Society: Victorian Minds in
Crisis, 1869-1880, New York, Columbia. BRUNER, J. S. (1957) 'Freud and the image of man', in Nelson (1957),
pp. 277-85.BUCKLEY, W. (1957) 'Structural-functional analysis in modern
sociology', in H. Becker and A. Boskoff (eds.), Modern Sociological Theory in
Continuity and Change, New York, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, pp. 236-59.
BURNHAM, J. C. (1960) 'Psychiatry, psychology and the progressive movement', American
Quarterly, Vol. 12, pp. 457-65. *BURROW, J. W. (1966) Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press. CALLAHAN, R. E. (1962) Education and the Cult of Efficiency: A Study of the Social
Forces that Have Shaped the Administration of the Public Schools, London, University
of Chicago Press. CANNON, W. B. (1932) The Wisdom of the Body, New York, Norton.*CAPLAN, A. L. (1978) The Sociobiology Debate: Readings on the Ethical and
Scientific Issues concerning Sociobiology, with a foreword by E. O. Wilson, London,
Harper and Row. CHAMBERS, R. (1844) Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation (reissued
Leicester University Press, 1969). CHANT, C. and FAUVEL, J. (eds.) (1980) Darwin to Einstein: Historical Studies on
Science and Belief, Longman/The Open University Press. CHILD, J. (1969) British Management Thought: A Critical Analysis, London, Allen
and Unwin. *CHOROVER, S. L. (1979) From Genesis to Genocide: The Meaning of Human Nature and
the Power of Behavioral Control, London, MIT Press. *COCKBURN, C. (1977) The Local State: Management of Cities and People, London,
Pluto. COLEY, N. G. and HALL, V. M. D. (eds.) (1980) Darwin to Einstein: Primary Sources on
Science and Belief, Longman/The Open University Press. COLLIER, P. and HOROWITZ, D. (1976) The Rockefellers: An American Dynasty, New
York, Holt, Rinehart and Winston (reissued, New York, New American Library, 1977). COLLINI, S. (1979) Liberalism and Sociology: L. T. Hobhouse and Political Argument
in England 1880-1914, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. COSER, L. (1956) The Functions of Social Conflict. London, Collier-Macmillan. *CRAVENS, H. and BURNHAM J. C. (1971) 'Psychology and evolutionary naturalism in
American thought, 1890-1940', American Quarterly, Vol. 23, pp. 635-57. DARWIN, C. (1871) The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex, London,
Murray; 2nd edition, 1874. DARWIN, C. (1895) On the Origin of Species by means of Natural Selection, or the
Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life, London, Murray, 6th edition,
with additions and corrections, London, Murray; 1st edition 1859 (reissued in facsimile
New York, Atheneum, 1967). DARWIN, C. (1960, 1961, 1967) Darwin's Notebooks on Transmutation of Species (1837-39), Bulletin of the British Museum (Natural History) Historical Series, Vol. 2, Nos.
2-6; Vol. 3, No. 5. DARWIN, C. (1974) Darwin's Early and Unpublished Notebooks, in Gruber, H. E. and
Barrett, P. H. Darwin on Man, New York, Dutton. DARWIN, C. and WALLACE, A. R. (1858) 'On the tendency of species to form varieties; and
on the perpetuation of varieties and species by natural means of selection', Journal of
the Linnean Society, Vol. 3, p. 45 (full text reprinted in Darwin, C. and Wallace, A.
R., (1958) Evolution by Natural Selection, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
pp. 257-79). *DAVIS, K. (1959) 'The myth of functional analysis as a special method in sociology and
anthropology', American Sociological Review, Vol. 24, pp. 757-72 (reprinted in
Demerath and Peterson (1967), pp. 379-402). DAVIS, L. E. and TAYLOR, J. C. (eds.) (1972) Design of Jobs: Selected Readings, Harmondsworth,
Penguin. *DEMERATH, N. J. M. and PETERSON, R. A. (eds.) (1967) System, Change and Conflict: A
Reader on Contemporary Sociological Theory and the Debate over Functionalism, London,
Collier Macmillan. DENNIS, W. (ed.) (1948) Readings in the History of Psychology, New York,
Appleton-Century Crofts. DRURY, H. B. (1922) Scientific Management: A History and Criticism, New York,
Columbia University Press (reissued, New York, AMS Press, 1968). DURKHEIM, E. (1893) The Division of Labour in Society, (reissued London,
Collier-Macmillan, 1964). DURKHEIM, E. (1895) The Rules of Sociological Method, (reissued London,
Collier-Macmillan, 1964). DURKHEIM, E. (1897) Suicide: A Study in Sociology (reissued London, Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1970). DURKHEIM, E. (1912) The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (reissued New York,
Collier Books, 1961). EHRENREICH, B. and J. (1977) 'The professional-managerial class', Radical America, Vol.
11, No. 2, pp. 7-31; No. 3, pp. 7-22 (reprinted in Walker, 1979, pp. 5-45).
*ERIKSON, E. (1957) 'The first psychoanalyst, in Nelson (1957),
pp. 79101. ERIKSON, K. T. (1964) 'Notes on the sociology of deviance', Social
Problems, Vol. 9, pp. 307 14 (reprinted in Becker, 1964, pp. 9-21). FIRESIDE, H. (1980) Soviet Psychoprisons, London, W. W. Norton. FIRTH, R. (1955) 'Function', Yearbook of Anthropology, pp.
23758. FIRTH, R. (ed.) (1957) Man and Culture: An Evaluation of the Work of
Malinowski, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul. FREUD, S. (1912-13) Totem and Taboo, in The Standard Edition
of the Complete Psycho logical Works of Sigmund Freud, London, Hogarth Press and the
Institute of Psychoanalysis, 24 vols., 1953-1974, Vol. 13, pp. 1-162. (Freud's writings
are available in various editions; many are available in Penguin paperbacks.) *FREUD, S. (1927) The Future of an Illusion, in Standard
Edition, Vol. 21, pp. 5-56. FREUD, S. (1930) Civilization and Its Discontents, in Standard
Edition, Vol. 21, pp. 57-145. FREUD, S. (1933) New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis, in Standard Edition, Vol. 22, pp. 1-182. FREUD, S. (1937) Moses and Monotheism, in Standard Edition, Vol.
23, pp. 1-137.FUHRNAM, E. R. (1978) 'Images of the discipline in early American
sociology', Journal of the History of Sociology, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 91-116. GATEWOOD, W. B. (ed.) (1969) Controversy in the Twenties:
Fundamentalism, Modernism, and Evolution, Nashville, Vanderbilt University Press. GAY, P. (1952) The Dilemma of Democratic Socialism: Eduard
Bernstein's Challenge to Marx, New York, Columbia University Press. *GEDICKS, A. (1975) 'American social scientists and the emerging
corporate economy: 1885-1915', The Insurgent Sociologist, Vol. 5, No. 4, pp.
25-47. *GIDDENS, A. (1971) Capitalism and Modern Social. Theory: An
Analysis of the Writings of Marx, Durkheim and Max Weber, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press.GIDDENS, A. (1978) Durkheim, London, Fontana/Collins. GINSBERG, M. (1961) Evolution and Progress, London, Heinemann. GLUCKMANN, M. (1961) 'Anthropological problems arising from the African
industrial revolution', in Southall, A. W. (ed.) (1961) Social Change in Modern Africa, London, International African Institute Studies, pp. 67-82. GODDARD, D. (1972) 'Anthropology: the limits of functionalism', in
Blackburn, R. (ed.) Ideology in Social Science: Readings in Critical Social Theory, London,
Fontana/Collins, GOFFMAN, E. (1968) Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental
Patients and Other Inmates, Harmondsworth, Penguin. GOLDSMITH, E. (1979) The Ecologist Catalogue, London, The
Ecologist. GOUGH, K. (1969) 'World revolution and the science of man', in Roszak,
T. (1969) pp. 125-44. GOULDNER, A. W. (1971) The Coming Crisis in Western Sociology, London,
Heinemann Educational Books. GREENE, J. C. (1959) 'Biology and social theory in the nineteenth
century: Auguste Comte and Herbert Spencer', in Clagett, M. (ed.) Critical Problems in
the History of Science, Madison, University of Wisconsin Press, pp. 419-46. *HABER, S. (1964) Efficiency and Uplift: Scientific Management in
the Progressive Era 1890-1920, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. HADLEY, A. T. (1909) 'The influence of Charles Darwin upon historical
and political thought' Psychological Review, Vol. 16, No. 3, pp. 143-218. HAINES, B. (1978) 'The inter-relation between social, biological and
medical thought, 1750-1850: Saint-Simon and Comte.' British Journal of the History of
Science, Vol. 11, pp. 19-35. *HARAWAY, D. (1978) 'Animal sociology and a natural economy of the body
politic, Part I: A political physiology of dominance; Part II: The past is the contested
zone: human nature and theories of production and reproduction in primate behavior
studies', Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, Vol. 4, No. I, pp. 21-36,
37-60. *HARAWAY, D. (1979) 'The biological enterprise: sex, mind and profit
from human engineering to sociobiology', Radical History Review, No. 20, pp.
206-37. HEIDEBREDER, E. (1933) Seven Psychologies, New York,
Appleton-Century-Crofts. HELFORD, M. S. (1977) 'T. H. Huxley's "Evolution and Ethics":
the politics of evolution and the evolution of politics', Victorian Studies, Vol.
20, pp. 159-77. HENDERSON, L. J. (1913) The Fitness of the Environment: An Inquiry
into the Biological Significance of the Properties of Matter, New York, Macmillan
(reissued Boston, Beacon Press, 1958). HENDERSON, L. J. (1970) L. J. Henderson on the Social System:
Selected Writings, London University of Chicago Press. HERZBERG, F. (1966) Work and the Nature of Man, New York, World
Publishing.*HEYL, B. (1968) 'The Harvard "Pareto Circle"', Journal of
the History of the Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 4, No. 4, pp. 316-34; also in
Chant and Fauvel (1980).HODGEN M. T. (1936) The Doctrine of Survivals: A Chapter in the
History of the Scientific Method in the Study of Man, London, Allenson and Co.HOFSTADTER, R. (1955) Social Darwinism in American Thought, 2nd
edition, Boston, Beacon Press (cf. Lynch, 1977, who argues that Hofstadter's argument is
based on functionalist premises).HOFSTADTER, R. (1963) Anti-Intellectualism in American Life, New
York, Alfred A. Knopf.HOROWITZ, I. L. (ed.) (1967) The Rise and Fall of Project Camelot:
Studies in the Relationship between Social Science and Practical Politics, London, MIT
Press. HOWARD, D. T. (1927) 'The influence of evolutionary doctrine on
psychology', Psychological Review, Vol. 34, pp. 305-12.*HUTTON, R. H. (1885) 'The Metaphysical Society', The Nineteenth
Century, Vol. 18, pp. 177-96; also in Collie and Hall (1980). HUXLEY, T. H. (1871) 'Administrative nihilism', Collected Essays, 1893,
Vol. 1, pp. 251-89.*HUXLEY, T. H. (1893) Evolution and ethics, Collected
Essays, 1894, Vol. 9, pp. 1116. HYMES, D. (ed.) (1974) Reinventing Anthropology, New York,
Vintage Books.*JACOBY, R. (1977) Social Amnesia: A Critique of Conformist
Psychology from Adler to Laing, Hassocks, Sussex, Harvester.JAMES, W. (1890) Principles of Psychology, 2 vols., New York,
Henry Holt and Co. (reissued New York, Dover Publications, n.d.).JAMES, W. (1902) The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in
Human Nature, London, Longmans, Green and Co. (reissued New York, Modern Library,
n.d.).JOHNSON, C. (1966) Revolutionary Change, Boston, Little, Brown
and Co. (reissued London, University of London Press, 1968). JOHNSON, H. M. (1968) 'Ideology and the social system', in Sills, D. L.
(ed.) International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, New York, Macmillan and
Free Press, Vol. 7, pp. 76-85. JONES, E. (1963-57) The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud, 3 vols.,
London, Hogarth Press (edition cited: New York, Basic Books). JOSEPHSON, M. (1934) The Robber Barons (reissued New York;
Harcourt, Brace and World, 1962).KAKAR, S. (1970) Frederick Taylor: A Study in Personality and
Innovation, London, MIT Press.*KESEY, K. (1972) One Flew over the Cuckoo's Nest, London,
Calder.*KOVEL, J. (1978) A Complete Guide to Therapy: From Psychoanalysis
to Behaviour Modification, Harmondsworth, Penguin.KROPOTKIN, P. (1902) Mutual Aid: A Factor in Evolution, London,
William Heinemann.KRUTCH, J. W. (1953) The Measure of Man: On Freedom, Human Values,
Survival and the Modern Temper, New York, Grosset and Dunlap.LASCH, C. (1979) The Culture of Narcissism: American Life in an Age
of Diminishing Expectations, London, W. W. Norton and Co.LEACH, E. (1957) 'The epistemological background to Malinowski's
empiricism', in Firth(1957), pp. 119-38. LEMERT, E. M. (1951) Social Pathology: A Systematic Approach to the
Theory of Sociopathic Behavior, New York, McGraw-Hill.LICHTHEIM, G. (1961) Marxism: An Historical and Critical Study, London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul. LIPSET, S. M. (1960) Political Man, London, Heinemann.LIPSET, S. M. (1972) 'Ideology and no end: the controversy till now', Encounter, Vol. 39, No. 6 (Dec.), pp. 17-22. LONDON LABOUR PROCESS/LEFT STRATEGY GROUP (1979) 'The problem of
articulation in left strategies', CSE Conference Papers, pp. 101-18. *LUKES, S. (1967) 'Alienation and anomie', in Laslett, P. and Runciman,
W. C. (eds.) Philosophy, Politics and Society, 3rd Series, Oxford, Blackwell, pp.
13-56 (reprinted in his Essays in Social Theory, London, Macmillan Press, 1977, pp.
74-95).LUKES, S. (1973) Emile Durkheim: His Life and Work; A Historical and
Critical Study, London, Allen Lane.LYNCH, F. R. (1977) 'Social theory and the progressive era', Theory
and Society, Vol. 4, No.2, pp. 159-210. MACINTYRE, A. (1971) 'The end of ideology and the end of the end of
ideology', in his Against the Self-Images of the Age: Essays on Ideology and
Philosophy, London, Duckworth, pp. 3-11.MADDEN, E. H. (1963) Chauncey Wright and the Founders of Pragmatism, Seattle, University of Wisconsin Press. MALINOWSKI, B. (1931) 'Culture', in Seligman, E. R. A. (ed.), Encyclopedia
of the Social Sciences, London, Macmillan, Vol. 4, pp. 621-46. MALINOWSKI, B. (1944) A Scientific Theory of Culture and Other
Essays, Chapel Hill, University of North Carolina Press (reissued New York, Oxford
University Press, 1960). MANDELBAUM, M. (1969) 'Functionalism in social anthropology', in
Morganbesser, H. (ed.) Philosophy, Science and Method: Essays in Honour of Ernest
Nagel, New York, St. Martin's Press, pp. 306-32. MANUEL, F. (1956) 'From equality to organicism', Journal of the
History of Ideas, 17, pp. 54-69 (reprinted in Freedom from History, pp. 221-41).
MANUEL, F. (1972) 'Henri Saint-Simon on the role of the scientist',
reprinted in his Freedom from History and Other Essays, London, University of
London Press, pp. 205-18; first published 1960. *MARCUSE, H. (1964) One Dimensional Man: The Ideology of Industrial
Society, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul. *MARCUSE, H. (1968) 'Industrialization and capitalism in the work of
Max Weber', in his Negations: Essays in Critical Theory, Boston, Beacon Press, pp.
201-26. *MARCUSE, H. (1969) Eros and Civilisation: A Philosophical Inquiry
into Freud, London, Sphere Books. MARCUSE, H. (1970) Five Lectures, London, Allen Lane. MARKS, J. (1979) The Search for the 'Manchurian Candidate': The CIA
and Mind Control, London, Allen Lane. MARTINDALE, D. (ed.) (1965) Functionalism in the Social Sciences:
The Strengths and Limits of Functionalism in Anthropology, Economics, Political Science,
and Sociology, Philadelphia, American Academy of Political and Social Science. MARX, K. and ENGELS, F. (1965) Selected Correspondence, Moscow,
Progress Publishers, 2nd revised edition. MAYO, E. (1933) The Human Problems of an Industrial Civilization, New
York, Macmillan (reissued New York, Viking Press, 1960). MAYO, E. (1949) The Social Problems of an Industrial Civilization, London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul. MCNALL, S. G. and JOHNSON, J. C. M. (1975) 'The new Conservatives:
ethnomethodologists, phenomenologists, and symbolic interactionists', The Insurgent
Sociologist, Vol. 5, No. 4, pp. 49-65. MEDVEDEV, Z. A. and MEDVEDEV, R. A. (1971) A Question of Madness, London,
Macmillan. *MERTON, R. K. (1948) 'Manifest and latent functions', in his Social
Theory and Social Structure, London, Collier-Macmillan, 3rd edition, 1968, pp. 73-138.
MILGRAM, S. (1974) Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View, London,
Tavistock. MILLS, C. W. (1964) Sociology and Pragmatism: The Higher Learning in
America, New York, Paine-Whitman. MILLS, C. W. (1970) The Sociological Imagination, Harmondsworth,
Penguin, first published 1959. MOORE, J. R. (1979) The Post-Darwinian Controversies: A Study of the
Protestant Struggle to Come to Terms with Darwin in Great Britain and America 1870-1900, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press. NADWORNY, (1955) Scientific Management and the Unions, 1900-1932, Cambridge,
Mass., Harvard University Press. NELSON, B. (ed.) (1957) Freud and the 20th Century, New York,
Meriden Books. PALMER, B. (1975) 'Class, conception and conflict: the thrust for
efficiency, managerial views of labor and the working class rebellion, 1903-22', Review
of Radical Political Economy, No. 7 (Summer), pp. 31-49. PARETO, V. (1966) Sociological Writings, London, Pall Mall
Press. PARSONS, T. (t951) The Social System, London, Routledge and
Kegan Paul. PARSONS, T. (1966) Societies: Evolutionary and Comparative
Perspectives, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, Prentice-Hall. PARSONS, T. (1970) 'On building social system theory: a personal
history', Daedalus, Vol. 99, pp. 826-81. PEYRE, H. (1960) 'Durkheim: the man, his time, and his intellectual
background', in Wolff, K. H. (ed.) Essays on Sociology and Philosophy by Emile Durkheim
et al. with Appraisals of His Life and Thought, New York, Harper and Row, pp. 3-31. PHILLIPS, D. C. (1970) 'Oragnicism in the late nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries', Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 31, pp. 413-32. *POLLARD, S. (1965) The Genesis of Modern Management: A Study of the
Industrial Revolution in Great Britain, London, Edward Arnold (reissued,
Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1968). POWELL, J. W. (1888) Competition as a factor in human evolution', American Anthropologist, Vol. 1, pp. 297-323. RADCLIFFE-BROWN, A. R. (1952) Structure and Function in Primitive
Society: Essays and Addresses, London, Cohen and West. *RADICAL SCIENCE JOURNAL COLLECTIVE (1978) 'Reading lists on marxism
and science, the labour process, scientism and psychoanalysis', Radical Science
Journal, No. 6/7, pp. 144-50 RADICAL SCIENCE JOURNAL COLLECTIVE SUBGROUP (1978) 'Marxism, feminism
and psychoanalysis', Radical Science Journal, No. 6/7, pp. 107-18. *RAISON, T. (ed.) (1969) The Founding Fathers of Social Science, Harmondsworth,
Penguin.RAPAPORT, D. (1959) 'A historical survey of psychoanalytic ego
psychology', Psychological Issues, Vol. 5, pp. 5-17 (reprinted in The Collected
Papers of David Rapaport, London, Basic Books, 1967, pp. 745-57). REJAI, M. (ed.) (1971) Decline of Ideology?, Chicago/New York,
Aldine/Atherton.*RICHARDS, A. I. (1957) 'The concept of culture in Malinowski's work',
in Firth (1957), pp. 15-32. *ROGERS, J. A. (1972) 'Darwinism and social Darwinism', Journal of
the History of Ideas, Vol. 33, pp. 265-80. ROSE, M. (1975) Industrial Behaviour: Theoretical Developments since
Taylor, London, Allen Lane (reissued, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1978). ROSEN, R. D. (1978) Psychobabble: Fast Talk and Quick Cure in the
Era of Feeling, London, Wildwood House. ROSZAK, T. (ed.) (1969) The Dissenting Academy, Harmondsworth,
Penguin.*RUSSETT, C. E. (1966) The Concept of Equilibrium in American Social
Thought, London, Yale University Press. RUSSETT, C. E. (1976) Darwin in America: The Intellectual Response
I865-1912, San Francisco, W. H. Freeman. *SCHNEIDER, M. (1975) Neurosis and Civilization: A Marxist/Freudian
Synthesis, New York, Seabury Press. SCHWENDINGER, H. and J. R. (1974) The Sociologists of the Chair: A
Radical Analysis of the Formative Years of North American Sociology (1883-1922), New
York, Basic Books. SCIENCE FOR PEOPLE (periodical of the British Society for Social
Responsibility in Science). SEDGWICK, A. (1845) 'Natural history of creation', Edinburgh Review, Vol. 82. pp. 1-85.SEMMEL, B. (1960) Imperialism and Social Reform: English
Social-Imperial Thought I895-1914, London, George Allen and Unwin (reissued Garden
City, New York, Anchor Books, 1968). SHILS, E. (1968) 'The concept and function of ideology', in Sills, D.
L. (ed.) International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, New York, Macmillan and
Free Press, Vol. 7, pp. 66-76. SKINNER, B. F. (1948) Walden Two, New York, Macmillan.SKINNER, B. F. (1971) Beyond Freedom and Dignity, London, Cape
(reissued Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1973). SPENCER, H. (1851) Social Statics: or, The Conditions Essential to
Human Happiness Specified and the First of Them Developed, London, John Chapman. SPENCER, H. (1852) 'The development hypothesis', The Leader (20
March), (reprinted in his Essays: Scientific, Political and Speculative, 3 vols.,
London, Williams and Norgate, 1901, Vol. 1, pp. 1-7). ~*SPENCER, H. (1860) 'The social organism', Westminster Review (January),
(reprinted in Essays, Vol. 1, pp. 265-307; and in The Man versus the
State: with Four Essays on Politics and Society, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1969, pp.
195-233). SPENCER, H. (1862) First Principles, London, Williams and
Norgate.SPENCER, H. (1862-93) The Synthetic Philosophy, including Principles
of Biology, Principles of Psychology, Principles of Sociology, Principles of Ethics, London,
Williams and Norgate. STAUDER, J. (1974) 'The "relevance" of anthropology to
colonialism and imperialism', Radical Science Journal, No. 1, pp. 51-70. STEENSON, G. P. (1979) Karl Kautsky I854-I938: Marxism in the
Classical Years, Pittsburgh, University Press. SULLOWAY, F. J. (1979) Freud: Biologist of the Mind: Beyond the
Psychoanalytic Legend, London, Burnett Books/André Deutsch. SUMNER, W. G. (1963) Selected Essays of William Graham Sumner, Englewood
Cliffs, New Jersey, Prentice-Hall. TAYLOR, F. W. (1902-3) 'Shop management', Transactions of the
American Society of Mechanical Engineers, Vol. 24, pp. 1337-1480. TAYLOR, F. W. (1907) 'On the art of cutting metals', Transactions of
the American Society of Mechanical Engineers, Vol. 28, pp. 27-279.
*TAYLOR, F. W. (l911) The Principles of Scientific Management, New
York&127;&127;, Harper and Row (reissued New York, W. W. Norton and Co., 1967).
TAYLOR, F. W. (1947) Scientific Management, comprising Shop
Management, The Principles of Scientific Management, Testimony before the Special House
Committee, London, Harper and Brothers. THACKRAY, A. (1978) 'Measurement in the historiography of science', in
Elkana, Y. et al. (eds.) Toward a Metric of Science: The Advent of Science
Indicators, New York, Wiley, pp. 11-30. THERBORN, G. (1980) 'Two thinkers on different sides of the barricades:
Herbert Marcuse and Talcott Parsons', Times Higher Education Supplement, 18
January, pp. 10-11. THOMAS, J. M. and BENNIS, W. G. (eds.) (1972) Management of Change
and Conflict: Selected Readings, Harmondsworth, Penguin. *TILLETT, A. et al., (eds.) (1970) Management Thinkers, Harmondsworth,
Penguin. TRIST, E. (1973) 'A socio-technical critique of scientific management',
in Edge, D. O. and Wolfe, J. N. (eds.) Meaning and Control: Essays in Social Aspects of
Science and Technology, London, Tavistock Publications, pp. 95-119. URWICK, L. and BRECH, E. F. L. (194548) The Making of
Scientific Management, 3 vols., London, Management Publications Trust. WALKER, P. (ed.) (1979) Between Labour and Capital, Hassocks,
Sussex, Harvester Press. WALLACE, A. R. (1870) 'The limits of natural selection as applied to
man', (reprinted in his Natural Selection and Tropical Nature: Essays on Descriptive
and Theoretical Biology, London, Macmillan and Co., 1891, pp. 186-214). WARR, P. and WALL, T. (1975) Work and Well-Being, Harmondsworth,
Penguin. *WATSON, J. B. (1913) 'Psychology as the behaviorist views it', Psychological
Review, Vol. 20, pp. 158-177 (reprinted in Dennis, 1948, pp. 457-471). WATSON, J. B. (1924) Behaviorism (reissued, Chicago, University
of Chicago Press, 1959). WAXMAN, C. L. (ed.) (1968) The End of Ideology Debate, New York,
Simon and Schuster. WEBER, G. (1974)' Science and society in nineteenth century
anthropology', History of Science, Vol. 12, pp. 260-283. WEBER, M. (1904-5) The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (reissued London, George Allen and Unwin, 1930). WEINBERG, J. (1972) Edward Alsworth Ross and the Sociology of
Progressivism, Madison, State Historical Society of Wisconsin. WHEELER, H., (ed.) (1973) Beyond the Punitive Society: Operant
Conditioning: Social and Political Aspects (including B. F. Skinner's 'Answers for my
critics'), London, Wildwood. WIENER, P. P. (1949) Evolution and the Founders of Pragmatism, Cambridge,
Mass., Harvard University Press, (reissued New York, Harper and Row, 1965). WILSON, E. O. (1975) Sociobiology: The New Synthesis, Cambridge,
Mass., Harvard University Press. *WOLLHEIM, R. (1971) Freud, London, Fontana/Collins. WOODCOCK, G. and AVAKUMOVIC, 1. (1950) The Anarchist Prince: A
Biographical Study of Peter Kropotkin (reissued New York, Schocken Books, 1971). WOODWORTH, R. S. and SHEEHAN, M. R. (1965) Contemporary Schools of
Psychology, 9th edition, London, Methuen and Co. WOOTTON, B. (1959) Social Science and Social Pathology, London,
George Allen and Unwin. YOUNG, R. M. (1967) 'Animal soul', in Edwards, P. (ed.) The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London, Collier-Macmillan, Vol. 1, pp. 122-7. YOUNG, R. M. (1967a) 'Review of Burrow, Evolution and Society',
Cambridge Review, Vol. 89 (10 June), pp. 409-11. *YOUNG, R. M. (1969) 'Natural theology, Victorian periodicals and the
fragmentation of a common context' (reprinted in his Darwin's Metaphor and Other
Studies of Nature's Place in Victorian Society, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
in press; also in Chant and Fauvel (1980) YOUNG, R. M. (1970) Mind, Brain and Adaptation: Cerebral
Localisation and Its Biological Context from Gall to Ferrier, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
YOUNG, R. M. (1970a) 'The impact of Darwin on conventional thought', in
Symondson, A. (ed.) The Victorian Crisis of Faith, London, SPCK, pp. 13-35. YOUNG, R. M. (1971) 'Evolutionary biology and ideology: then and now', Science
Studies, Vol. 1, pp. 177-206. YOUNG, R. M. (1971a) ' "Non-scientific" factors in the
Darwinian debate' Actes du XII'e Congrès International d'Histoire des Sciences, 1968,
Paris, Blanchard, Vol. 8 pp. 221-6. YOUNG, R. M. (1972) 'Darwinism and the division of labour', The
Listener, 88 (17 August), pp. 202-5. YOUNG, R. M. (1973) 'The role of psychology in the nineteenth-century
evolutionary debate', in Henle, M. et al. (eds.) Historical Conceptions of
Psychology, New York, Springer, pp. 180-204; also in Chant and Fauvel (1980). YOUNG, R. M.. (1973a) 'Association of ideas', in Wiener, P. P. (ed.) Dictionary
of the History of Ideas, New York, Scribner's, Vol. 1, pp. 111-18. YOUNG, R. M. (1973b) 'The historiographic and ideological contexts of
the nineteenth century debate on man's place in nature', in Teich, M. and Young, R. M.
(eds.) Changing Perspectives in the History of Science: Essays in Honour of Joseph
Needham, London, Heinemann, pp. 344-438. YOUNG, R. M. (1973c) 'The human limits of nature', in Benthall, J.
(ed.), The Limits of Human Nature, London, Allen Lane, pp. 235-74. YOUNG, R. M. (1976) 'Review of Braverman, Labor and Monopoly
Capital', Radical Science Journal, No. 4, pp. 81-93. YOUNG, R. M. (1977) 'Science is social relations', Radical Science
Journal, No. 5, pp. 65-129.YOUNG, R. M. (1979) 'Why are figures so significant? The role and the
critique of quantification', in Miles, J. et al. (eds.) Demystifying Social
Statistics, London, Pluto Press, pp. 63-74. YOUNG, R. M. (1979a) 'Interpreting the production of science', New
Scientist, (29 March), pp. 1026-28. YOUNG, R. M. (1979b) 'Science is a labour process', Science for
People, Nos. 43/44, pp. 31-7. YOUNG, R. M. (1979c) 'Reconstituting technology: chips, genes, spares', CSE Conference Papers, pp. 119-28 (available from CSE, 55 Mount Pleasant, London,
WCIX OAE). YOUNG, R. M. (1979d) 'Science as culture', Quarto, No. 2
(December), pp. 7-8. This essay first appeared as an Open University Course Unit for the
course Science and Belief: from Darwin to Einstein, Block VI: Problems in
the Biological and Human Sciences. Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1981, pp.
63-110.
Address for correspondence: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|