Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
DARWINISM IS SOCIAL
by Robert M. Young
It strikes me that there should be little need for this paper. Only
positivists believe that scientific facts and theories are separate from human meanings
and values, and even they, inconsistently, set out to extrapolate human and social
conclusions from putatively decontextualized facts. Only religious fundamentalists believe
that a belief in God cannot be reconciled with science, and that true religion is based on
the literal truth of Scripture. This is a sort of religious positivism, as is the notion
of creation science, which the ultra-right is currently deploying in opposition to a
vulnerable, neo-Darwinian scientific orthodoxy, as part of an attack on the role that
science plays in giving legitimacy to a liberal vision of capitalism.Except for scientific positivists and religious fundamentalists, then,
the connection between Darwinism and society is acknowledged. Indeed, the
nineteenth-century Comtean positivist historical progression of stages - from theological
to metaphysical to positive science - is now more likely to be seen as conceptual layers,
rather than stages, with the social totality as the most basic level below those three.But, of course, I've already made the situation far too simple. There
is no such thing as "the" connection between Darwinism and society. And we must
pick our way carefully among the various versions of the connection that are now on offer
and that were on offer in the nineteenth century.I have heart for this task, but I want to begin by registering a
certain weariness, even impatience, that it's still necessary to argue that: first, the
intellectual origins of the theory of evolution by natural selection are inseparable from
social, economic and ideological issues in nineteenth-century Britain (I nearly wrote
"Victorian", but that would beg the question of what happened for over a third
of that century); second, the substance of the theory was, and remains, part of the wider
philosophy of nature, God, and society, where the conceptions of nature and God are
themselves changing in complex ways which are integral to the changing social order;
third, the extrapolations from Darwinism to either humanity or society are not separable
from Darwin's own views, nor are they chronologically subsequent. They are integral.Let me reiterate that it still seems odd to have to argue that the
great nineteenth-century debate was about "man's place in nature". Yet I well
recall a seminar in which the historian of biology Jonathan Hodge said, in a barbed aside,
that not everything in the nineteenth-century evolutionary debate was about man's place in
nature. And yet Darwin called it the highest and most interesting problem for the
naturalist. Another way of making the point is to say that it's very implausible indeed
that the great nineteenth-century quarterlies - rooted in history, literature, and
social questions - would have devoted so much space and would have gone into such
detail about geology and natural history, unless something rather important was
implicitly, and often explicitly, at issue, which was itself centrally concerned with the
natural order as the symbolic basis for the social order.Efforts are still made to separate the origins of the theory of
evolution by natural selection from the substance of the theory and from extrapolations to
society. Efforts are also made to separate the origins and substance of the theory from
social and economic contexts and debates. There is something of a supermarket of
distinctions on offer. It's argued that contemporary social and economic conditions and
theories played no part; or that since Malthus didn't say what Darwin took him to say, the
connection is thereby weakened - as if there were a neutral "what X said", any
more than there is a neutral observation language in science; or that we can legitimately
trace the geological and/or theological connections while being silent about the social
origins and resonances of ideas of the earth or of the deity; or that we can separate out
the positivist Darwin from the ideologue, either within the Origin and other
relatively strictly scientific works, or between what he said about species and what he
went on to say about humanity and society; or that we can separate the Darwin and Wallace
scientific theory from the wider debate embracing, most notably, Chambers, Spencer, and
(Lyell's version of) Lamarck. Then there is the attempt to privilege natural selection as
the mechanism of evolution and deny the real strength of other mechanisms in the Origin,
and their growing prominence in subsequent editions and in Darwin's other writings.I don't deny that there are meaningful distinctions to be made among
all these issues, disciplines, figures, and periods, but none of those distinctions is
ultimately important. I'm not arguing for a concept of the evolutionary totality so
Leibnitzean that every monad reflects all the others with equal intensity. Rather, I'm
suggesting that, then as now, the issues are all related to changing notions of humanity
and society, and that the points at which the distinctions of issue, discipline, or level
are made are themselves of socioeconomic and ideological interest. Once it is granted that
natural and theological conceptions are, in significant ways, projections of social ones,
then important aspects of all of the Darwinian debate are social ones, and the distinction
between Darwinism and Social Darwinism is one of level and scope, not of what is social
and what is asocial.Nature is a societal category, and so is God. The ideological process
that, it seems to me, underlies these developments is one that must be seen as
arising in nineteenth-century secularization and that culminates in twentieth-century
functionalism and sociobiology. That process is the naturalization of value systems. If we
look at the debate about man's place in nature in those terms, we have to look much more
widely: that is, look backward into a wider process of biological naturalization in the
nineteenth-century movement that embraced the work of St. Simon, of Comte, of Gall.
Looking forward, we have to consider much more carefully the biologization of human
sciences, which is most prominently displayed in the present in ethology and sociobiology.Once we have begun to consider the process of the naturalization of
value systems in broader terms and see the debate on man's place in nature as a part of
that wider set of issues, we must also consider our historical explanations as calling for
a more comprehensive set of determinations. Just as we are interested in the findings, the
data, the ruminations and the thought processes of Darwin - the notebooks, the scraps of
paper and the crossings-out - we should also be interested in the large-scale forces and
their resolutions, and the prevailing compromises of the period, as well as the issues
that frame the inquiries of disciplines and the figures in them. We can, for example,
trace these determinations for Paley, for Malthus, and for Lyell. Respectively, they help
us to grasp the meaning of a utilitarian natural theologian, a Newtonian concept of
progress through struggle, and a religious uniformitarian. Each is arguing a case in
relation to particular prevailing views find traditions.Let's develop these points. Lyell's opposition to a caricatured
catastrophism was on behalf of a less hide-bound theology and conception of nature. His
exposition of Lamarck made evolution so plausible that it convinced Spencer, among others,
and Lyell finally reached a point where he had to put in what amounted to a scholium, to
preclude the impending conclusion that he finally came to as late as 1869. He said in the Principles that even if other animals came to be by transmutation, to extend this view to
man would "strain analogy beyond all reasonable bounds" (Lyell 1830-1833, 1:
156).Paley, in his Natural Theology, expressed a certain dying
pastoral order. Paley managed to absorb the issues that became the motor of Darwinian
progress into a balanced order of nature. Here is the flavour of his world:
But, to do justice to the question, the system of animal destruction must always be considered in strict connection with another property of animal nature,
viz, superfecundity. They are countervailing qualities. One subsists by the
correction of the other. (Paley 1816, p. 408)
He comments on how this attribute keeps the world full and in balance.
But what happens when fruitfulness gets out of hand?
But then this superfecundity, though of great occasional use and
importance, exceeds the ordinary capacity of nature to receive or support its progeny. All
superabundance supposes destruction, or must destroy itself. Perhaps there is no species
of terrestrial animals whatever, which would not overrun the earth if it were permitted to
multiply in perfect safety; or a fish, which would not fill the ocean: at least, if any
single species were left to their natural increase without disturbance or restraint, the
food of other species would be exhausted by their maintenance. It is necessary, therefore,
that the effects of such prolific faculties be curtailed. In conjunction with other checks
and limits, all subservient to the same purpose, are the thinnings which take place
among animals, by their action upon one another. In some instances we ourselves
experience, very directly, the use of these hostilities. One species of insects rids us of
another species; or reduces their ranks. A third species perhaps keeps the second within
bounds; and birds or lizards are a fence against the inordinate increase by which even
these last might infest us. In other more numerous and possibly more important instances,
this disposition of things, although less necessary or useful to us, and of course less
observed by us, may be necessary and useful to certain other species; or even for the
preventing of the loss of certain species from the universe; a misfortune which seems to
be studiously guarded against. Though there may be the appearance of failure in some of
the details of Nature's works, in her great purposes there never are. (1816, pp. 411-412)
He concludes reassuringly:
We have dwelt the longer on these considerations because the subject to
which they apply, namely, that of animals devouring one another, forms the chief,
if not the only, instance in the works of the Deity of an economy stamped by marks
of design, in which the character of utility can be called in question. (1816, p. 413)
Paley's pastoral order was being challenged by an urban industrializing
order, in which progress was not the smooth process of the pleasure/pain principle of
utility. It was, rather, progress through a more disruptive and rapacious version of pain,
evil, suffering, famine, war, and death. Paley tried to accommodate this Malthuslanism
with a gentle rendering of God's superfecundity: the necessity of "thinnings".
Malthus's Law of Change was more brutal: not pruning shears, but unremitting pressure, the
"thousand wedges" we find in Darwin's D Notebook. These were the same
wedges that prevented the huge gap between arithmetic increase of food and geometric
increase of population from ever opening up.Malthus's order of society and nature had a very different flavour from
Paley's:
The history of the early migrations and settlements of mankind,
with the motives which prompted them, would illustrate in a striking manner the constant
tendency in the human race to increase beyond the means of subsistence. Without some
general law of this nature, it would seem as if the world could never have been peopled. A
state of sloth, and not of restlessness and activity, seems evidently to be the natural
state of man; and this latter disposition could not have been generated but by the strong
goad of necessity, though it might afterwards be continued by habit, and the new
associations that were formed from it, the spirit of enterprise, and the thirst of
martial glory. (Malthus 1826, 1: p. 92)
He then reflects on the consequences of a population in a congenial
environment.
These combined causes soon produce their natural and invariable effect,
an extended population, A more frequent and rapid change of place then becomes necessary.
A wider and more extensive territory is successively occupied. A broader desolation
extends all around them. Want pinches the less fortunate members of society: and at length
the impossibility of supporting such a number together becomes too evident to be resisted.
Young scions are then pushed out from the parent stock, and instructed to explore fresh
regions, and to gain happier seats for themselves by their swords. 'The world is all
before them where to choose.' Restless from present distress, flushed with the hope of
fairer prospects, and animated with the spirit of hardy enterprise, these daring
adventurers are likely to become formidable adversaries to all who oppose them. The
inhabitants of countries long settled, engaged in the peaceful occupations of trade and
agriculture, would not often be able to resist the energy of men acting under such
powerful motives of exertion. And the frequent contests with tribes in the same
circumstances with themselves, would be so many struggles for existence, and would be
fought with a desperate courage, inspired by the reflection, that death would be the
punishment of defeat, and life the prize of victory.
In these savage contests, many tribes must have been utterly
exterminated. Many probably perished by hardship and famine. Others whose leading star had
given them a happier direction, became great and powerful tribes, and in their turn sent
off fresh adventurers in search of other seats. (1826, 1: 94-95)
Paley and Malthus described different social orders, with very
different moods and sanctions of God and nature, producing very different conceptions of
biological stability and change - both theistic and both orderly. Paley extolled being
content with your lot, while Malthus offered upward social mobility in return for moral
restraint. Very different mechanisms were at work. The Malthusian law of progress was not
inescapably pessimistic. Indeed, Panglossian renderings of it were expressed by
Spencer, whereby progress to perfection was the consequence of the law of organic change,
and the law of population was its proximate cause (cf. Young 1969, pp. 130-137).Spencer said in 1851,
Progress, therefore, is not an accident, but a necessity. Instead of
civilization being artificial, it is a part of nature; all of a piece with the development
of the embryo or the unfolding of a flower. The modifications mankind have undergone, and
are still undergoing, result from a law underlying the whole organic creation; and
provided the human race continues, and the constitution of things remains the same, those
modifications must end in completeness. As surely as the tree becomes bulky when it stands
alone, and slender if one of a group; as surely as the same creature assumes different
forms of cart-horse and race-horse, according as its habits demand strength or speed; as
surely... so surely must the things we call evil and immorality disappear; so surely must
man become perfect. (1851, p. 65)
In 1857 Spencer put forward a comprehensive law of progress:
This is the history of all organisms whatever. It is settled beyond
dispute that organic progress consists in a change from the homogeneous to the
heterogeneous.
Now, we propose in the first place to show that this law of
organic progress is the law of all progress. Whether it be the development of the Earth,
in the development of Life upon its surface, in the development of Society, of Government,
of Manufactures, of Commerce, of Language, Literature, Science, Art, this same evolution
of the simple into the complex, through successive differentiations, holds throughout.
(1901, p. 10)
He then develops the law of progress throughout many manifestations and
passes from individual humanity to society, where he, concludes: "The authority of
the strongest or the most cunning makes itself felt among a body of savages as in a herd
of animals, or a posse of schoolboys" (1901, p.19).Once again he draws the most general conclusion:
It will be seen that as in each event of to-day, so from the beginning,
the decomposition of every expended force into several forces has been perpetually
producing a higher complication; that the increase of heterogeneity so brought about is
still going on and must continue to go on; and that, thus progress is not an accident, not
a thing within human control, but a beneficent necessity. (1901, p. 60)
Nor was Spencer the only person to put a dramatically optimistic
interpretation on Malthusianism. Consider, in this light, the passage that ends:
Thus, from the war of nature, from famine and death, the most exalted
object which we are capable of conceiving, namely, the production of higher animals,
directly follows. There is grandeur in this view of life with its several powers, having
been originally breathed into a few forms or into one; and that, whilst this planet has
gone cycling on according to the fixed laws of gravity, from so simple a beginning endless
forms most beautiful and most wonderful have been, and are being, evolved. (Origin, p.
490)
If it is thought that the last paragraph of the Origin was
merely a rhetorical flourish, one also has to explain away the last sentence of the
chapter on Instinct:
Finally, it may not be a logical deduction, but to my imagination it is
far more satisfactory to look at such instincts as the young cuckoo ejecting its
foster-brothers, ants making slaves, the larvae of lchneumonidae feeding
within the live bodies of caterpillars, not as specially endowed or created
instincts, but as small consequences of one general law, leading to the advancement of all
organic beings, namely, multiply, vary, let the strongest live and the weakest die. (Origin,
pp. 243-244)
Recent scholarship has confirmed the close link between Darwin's work
and both social theories and theological theories, which were in turn closely linked with
changing conceptions of the order of nature and society. There is also a growing consensus
that Darwinism was a subtle accommodation within natural theology, rather than a clean
break with it. Anyone wishing to take Darwin's mature views outside the context of natural
theology has a lot of explaining to do, from the frontispiece quotations to many of the
forms of reasoning and rhetoric in the Origin. Darwin was meticulous in his
revision, as is obvious from Peckham's variorum edition (Origin,1959). Why would
Darwin fail to remove forms of address and reasoning if they had become odious to him?To the extent that the conclusion is gaining credence that Darwinism
was a subtle accommodation within natural theology, then Darwin takes a place within the
history of Victorian theology, on the one hand; on the other, given the direction taken by
middle-brow theology with respect to science, it also points to an increasing embedding of
value systems in conceptions of living nature.Recall, for example, R. H. Hutton's rendering of the deliberations of
the Metaphysical Society, where he wrote that "The uniformity of nature is the veil
behind which, in these latter days, God is hidden from us" (Hutton 1885, p. 180). It
is a changed and very watered-down natural theology within which one finds Darwins
mature work, but it is natural theology nonetheless.An analogous change is that as nature, not God, bore the weight of the
laws of life and mind, fundamentalism itself born in opposition to the
presumptuous reductionism of science gave the believer a much more personal,
intimate, and ethical God. Science could not carry the role of the transcendent. This was
clear to Darwin, who on the whole avoided such questions. It was true of the spiritualist
Wallace, who invoked a rather pale deity to account for the origin of important (and to
him otherwise inexplicable) intellectual and moral faculties of man. He invoked socialist
politics to deal with the need for a just and ethical society. Huxley was as clear as
Wallace in believing that evolution itself could not bring about the millennium. He argued
against Spencer, saying contra inevitable millenniarianism that ethics has to be brought
in against the results of biology.Here we come upon another curious set of distinctions. Edward Thompson
has treated Darwin as the careful empiricist and Huxley as the ideologue. In his
controversy with Perry Anderson, his side of which has recently been published in the
collection of essays, The Poverty of Theory, Thompson tries to make Darwin an
empiricist of the first order and to draw a very sharp separation between Darwin on the
one hand as an inductive scientist, and Huxley on the other as a political and
ideologically tainted publicist (1978, pp. 60-62; cf. pp. 255-256). (Is there a whispered
parallel between himself and Darwin on the one hand, and Perry Anderson and Huxley on the
other?)What is striking about Thompson's position in this matter is the
shocking isolation of his writing as a social historian from the mainstream of debate then
and now about these matters. That is, he very surprisingly argues that there should have
been much more of a furore, much more manifesto writing, much more debate within the
periodicals. And in saying so he ignores just what ubiquitous debate there was throughout
the literature of the period. It was not confined to the periodicals; but were one to
consider only that sector, it takes Ellegard fifteen pages just to list the periodicals
that were involved in his research about that debate. That is, Thompson, has simply
ignored the breadth and texture of the debate in which both Darwin and Huxley were
embedded, a debate I should add, in which science and ideology were inextricably
intertwined (cf. Rad. Sci. J. Collective, 1981, pp. 25-26).In a related set of distinctions, Greta Jones (1980) has also set about
separating the scientist Darwin from the ideologue, and both of those from Social
Darwinism. As I see it, both Huxley and Darwin were expressing commonly held positions
that were relatively progressive for their time, but relatively shocking to our eyes. I'm
thinking, for example, of what Huxley had to say about blacks and women. I shall quote
this, as well as passages from Darwin, in some detail, in the hope that these striking
examples will destroy once and for all the notion that it's possible to distinguish
sharply the scientist from the ideologue.Huxley's essay is called "Emancipation - Black and White".
First blacks:
It may be quite true that some negroes are better than some white men;
but no rational man, cognizant of the facts, believes that the average negro is the equal,
still less the superior, of the average white man. And, if this be true, it is simply
incredible that, when all his disabilities are removed, and our prognathous relative has a
fair field and no favor, as well as no oppressor, he will be able to compete successfully
with his bigger-brained and smaller jawed rival, in a contest which is to be carried on by
thoughts and not by bites. The highest places in the hierarchy of civilization will
assuredly not be within the reach of our dusky cousins, though it is by no means necessary
that they should be restricted to the lowest. But whatever the position of stable
equilibrium into which the laws of social gravitation may bring the negro, all
responsibility for the result will henceforward lie between nature and him. The white man
may wash his hands of it, and the Caucasian conscience be void of reproach for evermore.
And this, if we look to the bottom of the matter, is the real justification for the
abolition policy. (Huxley 1865, pp. 17-18)
Notice that he's opposing slavery and saying that blacks are
biologically inferior, but that we shouldn't make it worse by adding social oppression. He
continues:
The like considerations apply to all the other questions of
emancipation which are at present stirring the world the multifarious demands that
classes of mankind shall be relieved from restrictions imposed by the artfice of man, and
not by the necessities of Nature. (1865, p. 18)
On the question of women, he is equally enlightened for his time.
For our parts, though loth to prophesy, we believe it will be [like the
result] of other emancipations. Women will find their place, and it will neither be that
in which they have been held, nor that to which some of them aspire. Nature's old salique
law will not be repealed, and no change of dynasty will be effected. The big chests, the
massive brains, the vigorous muscles and stout frames, of the best men will carry the day,
whenever it is worth their while to contest the prizes of life with the best women. . . .
The most Darwinian of theorists will not venture to propound the doctrine that the
physical disabilities under which women have hitherto laboured, in the struggle for
existence with men, are likely to be removed by even the most skilfully conducted process
of educational selection. (1865, p. 22)
And he concludes: "The duty of man is to see that not a grain is
piled upon that load beyond what Nature imposes; that injustice is not added to
inequality" (p. 23).This essay illustrates the principle that the science/ideology
distinction is at any point a contingent resolution of historical forces, playing its own
ideological role. The more ostensibly pure the science, the deeper one often has to look
in order to demonstrate this principle. It is therefore easier in the case of, say, a
Spencer or a Chambers than a Darwin or a Lyell. The evaluative conceptions that constitute
the problems and parameters of a discipline, however, apply to a Newton and an Einstein
just as much as they do to a Voltaire or a Velikovsky. Here, for example, is Darwin in the Descent of Man.
With savages, the weak in body or mind are soon eliminated; and those
that survive commonly exhibit a vigorous state of health. We civilised men, on the other
hand, do our utmost to check the process of elimination; we build asylums for the
imbecile, the maimed, and the sick; we institute poor-laws; and our medical men exert
their utmost skill to save the life of everyone to the last moment. There is reason to
believe that vaccination has preserved thousands, who from a weak constitution would
formerly have succumbed to small-pox. Thus the weak members of civilised societies
propagate their kind. No one who has attended to the breeding of domestic animals will
doubt that this must be highly injurious to the race of man. It is surprising how soon a
want of care, or care wrongly directed, leads to the degeneration of a domestic race; but
excepting in the case of man himself, hardly anyone is so ignorant as to allow his worst
animals to breed.... (Descent, 1874, pp. 133-134)
He goes on:
We must therefore bear the undoubtedly bad effects of the weak
surviving and propagating their kind; but there appears to be at least one check in steady
action; namely that the weaker and inferior members of society do not marry so freely as
the sound, and this check might be indefinitely increased by the weak in body or mind
refraining from marriage, though this is more to be hoped for than expected. (Descent, 1874, p. 134)
A little bit later:
But the inheritance of property by itself is very far from an
evil; for without the accumulation of capital the arts could not progress; and it is
chiefly through their power that the civilised races have extended and are now everywhere
extending their range, so as to take the place of the lower races. (Descent, 1874, p. 135)
Further on:
The presence of a body of well-instructed men, who have not to labour
for their daily bread, is important to a degree which cannot be overestimated. As all high
intellectual work is carried on by them, and on such work, material progress of all kinds
mainly depends, not to mention other and higher advantages. (Descent, 1874.
p. 135)
American Social Darwinism could take comfort from the following:
There is apparently much truth in the belief that the wonderful
progress of the United States, as well as the character of the people, are the results of
natural selection; for the more energetic, restless, and courageous men from all
parts of Europe have emigrated during the last ten or twelve generations to that great
country, and have there succeeded best. (Descent, 1874, p. 142)
He carries on:
Obscure as is the problem of the advance of civilisation, we can at
least see that a nation which produced during a lengthened period the greatest
number of highly intellectual, energetic, brave, patriotic, and benevolent men, would
generally prevail over less favored nations. (Descent, 1874, p. 142)
And further on:
Nevertheless the more intelligent members within the same community
will succeed better in the long run than the inferior, and leave a more numerous progeny,
and this is a form of natural selection. The more efficient causes of progress seem to
consist of a good education during youth whilst the brain is impressible, and of a high
standard of excellence, inculcated by the ablest and best men, embodied in the laws,
customs and traditions of the nation, and enforced by public opinion. (Descent, 1874, p. 143)
I skip now to the general summary where Darwin reprises the
quasi-imperialist views in the above passages.
The advancement of the welfare of mankind is a most intricate problem:
all ought to refrain from marriage who cannot avoid abject poverty for their children; for
poverty is not only a great evil, but tends to its own increase by leading to recklessness
in marriage. (Descent, 1874, p. 618)
Who says, by the way, that Darwin didn't take in what Malthus said? He
goes on:
On the other hand, as Mr. Galton has remarked, if the prudent avoid
marriage, whilst the reckless marry, the inferior members tend to supplant the better
members of society. Man, like every other animal, has no doubt advanced to his present
high condition through a struggle for existence consequent upon his rapid multiplication;
and if he is to advance still higher, it is to be feared that he must remain subject to a
severe struggle. Otherwise he would sink into indolence, and the more gifted men would not
be more successful in the battle of life than the less gifted. Hence our natural rate of
increase, though leading to many and obvious evils, must not be greatly diminished by any
means. There should be open competition for all men; and the most able should not-be
prevented by laws or customs from succeeding best and rearing the largest number of
offspring. Important as the struggle for existence has been and even still is, yet as far
as the highest part of man's nature is concerned there are other agencies more important.
For the moral qualities are advanced, either directly or indirectly, much more through the
effects of habit, the reasoning powers, instruction, religion, &c, than through
natural selection; though to this latter agency may be safely attributed the social
instincts, which afforded the basis for the development of the moral sense. (Descent, 1874, p. 618)
I have quoted at length these passages from Huxley and Darwin to show
the inseparability of so-called Darwinism from so-called Social Darwinism and, congruent
with that, between science and ideology. Anyone wishing to separate the scientific from
the social from the theological will have to contend with these passages in these men's
work. And anyone wishing to confine Darwin's Social Darwinism to his post-Origin work
will have to contend with Silvan Schweber's claim: "To the best of my knowledge the M
and N notebooks contain the first presentation of an evolutionary view of society based on
an evolutionary view of nature" (1977, p. 232).Would-be separators of Darwin the biological scientist from Darwin the
Social Darwinist would also be likely to stumble over passages from the E Notebook; the
projected Chapter 6 of Natural Selection ("Theory Applied to the Races of
Man", Stauffer, 1975); the marginal annotations in Darwin's own books on the races
of man; a letter to Lyell in 1859 that applied natural selection and the effects of
inherited mental exercise as follows: "I look at this process as now going on with
the races of man; the less intellectual races being exterminated" (LL 2: 211). These
evidences of continuity, along with many more, have been set forth in John Greene's
convincing essay on "Darwin as a Social Evolutionist" (1981a, pp. 95-127). This
complements his earlier on "Biology and Social Theory in the 19th Century"
(1981, pp. 60-94), and both invite us to broaden and deepen our views on the mutual
constitutiveness of scientific and social thought.Turning now to Social Darwinism per se, my first point is that there is
no such clearly separable thing. There was, however, a movement that was concerned chiefly
with the interpretation of evolutionary ideas in the social context. It was a
Malthusianism buttressed by the law of the history of life. It was based on a conception
of the imbalance between human instincts and needs on the one hand, and human industry and
nature's bounty on the other. It was not always pessimistic, but it was never very
pleasant. Moreover, it was almost always associated with concepts of social hierarchy and
mobility via competition.My own conception of Social Darwinism is that it was an attitude toward
nature with common elements, usually including Malthusianism, a belief in the science of
social laws, and a belief that nature decreed extreme inequalities that most thought would
lead to progress. Social Darwinists usually invoked some version of the survival of the
fittest, although there were differing views about what the fittest were fit for. For more
on conceptions of Social Darwinism, we can look at some passages from Robert Bannister's
interesting monograph, Social Darwinism: Science and Myth in Anglo-American
Social Thought. One definition presents Social Darwinism as "the type of theory
that attempts to describe and explain social phenomena chiefly in terms of competition and
conflict, especially the competition of group with group and the equilibrium and
adjustment that ensues upon such struggles" (Bannister 1979, p. 4). Another described
it as "the name loosely given to the application to society of the doctrine of the
struggle for existence and survival of the fittest" (p. 5). Another definition said
that it's "the more general adaptation of Darwinian, and related biological concepts
to social ideologies" (p. 5). A last example was: "a ruthless form of
laissez-faire that it has become fashionable to call 'Social Darwinism' " (p. 6).Moving away from definitions to the question of how broadly this
attitude towards nature was represented, it's important to remember that it was very
widespread and not confined to post-Darwinian writings. For example, Lyell wrote that
"In the universal struggle for existence, the right of the strongest eventually
prevails" (quoted in Young 1969, p. 129). The concept of struggle is very common in
the Principles (see Young 1969, p. 129, n. 76).In a way that is echoed in the last passage from the Descent, Malthus
himself said: "Had population and food increased in the same ratio, it is probable
that man might never have emerged from the savage state" (Malthus 1798, p. 364).
Malthus remarked:
The first great awakeners of the mind seem to be the wants of the body.
They are the first stimulants that rouse the brain of infant man into sentient activity,
and such seems to be the sluggishness of original matter that unless, by a peculiar course
of excitements, other wants, equally powerful are generated, these stimulants seem, even
afterwards, to be necessary, to continue that activity which they first awakened. The
savage would slumber for ever under his tree unless he were roused from his torpor by the
cravings of hunger, or the pinchings of cold; and the exertions that he makes to avoid
these evils, by procuring food, and building himself a covering, are the exercises which
form and keep in motion his faculties, which otherwise would sink into listless
inactivity. From all that experience has taught us concerning the structure of the human
mind, if those stimulants to exertion, which arise from the wants of the body, were
removed from the mass of mankind, we have much more reason to think, that they would be
sunk to the level of brutes, from a deficiency of excitements, than that they would be
raised to the rank of philosophers by the possession of leisure. In those countries, where
nature is the most redundant in spontaneous produce, the inhabitants will not be found the
most remarkable for acuteness of intellect. Necessity has been with great truth called the
mother of invention. (pp. 356-358)
Of course, Social Darwinism was, one might say, a broad church. A very
optimistic interpretation was put on it in the writings of Darwin; the same was true of
Spencer's rendering of it, just as was the use to which it was put in Social
Darwinist ideas of the American robber barons. There is perpetually an undertone, however,
as there was in Malthus, another note, a sense of pessimism. In Malthus's case it was a
pessimism that allowed scope for striving and moral restraint. But there were worse forms
of pessimism. Henry George one of the passionate followers of Spencer became
disillusioned and played in turn an important role in inspiring the social ideas of
Wallace (see Young 1968b). George once recalled a conversation between himself and
Spencer's great American publicist, E. L. Youmans, concerning the state of American
society. "What do you propose to do about it?" George had asked. To this Youmans
responded with something like a sigh": "Nothing! You and I can do nothing at
all. It's all a matter of evolution. We can only wait for evolution. Perhaps in four
or five thousand years evolution may have carried men beyond this state of affairs. But we
can do nothing" (quoted in Bannister 1979, p. 75).The doctrine of this broad church, then, conveyed both optimism and
pessimism both a concept of progress and a fatalism about its parameters and its
pace. But more important of all, it rooted social ideas in biological ideas. The point I'm
making is that biological ideas have to be seen as constituted by, evoked by, and
following an agenda set by, larger social forces that determine the tempo, the mode, the
mood, and the meaning of nature. In particular, evolutionary concepts of society changed
quite fundamentally in the three decades from 1880 to 1910, from those of Social Darwinism
to those of functionalism. The change coincides with the shift in the epochs of capitalism
from that of primitive accumulation to that of managerialism; from a conception of the
frontier and of moving ever onward, exploiting new areas of nature, to a conception of
ordering and managing the space in society that is already occupied; from a doctrine of
pure competition to one of competition within meritocracy, or consensus; from brawling to
achievement; from survival to careers; from omnivorous trusts à la Rockefeller's Standard
Oil to philanthropic trusts à la the Rockefeller Foundation; from conquest to
organization. And of course some of the most vehement defenders of rampant capitalism set
up some of the most philanthropic foundations not just Rockefeller, but also the
steel magnate Andrew Carnegie. In the succeeding epoch, the great defender of managerial
capitalism was the patron of yet another foundation, Henry Ford. The Ford Foundation was
concerned with the next generation of philanthropy in the social sciences.Although it was fed by many streams, the managerial order of capitalism
and its theoretical representation, functionalism, used the rhetoric of evolutionary
biology. Concepts of structure, function, adaptation, evolution, were fundamental to the
whole conceptual vocabulary of both nature and society for two, and probably three,
generations.This framework of ideas, about which I've written in detail elsewhere,
became pervasive throughout the human and social sciences and, in particular, in
psychology, sociology, and anthropology (Young 1981). The most succinct summary of the
assumptions of functionalism, the one in which the density of biologistic concepts is the
greatest, is the address "On the Concept of Function in the Social Sciences" ,
which A. R. Radcliffe-Brown gave to the American Anthropological Association in 1935,
where he began:
The concept of function applied to human societies is based on an
analogy between social life and organic life. The recognition of the analogy and of some
of its implications is not new. In the 19th century the analogy, the concept of function,
and the word itself appear frequently in social philosophy and sociology. (Radcliffe-Brown
1935, p. 178)
He goes on to develop the analogy between social life and organic life,
and to dwell on the concept of function. He says,
As the word 'function' is here being used the life of an organism is
conceived as the functioning of its structure. It is through and by the continuity
of the functioning that the continuity of the structure is preserved. If we consider any
recurrent part of the life-process, such as respiration, digestion, etc., its function is
the part it plays in, the contribution it makes to, the life of the organism as a
whole. (1935, p. 179)
By analogy, the function of a particular social usage
is the contribution it makes to the total social life as the
functioning of the total social system. Such a implies that a social system (the total
social structure of a society together with the totality of social usages in which that
structure appears and on which it depends for its continued existence) has a certain kind
of unity, which we may speak of as a functional unity. We may define it as a condition in
which all parts of the social system work together with a sufficient degree of harmony or
internal consistency, i.e. without producing persistent conflicts which can neither be
resolved nor regulated. (1935, p. 181)
Radcliffe-Brown acknowledges that the idea of the functional unity of
the social system is hypothesis (p. 181). In the functionalist tradition, however, this
hypothesis has become the model according to which societies are viewed. It is a model
that therefore systematically places second and treats secondarily concepts of conflict,
and a model within which concepts of contradiction simply do not arise. In particular,
irreconcilable class conflicts are unthinkable, as is the notion of a mode of production
as a contradictory unity of forces and relations of production (Clarke 1977). Put another
way, the language of functionalism has a profound ideological role to play in the way that
social theories operate as lenses through which to view societies. Using concepts like
morphology, organic unity, physiology, structure, sets of relations, continuity,
adaptation, etc., the functionalist tradition leads us to think in certain ways and
systematically diverts our gaze from other directions (Russett 1966).The applications of this model are not confined to the sociology of
"primitive" peoples but are orthodox in the sociology of our own society, and
extend to the ruling conceptual framework for the social interpretation of science itself.
For, as Barbara Heyl showed in a brilliant paper on "The Harvard Pareto
Circle'" (1968), it was within a certain social group centered around Harvard in the
1930s and 1940s that models were taken up from physiology, and particularly the
circulatory physiology of L. J. Henderson. These models were applied to society, and
extrapolated from the society to units within society, including the sociology of science
itself. Robert Merton, the doyen of the sociology of science, was a member of this
self-same circle, which has provided the reigning model of the interpretation of science
within society (Young 1982a). Looking more broadly, it is a model that has not been
confined to the social sciences, but has been applied to epistemology itself, in the work
of Karl Popper, Stephen Toulmin, and David Hull. The provocative epigram "Darwinism
is Social" is meant to evoke the role of biological and organic analogies, which move
freely from biology to society to the theory of knowledge itself, and lead us to think in
certain ways about the most abstract levels of nature and society, from the thermodynamics
of particles to systems theory, itself a metafunctionalism (Emery 1969; Beishon and Peters
1972; Haraway 1981-1982). In attempting to understand the ways in which these conceptions operate in the
society itself, it's important to realize that in general culture, and in
upper-middle-brow culture, the sharp distinction we might choose to make between pure
science, applied science, extrapolation, ideology, and popularization, simply do not
apply. If we examine the illustration from the Sunday Times magazine of 24
July 1977, we find a gestalt: a picture of the double helix of DNA and portraits with
potted biographies of Charles Darwin, Konrad Lorenz, Robert Ardrey, Edward Wilson, and
very beautifully portrayed Richard Dawkins. People see the chemistry of life
and On the Origin of Species, On Aggression, The Social Contract, Sociobiology, and The Selfish Gene as of a piece.It's worth adding that in the same issue of the magazine there are
pictures of women dressed up as leopards in very provocative poses. That is, concepts of
biologism and animality are not only intermingled in the gestalt of the illustration, but
are also adjacent to the gestalt of feline conceptions of woman, femininity, and
sexuality.The different elements of that gestalt are really those of a right-wing
liberal consensus. In the present, of course, that is under attack. Darwinism and forms
represented by ethology, sociobiology, behavioral genetics, are seen as an appropriate
target for people who are in opposition to the liberal consensus and feel that
Keynesianism, the United Nations, Trilateralism, meritocracy, and expertocracy are
undermining traditional values and threatening the moral fabric of society. (Spare a
thought for the poor ole liberal-capitalist-scientific consensus: the ultra-right attacks
it for being liberal, while the ultra-left attacks it for being capitalist.)I do not agree with the Moral Majority/radical right about abortion and
the nuclear family, for example, but I do see their point in wanting to maintain a basis
for values that is not caught up in instrumental rationality (Young 1982b). I also agree
with them that sociobiology is pernicious, and utterly reject the thesis that ethics
should be given for a time to the people who will here's a neologism
"biologicize" it (E. O. Wilson 1975 p. 562). That is, I don't look to genetics,
neurophysiology and the study of ants, troops and prides for my conception of society, nor
do I accept the thesis that biology is destiny.And here's where we come up against quite a profound truth about
conceptions in science. If you work your way systematically through E. O. Wilson's Sociobiology:
The New Synthesis, you will find the following terms as part of his working
vocabulary: division of labor (sexual and task), hierarchy, competitiveness, domination
and submission, peck order, aggression, selfishness, altruism, rank, caste, role, worker,
slave, soldier, queen, host, harem, promiscuous, mob, combat, spite, bachelor, jealousy,
territoriality, leadership, indoctrinability, élites. If we look a bit wider to Richard
Dawkins's The Selfish Gene, we find cheat, sucker, grudger; wider still, we find
nepotism, philandering, rape. What possible source except a society such as ours can we
consider for a conceptual vocabulary such as that? What possible significance except the
scientific underpinning of a competitive, fatalistic, individualistic, élitist,
patriarchal, sexist society can be attached to the following titles that have appeared
recently around these questions: On Aggression, The Naked Ape, The Territorial
Imperative, The Imperial Animal, The Dominant Man, The Inevitability of Patriarchy,
The Biological Imperative, and, once again, The Selfish Gene? Only two of those
were written by people who were not professional, academic biological or social
scientists. And of course we have On Human Nature itself, the Pulitzer
Prize-winning work of E. O. Wilson.These texts provide the current analogy to the nineteenth-century
debate, more evidence that the relationship between so-called purely biological and
so-called purely ideological ideas, books, and concepts is one that can't be sorted out at
all easily. We find that levels and concepts intermingle and that it is from society that
we derive our conceptions of nature. These conceptions are in turn inextricably
intermingled with our conceptions of human nature. It is, after all, the Darwinian theory
of evolution by natural selection that made conceptions of nature, living nature, and
human nature part of a single framework of ideas. It is also in the age of Darwinism that
we live in our attempts to formulate a single science.What is problematic about that attempted formulation is that our
conception of living nature may be so paltry as to give us a pessimistic and fatalistic
notion of humanity. Some people say that modern science's concepts of matter are not rich
enough to give us mind (Young 1967a, argued that conceptions of animality are not rich
1967b). It can also be enough to give us humanity in the required sense. By that I mean a
conception of humanity that envisages a society worth living in and a world worth
changing.Here are some examples of recent Social Darwinism, which are so
pessimistic that they leave us with conceptions of humanity not worth bothering about. The
first is from the work of the Nobel Laureate in ethology, Konrad Lorenz, who wrote during
the Nazi era:
This high valuation of our species specific and innate social
behavior patterns is of the greatest biological importance. In it as in nothing
patterns else lies directly the backbone of all racial health and power. Nothing is so
important for the health of a whole Volk as the elimination of invirent types;
those which, in the most dangerous, virulent increase, like the cells of a malignant
tumor, threaten to penetrate the body of a Volk. This justified high valuation, one of our
most important hereditary treasures, must however not hinder us from recognizing and
admitting its direct relation with Nature. It must above all not hinder us from descending
to investigate our fellow creatures, which are easier and simpler to understand, in order
to discover facts which strengthen the basis for the care of our holiest racial, volkish
and human hereditary values. (quoted in Kalikow 1978, pp. 174-175)
Lorenz felt that if it turned out that in conditions of civilization
where natural selection was inoperative, there was an increase in mutants leading to
"imbalance of the race, then race-care must consider an even more stringent
elimination of the ethically less valuable than is done today, because it would, in this
case, literally have to replace all selection factors that operate in the natural
environment" (quoted in Kalikow 1978, p. 176). These avowedly fascistic views are, of course, the extreme. But, they
are by no means extinct. Sociobiology is used to argue for analogously Social Darwinist
and racist views in the present. The National Front magazine Spearhead draws
routinely on biological reductionism, for example, in the article
"Sociobiology: the Instincts in our Genes" by Richard Verrall, who points out
that "Genetically determined instinctual behaviour lies at the root of social
organisation and even ethical and altruistic impulses" (1979, p.10). He goes on to
review recent sociobiological and biologistic literature and draws the expected racist
conclusions.More individualistic forms of Social Darwinism are not hard to find in
the mass media. Consider the most gripping scene in The Third Man, when Harry Lime
meets his friend Harley on the top of a huge ferris wheel in post-World War II Vienna.
When Harley confronts his old friend with the consequences of his selling diluted
penicillin horribly brain-damaged children the conversation continues as
follows:
Harley: Have you ever seen any of your victims?
Harry: (moving as if to push his friend out) You know I don't feel
comfortable on these sorts of things. Victims? Don't be melodramatic. Look down there [at
the pedestrians far below]. Would you really feel any pity if one of those dots stopped
moving forever? If I offered you £20,000 for every dot that stopped, would you really,
old man, tell me to keep my money, or would you calculate how many dots you could afford
to spare? Free of income tax. Free of income tax: it's the only way you can save money
nowadays.
After an interchange in which it becomes apparent that killing Harley
won't eliminate the only evidence against him, Harry chuckles and says that he still
believes in God and mercy, but that the dead are better off dead since there's not much to
miss on earth. As he walks away, he says,
Don't be so gloomy. After all, it's not that awful. You know what the
fellow says. In Italy for thirty years under the Borgias they had warfare, terror,
murders, bloodshed, but they produced Michelangelo, Leonardo da Vinci, and the
Renaissance. In Switzerland they had brotherly love; they had five hundred years of
democracy and peace. And what did that produce? The cuckoo clock.
As to corporate Social Darwinism, we have the following example from an
editorial in Computer Weekly commenting on the dominant role of IBM in the
industry:
The problem of trying to regulate IBM is that what is good for IBM is
in general good for the user, and as the company becomes more innovative and more
competitive that becomes increasingly true. IBM is an inevitable product of the capitalist
system in which survival of the fittest must always tend toward monopoly. (Anon. 1980)
These examples - drawn from ethology, fascism, film, and business -
might be dismissed as on the wrong side of the science/ideology divide. Then try this:
The evolution of society fits the Darwinian paradigm in its most
individualistic form. Nothing in it cries out to be otherwise explained. The economy of
nature is competitive from the beginning to end. Understand that economy, and how it
works, and the underlying reasons for social phenomena are manifest. They are the means by
which one organism gains some advantage to the detriment of another. No hint of genuine
charity ameliorates our vision of society, once sentimentalism has been laid aside. What
passes for co-operation turns out to be a mixture of opportunism and exploitation. The
impulses that lead one animal to sacrifice himself for another turn out to have their
ultimate rationale in gaining advantage over a third; and acts 'for the good' of one
society turn out to be performed to the detriment of the rest. Where it is in his own
interest, every organism may reasonably be expected to aid his fellows. Where he has no
alternative, he submits to the yoke of communal servitude. Yet given a full chance to act
in his own interest, nothing but expediency will restrain him from brutalizing, from
maiming, from murdering his brother, his mate, his parent, or his child. Scratch an
'altruist,' and watch a 'hypocrite' bleed. (Ghiselin 1974a, p. 247)
The author of that charming integration of biological and social
thought is a distinguished academic biologist and holds a MacArthur Fellowship, one of
America's most prestigious research awards. It would be wrong to claim that this is not a
minority, even eccentric, view among scientists. But holders of it and of closely
related views - for example, the "lifeboat" theory of scarcity, Friedmanite
economics, and the biological, social, and historical synthesis of C. D. Darlington and
that of Sir Hans Krebs (cf. Young 1973c, esp. pp. 247-249) are all well within the
scientific and social scientific cultures of eminent professors at the Universities of
California, Chicago, and Oxford as well as Fellows of the Royal Society and Nobel
Laureates (see Kalikow 1978; Hirshleifer 1977; and Anon. 1978 for further extremes of
conservative biologism).The point of this portion of the argument is to reject Social Darwinism
in an extremely important sense, while embracing it in another. Having rejected
crude Social Darwinist extrapolations from other animals to humankind, it is therefore
legitimate to ask: What next? Do we turn altogether away from extrapolations? Or do we
choose others?The first option, it seems to me, isn't open, since ideas of nature and
humanity, as I've said repeatedly, are mutually constitutive. There is nature apart
from human values, priorities, and perceptions, to be sure. But as far as we know it
as far as we characterize it, have research programs, put questions to
nature, and have criteria of acceptable answers we do so in inescapably
anthropocentric and anthropomorphic terms (Young 1973c, 1982c). So my rejection of Social
Darwinists' characterization of nature is not in the service of avoiding illegitimate extrapolations
in favor of nature "as it is." Nature is as we characterize it, and
extrapolations are as inescapable as the humanocentric relationship with nature in the
first place.The issue is how we characterize and work out the humanity and/as
nature that is, the humanity and nature, and the humanity as nature
relationship. I want to treat it as a transformative process of human labor. This
is as true of knowledge as it is of any other form of human industry.If we take that point seriously, we have to take seriously that, as
Marx put it,
Industry is the actual, historical relation of
nature, and therefore of natural science, to man. If, therefore, industry is conceived as
the exoteric revelation of man's essential powers, we also gain an understanding of
the human essence of nature, or the natural essence of man. In consequence,
natural science will lose its abstractly material or rather, its idealistic
tendency, and will become the basis of human science, as it has already become the
basis of actual human life, albeit in an estranged form. One basis for life and
another basis for science, is a priori a lie. The nature which comes to be in human
history the genesis of human society is man's real nature. Hence
nature as it comes to be through industry, even though in an estranged form, is
true anthropological nature. (Marx 1961, pp. 110-111)
The point of that quotation is to reinforce once again that nature,
knowledge, and human industry are part of a single mode of relating, conceiving, doing.If we try to look at Darwinism and Darwinism-as-social in this way, the
basis for humanity is not biology, genes, instincts, the givenness of our species in an
evolutionary sense: not body, not mind, but the concept of person, and that concept is
ontologically primitive. There's a parallel ontologically primitive concept that promises
to resolve the nature/culture dualism: labor. Labor is neither nature nor culture, but
their matrix.It is at this point that my historiographic argument about how we
should think about Darwin, Darwinism, and the debate about the place of humanity in nature
as the nineteenth century called it, the debate on "man's place in
nature" has to be recontextualized and connected up with the points I've been
making here about the concepts of industry, the concept of a person, and of labor.
Historiography has to be reintegrated into a new conception of what we mean by humanity, a
conception that is not based on nature/culture, body/mind, animal/human dualisms.This would give us a notion of humanity and secondarily of
biology that is not fatalistic, pessimistic, reifying, and scientistic. I would
like to think that it is a progressive and optimistic historiography, one without
blinkers, as opposed to the historiography of much of what I've come to think of as the
Darwin industry, which is very much a historiography whose distinctions and whose
narrowness of perspective makes it a historiography of the status quo.I'd like to drive this point home by recalling a letter that Engels
wrote to the sociologist P. L. Lavrov in 1875, because I think it captures quite a lot of
the points I've been making. It came as something of a surprise to me after I'd completed
the argument. I thought I would include a bit from this letter and found that it really
said, for all my reservations about some of Engels's ideas, quite a lot of what I've been
trying to say here. The first passage will be very familiar, but I shall go on to three
others that I think are quite helpful. Engels says,
The whole Darwinist teaching of the struggle for existence is simply a
transference from society to living nature, of Hobbes' doctrine bellum omnium contra
omnes [that is, the war of all against all] and of the bourgeois-economic doctrine of
competition, together with Malthus's theory of population. When this conjuror's trick has
been performed (and I question its absolute permissibility, as I've indicated ...
particularly as far as the Malthusian theory is concerned), the same theories are
transferred back again from organic nature into history and it is now claimed that their
validity as eternal laws of human society has been proved. The puerility of this procedure
is so obvious that not a word need be said about it. (Marx and Engels 1965, p. 302)
But of course he does go on. The key to the above is, of course, the
sentence, "When this conjuror's trick has been performed, the same theories are
transferred back from nature to history and claimed as eternal laws of society",
which I think is a fair summary of a great deal of what goes on in ethology, sociobiology,
and the human sciences, vis-à-vis their relationship with biology, in particular,
genetics, behavioral genetics, and the study of the nervous system, Engels says,
When therefore a self-styled natural scientist takes the liberty of
reducing the whole of historical development with all its wealth and variety to the
one-sided and meager phrase 'struggle for existence, a phrase which even in the
sphere of nature can be accepted only cum grano salis, such a procedure really
contains its own condemnation. (Marx and Engels 1965, p. 302)
Once again, a fair summary of much of what I've been saying. But here's
the point that moves us on the relationship between animal and human. He says,
The essential difference between human and animal society consists in
the fact that animals at most collect, while men produce. This sole but
cardinal difference alone makes it impossible simply to transfer laws of animal societies
to human societies. It makes it possible, as you properly remark, 'for man to struggle not
only for existence but also for pleasures and for the increase of his pleasures to
be ready to renounce his lower pleasures for the highest pleasure.' Without disputing your
further conclusions from this I would, proceeding from my premises, make the following
inferences: At a certain stage the production of man thus attains such a high level that
not only necessaries but also luxuries, at first, true enough, only for a minority, are
produced. The struggle for existence if we permit this category for the moment to
be valid is thus transformed into a struggle for pleasures, no longer for mere
means of subsistence, but for means of development, socially produced means
of development, and to this stage the categories derived from the animal kingdom are no
longer applicable. (p. 303)
And then later he says: "The struggle for existence can then
consist only in this: that the producing class takes over the management of production and
distribution from the class that was hitherto entrusted with it but has now become
incompetent to handle it, and there you have the socialist revolution" (p. 303).Now what Engels did in this letter was make a critique with which I
absolutely agree, about the interplay between social conceptions, their biologization and
then extrapolation back to being laws of nature. He then pointed out the limitations of
that interplay when applied to humanity. Instead, at a certain point the conceptual and
historical framework moves away from mere animality to production, which entails human
industry and the concept of labor. The concept of labor is not one which we find inside
biology in its narrow, Darwinian sense. But we do find social concepts at every level
inside the Darwinian theory. In that sense Darwinism is social.What I have attempted to convey in this essay is the need
for a greater sense of different scope and, more importantly, different levels, of the
mutual constitutiveness of conceptions of nature, science, and society, including the
deity. We're not forced to choose between Darwin's falsely conscious claims to have
nothing to do with politics, on the one hand, and scholars' fears, on the other, that to
invoke politics in the broader sense is to pollute natural science. The
"pollution" is inherent in the labor of knowing.The historiographic and political issue is how societies constitute
their knowledge, and why they conceive of that process as they do. And that's as important
a question about the Darwinian debate as it is about our own time. It entails a
historiography of then and a historiography of now and their relationship to whether we're
trying to keep knowledge and society as they are or put them in the service of a better
world. A better world would be one in which the struggle for existence doesn't have
the resonances that it had in the period of Social Darwinism and that it now has in the
renewed period of laissez-faire, Friedmanism, Thatcherism, and Reaganism.
Historiographic Afterthoughts on the Science of History
Just as I have argued that the history of science must find its place
within history, it is important to realize that the history of science, as an academic
discipline that reflects on the history of science per se, must also find its place
in history. That is, this volume and the historians writing in it are doing so within a
cultural, politico-economic and ideological framework Putting it yet another way, it can
be argued that just as Darwinism is social, so is Darwinian scholarship.I should like to illustrate this point of view with some reflections on
the conference at the Villa di Mondeggi near Florence, where the papers for this volume
were presented and discussed. I came to the conference in the capacity of a Rip Van
Winkle. In the period between 1968 and 1973 I had written a dozen or so papers and a
monograph containing a series of hypotheses about the role of certain factors in the
nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature, in particular, natural theology,
Malthusianism, political economy, the concept of progress, and the relations between the
history of the earth, biology, psychology, neurology, and wider political and economic
issues in the period, around the general theme of "The Naturalization of Value
Systems in the Human Sciences". This research, and historical and personal issues in
the period around 1968, led me to move away from Darwinian scholarship. Indeed, my subject
was never Darwin. It was always the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature,
and my effort was always to combine a detailed reading of texts with a wider perspective
on the issues. However, the definition of "texts" is itself a contentious issue
in Darwinian scholarship, since my texts have been primarily published ones; in
particular, the debate in the Victorian periodicals, which provided the intellectual
milieu for the debate on mans place in nature, into which the major papers and
monographs were received and which, in turn provided the context for their own views.Returning to these questions after a decade in order to prepare a paper
for this volume and to collect my essays, I felt strongly that there has been a
restriction of framework and perspective. In particular, the general issue of the
nineteenth-century debate on man's place in nature seems to have fallen off the agenda.
The zeal with which current scientists-historians seek to separate Darwin's genius and
achievements from the work, ideas, and influences of Spencer, Chambers, and Wallace seems
to be to betray a pathetic, sycophantic hagiography Great Man history which
I had thought was waning in the history of science, as historians of science thought of
their discipline in terms of the history of ideas, the history of culture, and the history
of society. Indeed, one distinguished biologist-historian concluded his comments by saying
that Darwin was the author of "the greatest and most universal revolution ever
experienced in the history of human thought". I found myself asking, why do we defer
to great men? Why do we defer to working scientists who are part-time historians? Why do
we defer to great men in the history of science? Why do we not consider the social
processes of scientific change in their broadest contexts? Where have these questions gone
in the past decade?In place of these issues, we find that scholars are looking deeper and
deeper and in greater and greater detail into the minutiae of Darwin's notes and thought
processes. What is it that we wish to find there? Is it the key to genius? Why is a higher
and higher power microscope applied to rethinking the thoughts of the "great"?Turning to a more particular issue, I would argue that the influence of
Malthus or of other social and political issues on Darwin's thinking is not an empirical
question in the sense that, for example, De Beer, Mayr, Schweber, or Greene pose it. The
dichotomy between so-called internal and so-called external factors (which I have been
advocating transcending since 1969) neglects two points. First, history including
intellectual history is overdetermined. Of course we can find sufficient factors to
explain the origin and development of Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection
without appealing to Malthus. Indeed, my own reading of what Darwin "got" from
Malthus is remarkably close to interpretations of socalled internalists.As I re-examine my own claims and compare them to those of Mayr and
Schweber, I am at a loss to understand the difference between us. I wrote,
It appears, then, that it was the removal of Malthus's idea of 'moral
restraint, and an emphasis on the concept of 'population pressure' which left a
natural law about plants and animals, that characterized Darwin's interpretation. He was,
in effect, reverting to the purity of the inescapable dilemma of Malthus's first edition.
It is 'the strong law of necessity; which Malthus emphasizes repeatedly in both editions,
even though in the second it lies side by side with the partial palliative of 'moral
restraint'. References with this deterministic basis appear in tens of places in
both editions and might themselves have influenced Darwin's application of the principle
to man... (Young 1969, p. 129)
I go on to point out that Lyell's Principles of Geology was
the work that most influenced Darwin and that there are innumerable references there to
the struggle for existence.I have no quarrel with Mayr's claim that "the role of Malthus was
very much that of a crystal tossed into a saturated fluid" (1982b, p. 493), nor with
Schweber, who says, "It seems to me that the Notebooks support the view that Darwin
was struck with the numerical and deterministic aspects of the Malthusian statement"
(1977, p. 296). Schweber also says,
How much we attribute to the Malthusian insight is to a certain
extent a reflection of our proclivities. My own reading is that the Malthusian statement
gave Darwin the quantitative element he needed to make the theory meet the
standards of theories in the natural sciences. (p. 303)
I find it ironic that the work of David Kohn, which Mayr acidly
contrasts with my own, concludes, "The work of one recent commentator, Robert M.
Young, stands out as nearly definitive" (Mayr 1982b, p. 492; Kohn 1980, p. 142). Kohn
proceeds to characterize the relationship in terms with which I wholly agree (pp.
142 sqq.). This agreement relates to my opposition to attempts to demarcate Darwin's
thinking sharply from ideological connections with his age. De Beer and Schweber are also
at pains to stress that "internal factors" are sufficient to account for
Darwin's concept of natural selection. In varying degrees, they are keen to separate
Darwin's originality and thinking from the age dramatically so in the cases of De
Beer and Mayr, less so in that of Schweber, and not at all in the case of Kohn. The wider
and deeper claim, which some are rejecting, is that the history of science is part of
history; that science is part of culture, not above it, or an alternative to it; that
science is the embodiment of the values of the epoch. It is ever so strange. Scholarship
about ancient Greece and Rome, Islamic science, the Middle Ages, the Renaissance, the
seventeenth and even the eighteenth centuries all take as a premise the thesis that
the intellectual life of the age, including and especially its conceptions of rationality
and of science, were part and parcel of its social and economic structure and value
system. The systems of knowledge are part of the culture of the age. Yet at the same time
there are scholars who know this, but put on blinkers and burrow deeper and deeper into
the minutiae of papers, early drafts, unpublished manuscripts, correspondence and minor
works as if these were not occurring in an age and in a context whose role is not
contextual but constitutive.In Darwin studies a trend has become dominant that would be welcome if
it were not becoming a near orthodoxy. It has been made possible by the publication of
more and more notebooks and early works, especially the M and N Notebooks, Natural
Selection, and other manuscript material. Some, but by no means all, of its
practitioners are people who did graduate work in biology. They are doing important and
interesting research in reconstituting the processes of intellectual development of Darwin
and his colleagues. But this work does not interdigitate or articulate with the wider
issues in the nineteenth century.It appears to me that we are, in the late 1970s and 1980s, in a period
in which scholars are attempting to cultivate their own gardens as a withdrawal from the
social activism of the preceding period. They look at the past in the same terms as they
approach the present. One aspect of this orthodoxy was expressed in some waspish remarks
at the Florence conference. Reference was made to "primary Whiggism", in which
it is claimed that the past leads to the present without any space for the contemporary
context of issues, without any consideration of the "losers in history". The
concept of "secondary Whiggism" was mentioned and also criticized. It is the
belief that a scientist's immature views lead only to his or her mature views. In both
cases the retrospect wipes out the integrity and the texture of the prospect. Whiggism
also implies that people don't hold clear views until they hold the views we remember them
for. Secondary Whiggism, on the other hand, has a tendency to underemphasize people's
mature work and can succumb to the temptation of disappearing without trace into the
minutiae of someone's "immature" thought processes.We can go on with this sort of thinking and produce a notion of
"tertiary Whiggism", which ignores other figures in the period and our hero's
real situation vis-à-vis fame and fortune. A tertiary Whig could leave out the eminence
of a Buckland in the geology of the 1830s and could fail to take seriously the Bridgewater
Treatises. Carrying on, "a quarternary Whiggism" could privilege topics and
issues we consider important and ignore, for example, the role of phrenology in the debate
on man's place in nature.If we look for a way forward in these matters, it would appear
important that people define and defend their reference group. Mine has always been
Victorian culture and the debate on man's place in nature: man, God, nature, society. The
relevant reference group is the debate in the Victorian periodicals. I suspect that the
relevant reference group for some current Darwin scholars is either the peer group of the
scientific community at the time or the peer group of present knowledge.With Whiggism goes positivism. Primary positivism treats facts as
decontextualized from their matrix of meanings and values. Secondary positivism does not
take our hero and his theory out of the context of the scientific community of his time.
No, these are meticulously considered, as are all nuances and contemporary meanings of
theories and concepts, no matter how they have been treated by subsequent history. But,
the secondary positivist draws a sharp boundary around the professional community of
contemporary scientists. The secondary positivist also treats all connections as
contextual and ignores immanent, structural or epochal causality. Therefore, for example,
if there is sufficient evidence in the texts to explain an influence, no consideration is
given to the possibility that other ambient forces might be at work in the intellectual
formation of a scientist. My view is that history is overdetermined: we have more
explanatory factors than we need. Which ones we choose to emphasize and which to
de-emphasize or ignore is a reflection of our political and ideological proclivities.Darwin and Darwinism are important because humanity is part of the
history of life at the same time that human history is an open prospect. Or is it? Does
biology set the limits to destiny? Shall we await the verdicts of the biologists
even the Darwin scholars to set and pursue our social, cultural and political
goals? Marx once said, "We know only a single science: the science of history"
(Marx and Engels 1968, p. 28n). I think the science of history was and should be much
richer than the history of science seems to be making it.When I say Darwinism is social, I mean it in two senses. First,
in Darwin's own work there was never a clear separation of his biological research and
thinking on the one hand, and its origins in and extrapolation to social evolution or
Social Darwinism on the other. I don't find that conclusion very interesting, except as a
stick with which to beat positivists and Whigs of the higher orders. Second, science is social. Of course we can disappear into the texts, but we must ask ourselves
what counts as a text. These were people who read and contributed to Victorian periodicals
and who lived in places that must he for us texts, for example, Shrewsbury, Edinburgh,
Cambridge, the Beagle, London, Down. In the same way that a machine and Victorian
Manchester are "texts" for the social and economic historian, these locations
are texts for a Darwin scholar. These determinations are efficacious, and no amount of
reading Darwin's reading lists and marginal annotations will get us exhaustively through
the determinations of Darwin's thinking, however much we might welcome the interpretation
of marginal notes done by, for example, Gillian Beer, Jim Moore, John Greene, and the
mentor of us all, Sydney Smith.Darwinism is social because science is. And of all science the theory
that links humanity to the history of nature is likely to be most so. Those who wish to
find sciences furthest from society should go to the haven of mathematics and physics, but
alas, even there, there are polluters such as Hodgkin and Forman to show the social
constitution of the issues in those esoteric disciplines.Why not instead join up scholarly traditions and make contact with
political, cultural, literary, and ideological studies of the period? In failing to do so
the orthodoxies of the left and right meet. The scientific left celebrates science and
tries to show that socialism is scientific. The right attempts to defend science and its
autonomy in a way that guarantees that ruling ideas of the prevailing ruling class are
scientific. The history of science, is of course, one battleground in this struggle. At
the moment it appears to me that the right is winning hands down.The connection between these two points is very important. It is
because science is not above history that no clear separation can be made between Darwin's
Darwinism and Darwin's Social Darwinism. That Darwin was a Social Darwinist is not news
however often it is conveniently forgotten. The point about that is a deeper one: the
search for the neat, isolable influence or cleavage plane is a search for a will o' the
wisp. It is a positivist search, and positivism was a historical movement in the
nineteenth century just as physicalism in the philosophy of science was in the
1940s-1960s, with its search for a decontextualized neutral observation language. I fear
that Darwin studies are lapsing into a positivism about the origins, originality, and
unequivocalness of Darwin's theory.I have no quarrel with people who wish to pursue the most detailed
studies of Darwinian texts. I wish only to challenge their doing so in a way that fails to
connect with other dimensions of the determination of scientific, intellectual, and
cultural phenomena. It is important to point out which questions a given social formation
wants through its science to pursue. This broader question extends from the
most general features of its philosophy of nature and society to its most mundane facts.
At the most general level a given socio-economic order a mode of production
constitutes and is constituted by a world view, which includes a framework of assumptions
and methods about what is known, what is discoverable, what it wants to discover, and how
to set about discovering it. At an intermediate level certain sorts of issues preoccupy
investigators at a given phase in the development of the mode of production, reflecting,
in more or less mediated ways, the contradictions of that period. In the eighteenth
century it was classification. In the mid-nineteenth century it was origins the
historicity of genesis of earth, life, mind, and society. In the late nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries it was structures and functions in the psychological and social
sciences with particular emphasis on stability, systems, and equilibria. In our own time
it is mechanisms and abilities the least elements and their recombination to suit
specified needs.These intellectual preoccupations are closely linked (in ways we need
to explicate further) with the development of machinofacture, the division of labor,
de-skilling, and the call for general ability in the society abstract ability for
abstract labor. Scientific research is seeking a secure foundation in our own epoch for
gradations of ability, for élitism (usually at least formally meritocratic), for
hierarchy, for a growing split between mental and manual labor, for dominance and
patriarchy. It seeks to root these social relations in biological givens to
naturalize them. These preoccupations can be seen as our era's analogy to the nineteenth
and early twentieth centuries' attempt to re-base its socioeconomic order on biological,
evolutionary, and physiological equilibria rather than the deistic principle. Competitive
individualism and functionalist views of the social order, cohesion and progress, were
more consistent with an urban industrialism and mobility of labor than with the rural
pastoral order that suited a deistic age of fixed, classified social stasis the
world of Paley. Looking at the issue and attempting to conduct the ideological battle on
this terrain makes it completely unsurprising that investigators whose disciplines
however unself-consciously favour the exisitng socioeconomic order will propose and
defend certain inquiries, and that radicals and some liberals will not. This is not just
to prove them wrong at the empirical or even the conceptual level but to say it is wrong
to ask such questions in isolation and to pursue whole areas in inquiry in a blinkered
way. Nor is it because one group is right and the other wrong, but because they have
starkly conflicting visions of the social order that throw up starkly different issues for
scientists and historians to pursue. The debate, therefore, becomes one between competing
ideologies and interest groups. My own perception of it is that it is a conflict between
those scholars concerned with the struggle for socialism and those concerned with the
struggle for existence.
REFERENCES
Anon. (1978) A Genetic Defence of the Free Market, Business Week, 10
April, pp. 103-104.Anon. (1980) Editorial. Computer Weekly, 24 January.Bannister, Robert C. (1979). Social Darwinism: Science and Myth in Anglo-American
Social Thought. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Beishon, J. and Peters, G., eds. (1972) Systems Behavior. New York: Harper &
Row. Chant, Colin, and Fauvel, John, eds. (1980). Darwin to Einstein: Historical Studies
on Science and Belief. Longman/Open University Press. Clarke, Simon (1977). Marxism, Sociology and Poulantzas' Theory of the
State, Capital & Class no. 2: 1-31. Darwin, Charles (1967). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or
the Preservation of FavouredRaces in the Struggle for Life (1859). Facsimile reprint. New
York: Athenaeum; 6th ed. (1872a). Murray. Darwin, Charles (1874). The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex (1871), 2nd ed. Murray. Darwin, Francis, ed. (1887). The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, 3rd ed. 3
Vols. Murray. Darwin, Francis, and Seward, A. C., eds. (1903). More Letters of Charles Darwin. 2
vols. Murray. de Beer, Sir Gavin, ed. (1960-1). "Darwin's Notebooks on Transmutation of
Species." Parts 1-5. Bulletin of the British Museum (Natural History) Historical
Series 2, nos. 2-6. de Beer, Sir Gavin et al., eds. (1967). "Darwin's Notebooks on Transmutation of
Species. Part 6. Pages Excised by Darwin." Bulletin of the British Museum (Natural
History) Historical Series. 3, no. 5. Emery, F. E., ed. (1969) Systems Thinking: Selected Readings. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.Ghiselin, M. T. (1974a) The Economy of Nature and the Evolution of Sex. Berkeley:
University of California Press. Greene, John C. (1959). "Biology and Social Theory in the Nineteenth Century:
Auguste Comte and HerbertSpencer." In M. Clagett, ed., Critical Problems in the History of Science,
pp. 419-46. Madison: University ofWisconsin Press. Reprinted in Greene (1981), pp. 60-94. Greene, John C. (1977). "Darwin as a Social Evolutionist." J. Hist. Biol. 10:
1-27. Reprinted in Greene (1981), pp.Greene, John C. (1981). Science, Ideology and World View: Essays in the History of
Evolutionary Ideas. Berkeley: University of California Press. Haraway, Donna J. (1981-82) The High Cost of Information in Post-World War II
Evolutionary Biology: Ergonomics, Semiotics and the Sociobiology of Communications
Systems, Philos. Forum 13: 244-78.Heyl, Barbara S. (1980). "The Harvard 'Pareto Circle."' J. Hist. Behav.
Sci. 4 (1968): 316-34. Reprinted in Chant and Fauvel (1980), pp. 135-55. Hirshleifer, J. (1977) Economics from a Biological Point of View, J. Law
and Econ. 20: 1-52.Hutton, R. H. (1885). The Metaphysical Society: A Reminiscence. Nineteenth
Century 18: 177-96. Huxley, T. H. (1865) Emancipation Black and White, The Reader 20
May 1865. Reprinted in Lay Sermons, Addresses and Reviews, 3rd ed., pp. 17-23.
London: Macmillan.Jones, Greta (1980). Social Darwinism and English Thought: The Interaction between
Biological and Social Theory. Hassocks, Sussex: Harvester. Kalikow, T. J. (1978) Konrad Lorenzs "Brown Past": a Reply to
Alec Nisbett, J. Hist Behav. Sci. 14: 173-80.Kohn, David (1980) Theories to Work By: Rejected Theories, Reproduction, and
Darwins Path to Natural Selection, Stud. Hist. Biol. 4: 67-170. Lyell, Charles (1830-3). Principles of Geology, being an Attempt to Explain the
Former Changes of the Earth's Surface by Reference to Causes Now in Operation. 3 vols.
Murray; also 2nd ed., 3 vols. (1833). [Malthus, Thomas R.] (1798). An Essay on the Principle of Population, as it Affects
the Future Improvement of Society, with Remarks on the Speculations of Mr. Godwin, M.
Condorcet, and Other Writers. J. Johnson. Reprint. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press
(1959). Malthus, Thomas R. (1826). An Essay on the Principle of Population; or, a View of
Its Past and Present Effects on Human Happiness; an Inquiry into Our Prospects Respecting
the Future Removal or Mitigation of the Evils which It Occasions, 6th ed. 2 vols. Murray. Marx, Karl (1961) Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. Moscow: Foreign
Languages Publishing House. Mark, Karl and Engels, Frederick (1965) Selected Correspondence, 2nd ed. Moscow:
Progress. Marx, Karl And Engels, Frederick (1968) The German Ideology. Moscow: Progress. Mayr, Ernst (1982b) The Growth of Biological Thought. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press. Paley, William (1816). Natural Theology.. or, Evidences of the Existence and
Attributes of the Deity. Collected from the Appearances of Nature (1802), new ed. Baynes. Peckham, Morse, ed. (1959). The Origin of Species by Charles Darwin: A Variorum
Text. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. (1935) On the Concept of Function in Social Science,
in Structures and Functions in Primitive Societies: Essays and Addresses. London:
Cohen and West, 1952, pp. 178-187.Radical Science Journal Collective (1981) Science, Technology, Medicine and the
Socialist Movement, Radical Science J. 11: 3-70.Russett, Cynthia E. (1966). The Concept of Equilibrium in American Social Thought. New
Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press. Schweber, Silvan S. (1977). "The Origin of the Origin Revisited." J. Hist.
Biol. 10: 229-316. Spencer, Herbert (1851). Social Statics: or, The Conditions Essential to Human
Happiness Specified, and the First of Them Developed. London: John Chapman. [Spencer, Herbert (1857). "Progress: Its Law and Cause." Westminster Rev.
II: 445-85; reprinted in Spencer, 1901. Spencer, Herbert (1901). Essays: Scientific, Political and Speculative. 3 vols.
Williams & Norgate. Stauffer, R. C., ed. (1975) Charles Darwins Natural Selection, being the
second part of his big Species book written from 1856 to 1858. London: Cambridge
University Press. Thompson, E. P. (1978). The Poverty of Theory and Other Essays. Merlin. Verrall, R. (1979) Sociobiology: the Instincts in our Genes, Spearhead (March):
10-11.Wilson, Edward O. (1975) Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press. Wilson, Edward O. (1978) On Human Nature. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Young, Robert M. (1967a). "Animal Soul." In P. Edwards, ed., The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York: Macmillan, vol. 1, pp. 122-27. Young, Robert M. (1967b). "Philosophy of Mind and Related Issues." Brit.
J. Philos. Sci. 18: 325-30. Young, Robert M. (1968b) The Development of Herbert Spencers Concept of
Evolution, in Actes du XIe Congrès Internationale du Histoire des Sciences..
Paris: Blanchard, vol. 2, pp. 273-78. Young, Robert M. (1969) Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of
Biological and Social Theory, Past & Present 43: 109-145.Young, Robert M. (1970a) Mind, Brain and Adaptation: Cerebral Localization and Its
Biological Context from Gall to Ferrier. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Young, Robert M. (1970b) The Impact of Darwin on Conventional Thought, in
A. Symondson, ed., The Victorian Crisis of Faith. London: SPCK., pp. 13-35.Young, Robert M. (1973a) The Historiographic and Ideological Contexts of the
Nineteenth-century Debate on Mans Place in Nature, in M. Teich and R. M.
Young, Eds., Changing Perspectives in the History of Science: Essays in Honour of
Joseph Needham. London: Heinemann, pp. 344-438.Young, Robert M. (1973b) The Role of Psychology in the Evolutionary Debate,
in M. Henle et al., eds., Historical Conceptions of Psychology. New York:
Springer, pp. 180-204. Young, Robert M. (1973c) Association of Ideas, in P. P. Wiener, ed., Dictionary
of the History of Ideas. New York: Charles Scribners Sons, vol. 1, pp. 111-118.Young, Robert M. (1973d) The Human Limits of Nature, in J. Benthall, ed., The
Limits of Human Nature. London: Allen Lane, pp. 235-274Young, Robert M. (1977) Science is Social Relations Rad. Sci. J. 5:
65-129.Young, Robert M. (1979) Science is a Labour Process, Sci. for People 43/44:
31-37. Young, Robert M. (1981). The Naturalisation of Value Systems in the Human
Sciences, in Problems in the Biological and Human Sciences. Block VI of Open
University Course, Science and Belief. from Darwin to Einstein. Milton Keynes: Open
University Press, pp. 63-110. Young, Robert M. (1982a) How Societies Constitute Their Knowledge.
Unpublished manuscript.Young, Robert M. (1982b) The Darwin Debate, Marxism Today 26(4):
20-22.
Young, Robert M. (1982c) Is Nature a Labour Process?, in L. Levidow and R. M.
Young, eds., Science, Technology and the Labour Process: Marxist Studies, Vol. II. London:
Free Association Books, pp. 206-32.
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|