Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Robert M. Young Online Writings
THE CONCEPT OF PSYCHOPATHOLOGY: A CRITIQUE
by Robert M. Young
This is the first chapter of a book which will concist of five chapters
exploring the concept of psychopathology.. At the risk of trying your patience, I'm
spending this first chapter entirely on the term and concept. of psychopathology I
hope you'll agree with good reason. My purpose is to convey something about the
historicity of ideas in psychoanalysis and how they appear to differ from how we think
about concepts in natural science. In my opinion, this is both philosophically and
clinically important. Concepts including scientific and clinical ones are
part of culture and subject to contending values and interests.
I think it is relevant how I came to be thinking abut this matter. I
had for some years been doing some lecturing for a psychotherapy training organization,
the London Centre for Psychotherapy. However, when they rang me up the next year I could
not do what they asked for a reason I cant recall. Then would you be
willing to give five lectures on Psychopathology? I accepted, put the
phone down and instantly felt that I knew nothing about the topic. Not being known for my
diffidence, I thought this odd and bewildering. Id been studying various aspects of
abnormal psychology, neurology, psychiatry, psychoanalysis and psychotherapy, as well as
the broader intellectual, cultural and ideological aspects of these disciplines for about
four decades. Why, then, was I diffident?
My reaction was to go out and buy a copy of DSM III-R, the Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual of Mental Diseases (Third Edition-Revised) (APA, 1987), which
is published by the American Psychiatric Association. This is something which I had never
before contemplated doing, I also bought an up-to-date textbook of Psychiatry, the UCH
Textbook of Psychiatry (Wolff et al., 1990). I had not bought a textbook
of psychiatry since I was a student in medical school the 1950s. I report these things
because of how strikingly they convey the separation between the assumptive worlds of
psychotherapy and psychiatry.
As it happens, neither book has the term psychopathology in
its index. Nor is it in the glossary of the textbook. That led me to feel that the concept
may be passé. That turns out not to be right, but in order to get a handle on why this is
so, it is necessary to take a long conceptual and historical detour.
What is packed into the concept of psychopathology? First, it implies a
medical model. There are two central points about the juxtaposition of psyche with
pathology. The first is a distinction between the normal and the abnormal or pathological.
The second is an analogy between psychic processes and somatic ones. Psychopathology draws
on an analogy to cellular pathology, a discipline which was only founded in the the
nineteenth century in the work of Bichat, Cruveilhier and Virchow (ref), who made it
possible to make diagnoses on the basis of specific observable characteristics of organs,
tissues and cells. Some date modern scientific medicine from this period in which diseases
were linked to highly specific lesions.
It doesnt take much reflection to realize that there is something
odd about this analogy, but when you ask what to do instead of making it, you come upon a
deep feature of the legacy of the mind-body problem as bequeathed to modern thought by
René Descartes (1637). He defined mind negatively as that which does not have the
attributes of matter. When people have sought to think scientifically about mind, they
soon discover that it has no language of its own which resonates with the scientific
languages used in thinking about bodies. So they reach for analogies. You could say that
these analogies provide much of the history of psychology. If you look closely at the
analogies which are employed, you see a parallel to the history of the physico-chemical
and biological sciences. Locke (1690) saw himself as an under-labourer to Newtonian
physics. He and the other practitioners of a set of enquiries in epistemology and
psychology, drew on the billiard-ball physics of the turn of the eighteenth century and
offered the notion of the association of ideas. Ideas impacted on one another;
memory was seen as somehow consequence of repetition of these impacts. This notion led to
a model which was elaborated by Étienne Condillac (1754)and others but systematically
developed by David Hartley in his Observations on Man, His Frame, His Duty and His
Expectations (1749), which was the treatise which inspired the associationist
tradition in empiricist psychology in the work of James Mill, John Stuart Mill, Alexander
Bain and Herbert Spencer (Ribot, 1873; Warren, 1921; Young, 1970, chs. 2, 3, 5). In fact,
Locke first used the association of ideas to explain wrong-headed connections, but the
model soon came to be extended until it became the foundation for all thought and
feelings. The major systematic psychology treatise before the advent of the theory of
evolution was written by Alexander Bain and used associationism to explain The Senses
and the Intellect (1855) and The Emotions and the Will (1859).
In the course of the nineteenth century and after, analogies were also
drawn between mental processes and chemistry, so that we have ideas of mental elements,
mental compounds, mental chemistry. A parallel process was occurring in which further
analogies were drawn from physiology, involving mental structures and functions. And then
came analogies from evolution, e.g., mental development and evolution and adaptation. More
recently, information theory and cybernetics have provided a fund of analogies, and much
of current psychology involves cognitive modelling based on analogies to digital
computing. I will return to these analogies below.
In addition to the dichotomy between the normal and the pathological
and the analogy between somatic and psychic processes, there is lurking around somewhere a
third feature of psychopathology, the disease-syndrome model. Specific constellations of
psychopathologies lead to diagnoses of mental disorders or diseases.
To be normal is to be in physiological and psychological balance. There
is also more than one ambiguity around the term normal. It can mean average,
as in the case of lying within a statistical range designated as normal, e.g., normal
intelligence or normal blood sugar of heart rate or pulse or height. It can mean normal
according to some criterion which few meet, e.g., within healthy weight limits in a
society where many or most are overweight. It can also mean not deviant, as in
conformist, not rebellious, obeying norms of behaviour. This often boils down to whether
or not the speaker approves of the person in question., e.g., I dont want you
going out with him; people who have rings in their noses arent normal.. These
meanings merge into one another in everyday speech. In physiological discourse, normal
usually means falling within limits which are taken to be usual in a healthy person, free
of perturbation. Important physiological concepts lie behind this designation., for
example, the milieu interieur or internal environment of Claude Bernard (18xx) and
the concept of homeostasis of Walter Cannon (1932). These refer to the
bodys stabilising mechanisms for keeping all sorts of physiological variables within
certain limits. Beyond this there are relations with the external environment, and once
again there is an elision between physiological, psychological and social evaluations:
healthy/adapted. adjusted.
In disease something occurs which upsets these equilibria. There are
several sorts of causes: infective, invasive, degenerative, assaultive, autoimmune,
genetic.
All of these concepts can be and have been applied to social phenomena.
Lemert wrote a book in 1948 entitled Social Pathology . Barbara Wootton published Social
Science and Social pathology in 1959. Baintons The Anatomy of Revolution (19xx) used anatomical concepts to write about social upheaval, while Coser wrote about The
Function of Social Conflict (1956).
So, starting from the oddity of juxtaposing psyche with pathology,
we have found many instances of the mixing up of mental language with biological and
medical concepts. All of these are heirs to a parent tradition known as functionalism (which I examine more extensively in Young, 1981 and 1989). It is a very widespread
way of thinking in the human sciences which is based on physiological models from the
early nineteenth century and evolutionary ones from mid-century. Franz Joseph Gall, the
founder of modern brain research and of phrenology, established a model for thinking about
the mind and the brain whereby the parts of the brain were seen as separate (though
interrelated) organs, and their activities were functions Young, 1968, 1970, ch. 1). This
extended the organ-function paradigm from stomach/digestion and kidney/filtration to so
that it could be argued that the categories of character and personality were functions of
the brain. This way of thinking was taken up by enlightened figures, such as Auguste Comte
, the founder of positivism (Greene, 1959), in France and G. H. Lewes, a prolific English
popularise in physiology and philosophy (Ashton, 1991). For our purposes, one particular
set of influences was crucial, since it was taken up by the father of evolutionary
associationism in psychology, Herbert Spencer, adopted from him by the eminent
neurologist, John Hughlings Jackson (Young, 1970, ch. 6), and found its way into the first
book of an impecunious researcher on the nervous system who would have to give up his
research at the lab bench and earn his way as a clinician in Vienna. Sigmund Freuds
first monograph, published in 1891, when he was 35, was entitled On Aphasia: a Critical
Study. This book brought functional thinking into the foundations of the ideas of the
person who, four years later, would co-author the first psychoanalytic book, Studies on
Hysteria. (Breuer & Freud, 1895)
It would not be possible to over-emphasize the pervasiveness of the
functionalist paradigm. Perhaps the most efficient way of grasping its essence is by
examining a few paragraphs from Herbert Spencer. In his first book, published in 1851,
with the scientistic title Social Statics, Spencer wrote:
We commonly enough compare a nation to a living organism. We speak of
the body politic, of the functions of its several parts, of its growth, and of
its diseases, as though it were a creature. But we usually employ these expressions as
metaphors, little suspecting how close is the analogy, and how far it will bear carrying
out. So completely, however, is a society organized upon the same system as an individual
being, that we may almost say there is something more than analogy between them. (Spencer,
1851, p. 448)
A FUNCTION to each organ, and each organ to its own function, is the
law of all organization. To do its work well, an apparatus must possess special fitness
for that work; and this will amount to unfitness for any other work. The lungs cannot
digest, the heart cannot respire, the stomach cannot propel blood. Each muscle and each
gland must have its own particular nerve. There is not a fibre in the body but what has a
channel to bring it food, a channel to take its food away, an agency for causing it to
assimilate nutriment, an agency for stimulating it to perform its peculiar duty, and a
mechanism to take away effete matter; not one of which can be dispensed with. Between
creatures of the lowest type, and creatures of the highest, we similarly find the
essential difference to be, that in the one the vital actions are severally decomposed
into their component parts, and each of these parts has an agent to itself. In
organizations of another order the same principle is apparent. (Spencer 1851, p. 274)
The date of Social Statics is important seven years
before the announcement of natural selection theory in the joint Darwin-Wallace paper of
1858, in which they announced the theory of organic evolution by means of natural
selection. In On the Origin of Species, published a year later, Darwin had only one
sentence on man, and in later editions he extended it with a tribute to Spencer: In
the future I see open fields for far more important researches. Psychology will be
securely based on the foundation already well laid by Mr. Herbert Spencer...
(Darwin, 1872, p. xxx)
By 1860 there was no coyness about analogies or metaphors in
Spencers writing. He discussed 'The Social Organism' in evolutionary terms, freely
mixing biological and social language:
Societies slowly augment in mass; they progress in complexity of
structure, at the same time their parts become more mutually dependent, their living units
are removed and replaced without destroying their integrity; and the extents these
peculiarities are proportionate to their vital activities.
These are traits that societies have in common with organic bodies. And
these traits in which they agree with organic bodies and disagree with all other things,
entirely subordinate the minor distinctions: such distinctions being scarcely greater than
those which separate one half of the organic kingdom from the other. The principles of organization are the same and the differences are simply differences of application
(Spencer, 1860, p. 206).
Having established the common principles, Spencer feels able to
pronounce with confidence on social and economic forms particularly the ones which
were in greatest need of justification because of the effects of the industrial revolution
on jobs and the social order:
The doctrine of the progressive division of labour, to which we are
here introduced, is familiar to all readers. And further, the analogy between the
economical division of labour and the physiological division of labour, is so
striking as long since to have drawn the attention of scientific naturalists: so striking,
indeed, that the expression physiological division of labour, has been
suggested by it. It is not needful, therefore, to treat this part of the subject in great
detail. (Spencer, 1860, pp. 211-12) .
Thinking in terms of biological and medical analogies became pervasive
in the next few decades. In particular, it was central to Emile Durkheims thinking
in The Rules of Sociological Method (1895).
Briefly, for societies, as for individuals, health is good and
desirable; disease on the contrary, is bad and to be avoided. If, then, we can find an
objective criterion, inherent in the facts themselves, which enables us to
distinguish scientifically between health and morbidity in the various orders of social
phenomena, science will be in a position to throw light on practical problems and still
remain faithful to its own method (Durkheim, 1895, p. 49).
We shall call 'normal' these social conditions that are the most
generally distributed, and the others 'morbid' or 'pathological'. If we designate as
'average type' that hypothetical being that is constructed by assembling in the same
individual, the most frequent forms, one may say that the normal type merges with the
average type, and that every deviation from this standard of health is a morbid
phenomenon.... It is the function of the average organism that the physiologist studies;
and the sociologist does the same (ibid., pp. 55-6).
The healthy constitutes the norm par excellence and can
consequently be in no way abnormal (ibid., p. 58).
Now, it is important, from the very beginning of research, to be able
to classify facts as normal and abnormal, save for the few exceptional cases, so that the
proper domains can be assigned to physiology and pathology, respectively (ibid., p. 63).
The various principles we have established up to the present are, then,
closely interconnected. In order that sociology may be a true science of things, the
generality of phenomena must be taken as a criterion of their normality (ibid., pp.
74-75).
By the 1930s the leading figure in social anthropology, A. R.
Radcliffe-Brown, who had taught in many academic centres, including holding the chair at
Oxford, was applying concepts from evolutionary theory and physiology directly to
societies and advocating this model as foundational for social science. Radcliffe-Brown
drew his idea of social evolution directly from Spencer and his ideas of social process,
structure and function directly from physiology. I mean this quite unequivocally. He wrote
in the Introduction to Structure and Function in Primitive Society (1952),
In reference to social systems and their theoretical understanding one
way of using the concept of functions is the same as its scientific use in physiology. It
can be used too refer to the interconnection between the social structure and the process
of social life. It is this use of the word function that seems to me to make it a useful
term in comparative sociology. The three concepts of process, structure and function are
thus components of a single theory as a scheme of interpretation of human social systems.
These three concepts are logically interconnected, since function is used to
refer to the relations of process and structure. The theory is one that we can apply to
the study both of continuity in forms of social life and also to processes of change in
those forms (p. 12).
In his highly influential essay, On the Concept of Structure in
Social Science Radcliffe-Brown begins, The concept of function applied to
human societies is based on an analogy between social life and organic life (p.
178). The task of social science is to see social life as a functional unity and to seek
out the functional role of any phenomenon as a contribution to that unity (p. 185).
By the definition here offered function is the contribution
which a partial activity makes to the total activity of which it is a part. The function
of a particular social usage is the contribution it makes to the total social life as the
functioning of the total social system. Such a view implies that a social system (the
total social structure of a society together with the totality of social usages to which
that structure appears and on which it depends for its continued existence) has a certain
kind of unity, which we may speak of as functional unity. We may define it as a condition
in which all parts of the social system work together with a sufficient degree of harmony
or internal consistency, i.e., without producing persistent conflicts which can neither be
resolved nor regulated (p. 181).
Functionalists in America supplemented this rhetoric with ideas drawn
from the research of eminent scientists at Harvard, Lawrence J. Henderson, who wrote on The
Fitness of the Environment (1913), and Walter B. Cannon, author of The
Wisdom of the Body (1932).. Both emphasized equilibrium, both intermixed social
and physiological concepts and both fed the widening stream which became the functionalist
tradition. Their physiological writings were routinely quoted by social scientists, and
Henderson later wrote both as a physiological and as a social scientist (Henderson, 1970;
Cross & Albury, 1987)). It has been pointed out in a remarkable piece of scholarly
research that a circle of scholars to which he was central was the cradle of much of the
influence of functionalism in American social science (Heyl, 1968). Functionalist thinking
became pervasive in psychology, sociology, anthropology, architecture, town planning,
economics, history and sociology of science and systems theory. It remained so until the
1970s (Martindale, 1965; Demerath & Peterson, 1967; Gouldner, 1971).
Functionalism has certain noteworthy features. It takes the organismic
and holistic points of view as given. It is therefore practically impossible to think in
revolutionary terms within this framework of ideas. Everything is expressed in terms of
parts and wholes, the contribution of the part to the whole, equilibria and
self-correcting mechanisms (Russett, 1966). There is no place for contradictions or
dialectical thinking. It is a philosophy for the slowly evolving status quo,
palliative in its view of conflict. Fundamental social change of the mode of production is
almost literally unthinkable (Mils, 1964, 1970; Gouldner, 1971; Young, 1981).
The spread of this way of thinking was not random. It became quite
explicitly the preferred approach of the Rockefeller charities, the funding agency which
paved the way for national government support for research (Kohler, 1991). It led to the
founding of great institutions: Yales Institute of Human Relations, Londons
Tavistock Institute of Human Relations, The London School of Hygiene and Tropical Medicine
(Brown, 1979a, 1979b). There were similar institutions at Harvard, in France, in China.
Rockefeller money founded sociobiology and supported x-ray crystallography. James Watson
was on a Rockefeller fellowship when he co-discovered the structure of DNA. This approach
reduced the human to the physiological and the physiological to the biochemical and the
molecular. The breadth and depth of this tradition, along with the ideological forces
which evoked and constituted it are most clearly made apparent in Donna Haraways.
All of this approaches human nature and society in ways which are in contrast to prose,
narrative, stories, humanism, yarns.
I dare say you may feel that I have taken you down a long side-track,
but I have not. The concept of psychopathology only makes sense in the context of the
functionalist tradition. The easy linkage of the psychological with the pathological
requires that it be commonplace to juxtapose mental (I almost write mental
functioning) with physiological, and mental distress (dysfunction) with
disease (pathology),
Let us now turn to psychopathology per se. Its literal etymology
is knowledge (logos) of the suffering (pathein) of the psyche. As Levin puts
it in a most interesting essay, it is all the ways of hiding, manifesting, communicating,
sharing and, in brief, living out the minds experience of worldly suffering (p. 2).
The term came into English as a transliteration of a German text by Baron Ernst von
Feuchsterleben in 1847. Such analogies were rife. Thomas Mayo write on The Pathology of
the Human Mind in 1838 and used the concept mental pathology. Henry
Holland wrote a book on Mental Physiology in 1852, and Henry Maudsley (after whom
the London hospital is named) wrote Physiology and Pathology of Mind in 1867. From
Galls idea that thought is a function of the brain, and the brain is the organ of
mind, there was a progressive movement of this paradigm throughout the nervous system and
outwards into the psychological and social sciences. Freud was heir to this tradition and
adopted the concept of psychophysical parallelism as his own approach to the mind-body
problem, which meant that there was no need to translate between mental and physical.
Indeed, functionalist thinking made them appear so nearly identical that one hardly felt
the need.
I trust that you will grant by now that quite a lot is tucked away into
this term. Here is a definition from a 1901 Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology:
the general study of diseased mental conditions; a synonym of
psychiatry and abnormal psychology, but rather more comprehensive that either, because it
emphasizes the general scientific study of all forms of mental aberration. Its more
precise synonym is mental pathology.. {Note the presence here of the concepts of disease,
abnormality, pathology.] The term psychopathist is sometimes used as a synonym for
psychiatrist (Baldwin, vol. 2, pp. 391-92).
Janet and Dunn founded a French journal of abnormal and pathological
psychology in 1903. A lectureship in psychopathology was established in Cambridge in 1923.
Hart says in 1927 that psychopathology is not a mere description but an attempt to explain
disorders in terms of psychological processes (Berrios, .p. 233). William McDougall, the
most eminent polymath in the human sciences of his era, quotes Bleuler with approval in
1926: one of the most important, if not the most important, of all paths to a
knowledge of the human soul is by way of psychopathology (Berrios, p,. 235). A
decade later it is scientized by Malamud: a science that deals with the recognition,
description, classification and understanding of phenomena of mental activity
(Berrios, p. 237).
This brings us to a fourth main feature to put alongside the
distinction between the normal and the pathological, the analogy to somatic medicine and
the disease/syndrome model: classification or nosology, the search for a natural
classification. Science seeks types, pigeon-holes, lists, differential diagnoses.
Thats what DSM III-R is, but there are things to be learned from the fact
that it is an evolving one. The first edition appeared in 1952; the second was in
1968 and was based on the eighth edition of the International Classification of Diseases.
The third edition appeared in 1979, was revised in 1987, and the fourth edition was
published in 1994. You might say that reflects a lot of accumulated knowledge, but the
history of such compendiums is more complex and interesting than that. It is not just that
knowledge accumulates. Another process is going on as well: the terms of reference of the
classification are historically relative and mutate.
A helpful analogy is the history of encyclopaedias. I am a collector of The Encyclopaedia Britannica. I have the seventh, eighth, ninth, tenth, eleventh
and fourteenth editions. You may think this excessively pack-rattish of me, but I have a
good reason. I am, among other things, a scholar of ideas abut nature and human nature in
the nineteenth century. The last volumes of the eighth edition went to press in 1859. It
contained a large article entitled Deluge, in which the history of discoveries
in geology were spelled out in Biblical terms (Anon., 1854). The ninth edition has no
article on the Biblical Deluge, but it has a long two-part article on
Evolution: Evolution in Biology, penned by T. H. Huxley
(Darwins loyal publicist), and on Evolution in Philosophy by James Sully
(Huxley, 1979; Sully, 1979). Knowledge does not just accumulate: the parameters of
knowledge change. Indeed, a whole volume of introductory essays taking an overview of
changing fields of knowledge had been a feature of successive editions of the Britannica for some time.
It is the same with psychiatric diagnosis. There is a rich and growing
literature on the historicity of psychiatric disease categories. One of the best studies
is Elaine Showalters (1985) careful exploration of the rise of hysteria: The
Female Malady: Women, Madness and English Culture, 1830-1980. She points out that the
World War I diagnosis of Shell shock was the male counterpart of hysteria, a
discourse of masculinity addressed to patriarchal thought and adds, but it was
scarcely possible for either male patients or male psychiatrists, themselves deeply
implicated in patriarchal structures, to see its meanings (Showalter, 1987, p. 194). Allen
Young has written a work of searching scholarship on Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder
(PTSD), a diagnosis which, in an immediate sense, grew out of the Vietnam War and which
has since become the basis of a burgeoning industry of publication and treatment. The main
roots of PTSD included the self-same story of World War I psychoneuroses, in particular
shell shock and related disorders emanating from that dreadful conflict where people were
daily blown to pieces in their thousands. He entitles his study The Harmony of
Illusions, with the subtitle, Inventing Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder (A.
Young, 1995). The first phrase was used by another scholar to point to the
illusiveness of facts, while the second starkly alludes to the social construction of
disease categories. They are no less real, but the sense in which they are true remains
unclear (A, Young, 1995, pp. 9-10). A third diagnosis which has undergone extensive study
as an historical and cultural phenomenon is Multiple Personality Disorder (MPD), which has
benefited from the philosophical ruminations of Ian Hacking (1992, 1995) and from the
anthropological contextualisation of Roland Littlewood (1966, 1998).
.There are other examples of this historicity and relativity.
Homosexuality was a mental disease in the 1960s; then it disappeared from DSM. Actually
ego-syntonic (at peace with ones self) disappeared. Ego-dystonic homosexuality
remains (Abelove, 1986). I have a whole volume in which the validity of the concept of
borderline disorder is debated (silver & Rosenbleuth, 1992). It includes a
chapter wherein Alex Tarnopolsky says that this concept is not much used in Britain, and
he claims that the Kleinian concept of pathological organisation does a better
job of accounting for the phenomena usually called borderline (Tarnopolsky,
1992, 1992a).
We are faced here with the relativity and the historicity of disease
concepts. Homosexuality ceased to be classified as a disease because of changing social
values and political agitation. You may think this feature which distinguishes diagnoses
in psychiatry from those in somatic medicine, but youd be wrong. In a fascinating
series of papers, Karl Figlio has shown that disease categories in somatic medicine come
and go. He traces the rise of two disorders, chlorisis (a fainting disorder common in
housemaids) and miners nystagmus (a jerking of the eyes commonly seen in miners).
They appear, wax, wane, get re-classified as functional nervous disorders and quietly
disappear from the textbooks of somatic medicine Figlio, 1978. 1982, 1985). If we take
seriously the historicity and cultural relativity of disease entities, then the idea that
the classifications could tell us about natural kinds, as the classifications of
elementary particles in physics, the Periodic Table of Elements in chemistry and the
taxonomy of species in biological taxonomy claim to do, we will be disappointed. Then what
is the status of the categories of psychopathology? I shall argue that they are
rabbit/ducks, i.e., gestalt-switch figures which in this case look like one thing when
viewed clinically and another when viewed nosologically. A binocular approach strikes me
as the best way of thinking about the phenomena we call psychopathological, and I shall
argue that we are better at our jobs as therapists when we think in dynamic terms rather
than in the static terms the classifiers have been prone to employ.
Lets take a quick tour of some recent literature. My textbook of
psychiatry when I was a medical student had one reference to psychopathology in its index
- to page one: that branch of science that deals with the principles of abnormal
behavior, or... the science of disordered functioning of the personality (Noyes
& Kolb, 1958). One reference covers the lot. A text from the same period had
psychopathology as a main entry, followed by of- and lists every disorder
(Ewalt et al., 1957).. A comprehensive dictionary of the same period designates
psychopathology as the science, with respect to which clinical psychology and psychiatry
are technologies (English & English, 1958). Something similar happens in Harold
Searles classic collection on Countertransference (1979). One entry refers
the reader to borderline patients, neuroses, psychoses, schizophrenia. In Greenberg and
Mitchells excellent Object Relations in Psychoanalytic Theory (1983)
psychopathology is a main index entry, touching on all the theorists discussed. The
interdigitation of the physiological and the psychological is quite explicit and still in
use. Taylors Psychopathology, published in 1966, includes the phrase
physiology of mind.
The index in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Works of Sigmund Freud has only one entry - to Freuds first paper on
psychopathology, the implication being that the rest are on it, too. It also forms the
middle of the three portions of his 1895 Project for a Scientific Psychology,
based on neuroanatomy, which he abandoned when he turned to exclusive reference to the
psychic side of his psychophysical parallelism. Yet the concept does not appear n
Winnicotts works, nor in Laplanche and Pontalis definitive dictionary of
orthodox psychoanalysis or Hinshelwoods on Kleinian theory or in Massermans
classic text (or its glossary) or Fenichels. Indeed, if you plow through the
forty-three pages of references in DSM III-R, you will find only four references to
it. It is not in Peter Gays excellent biography of Freud, except to refer to The
Psychopathology of Everyday Life (Freuds only title employing the term).
So it is something between everything and nothing. We have
functioning normal and disordered. Disordered is psychopathology. Thinking in terms
of this dichotomy keeps coming up. Although most say that the line is hard to draw, they
are looking for it.
Where does psychopathology come from? Eric Rayner says it comes from
repression (Rayner, 1991, p. 24), but it gets more complicated later on. The
British Independent psychoanalysts root it in external object relations, Bowlby and Alice
Miller attribute it to real traumatic experiences, Kleinians to the conflict between
impulses derived from the life and death instincts. Greenberg and Mitchell (1983, pp.
135-6) say that Klein attributes the main causation of psychopathology to factors arising
primarily in the internal world. It is clear that when we seek to fathom aetiology, we are
quickly up to our necks in controversy.
I am trying to convey something about the conceptual language of
psychoanalysis, psychiatry and the human sciences generally. German Berrios, who has
devoted considerable efforts to tracing the history of concepts in psychopathology, opines
that the persistence of psychopathology in British psychiatry can be
attributed to the empiricist false consciousness seeking theory-neutral statements. The
effort to describe and classify frees one from understanding, process, dynamics and
aetiology (Berrios, 1991, pp. 241-42). Indeed, if you look at the aetiologies of mental
disorders as listed in DSM III-R, you will find that most are unknown (APA,
1987, pp. xxii-xxiii). Once again, the syndromes listed in this compendium are presented
as if they were natural kinds, but we can easily see that they are nothing of the sort.
They are inside history and inside culture. During the nineteenth century in America there
was a mental disease in the textbooks called dropitomania, defined as the
compulsive need on the part of mentally deranged slaves to run away. When I first worked
in a mental hospital in Arizona in 1955, some patients; charts listed as diagnoses
priapism and nymphomania, patterns of behaviour which were
relatively valued just over a decade later.
Diagnoses which are contentious from a commonsense point of view have
not disappeared from psychiatric classification. Here are the diagnostic criteria for
Self-Defeating Personality Disorder:
A. A pervasive pattern of self-defeating behavior, beginning by early
adulthood and present in a variety of contexts. The person may often avoid or undermine
pleasurable experiences, be drawn to situations or relationships in which he or she will
suffer, and prevent others from helping him or her, as indicated by at least five of the
following:
(1) chooses people and situations that lead to disappointment, failure,
or mistreatment even when better options are clearly available
(2) rejects or renders ineffective the attempts of others to help him
or her
(3) following positive personal events (e.g., new achievement),
responds with depression, guilt, or a behavior that produces pain (e.g., an accident)
(4) incites angry or rejecting responses from others and then feels
hurt, defeated, or humiliated (e.g., makes fun of spouse in public, provoking an angry
retort, then feels devastated)
(5) rejects opportunities for pleasure, or is reluctant to acknowledge
enjoying himself or herself (despite having adequate social skills and the capacity for
pleasure)
(6) fails to accomplish tasks crucial to his or her personal objectives
despite demonstrated ability to do so, e.g., helps fellow students write papers, but is
unable to write his or her own
(7) is uninterested in or rejects people who consistently treat him or
her well, e.g., is unattracted to caring sexual partners
(8) engages in excessive self-sacrifice that is unsolicited by the
intended recipients of the sacrifice
B. The behaviors in A do not occur exclusively in response to, or in
anticipation of, being physically, sexually, or psychologically abused.
C. The behaviors in A do not occur only when the person is depressed
(APA, 1987, pp. 373-74).
There is an uneasy atmosphere in my seminars whenever I read out these
diagnostic criteria. Most students feel that they are candidates for this diagnosis. I do.
I should add that this syndrome appears in DSM III-R in Appendix A: Proposed
Diagnostic Categories Needing Further Study A sign of things perhaps to come.
Trichotillomania or persistent fiddling with ones hair and
Factitious Disorder symptoms intentionally produced or feigned
are established diagnoses, as are Impulse Disorders.
I have produced these examples at the trailing edge of established
psychiatric diagnostic classification to make it clear, once again, that we are dealing
with the history of the delineation of deviance in some of these instances, just as much
as we are with clinically worrying phenomena.
I want now to turn once again to the concepts of normal and
pathological in their original medical context. They, too, are inside history, and we are
fortunate that as distinguished an historian of science as Georges Canguilhem has written
a classic study of them, in which he argues that the ideas of the normal and the
pathological, far from being scientifically or statistically determined, are rather
concepts of value deeply imbued with political, economic and technological
imperatives (cover blurb). If this is true of the bedrock of medical concepts, by
analogy to which we construct our psychopathological categories, the same adjectives must
surely apply in the psychic realm: value-laden, imbued with political, economic and
technological, in short, with ideological imperatives.
I shall be offering an alternative model as we go along, but I shall
offer a taste of it here. The concept of psychopathology implies a fairly sharp dichotomy,
a model of the mind in which the rational is the desirable state, and the irrational is
kept at bay by defence mechanisms, through which intense emotions break from time to time
and sometimes for long periods. But what if intense primitive mentation is normal?
According to Kleinian psychoanalysis, there is a warrant in Freud for considering
primitive processes and distortions of experience which are usually considered to be
psychotic as part of everyday experience. Joan Riviere appeals to Freud's hypothesis that
the psyche is always interpreting the reality of its experiences 'or rather, misinterpreting
them in a subjective manner that increases its pleasure and preserves it from pain'
(Riviere, 1952, p. 41). Freud calls this process 'hallucination; and it forms the
foundation of what we mean by phantasy-life. The phantasy-life of the individual is
thus the form in which the real internal and external sensations and perceptions are
interpreted and represented to himself in his mind under the influence of the
pleasure-pain principle'. Riviere adds that 'this primitive and elementary function of his
psyche to misinterpret his perceptions for his own satisfaction and to do so to a
degree which it is appropriate to call hallucination still retains the upper hand
in the minds of the great majority of even civilised adults' (p. 41). This general
function for phantasy is repeated in Susan Isaacs' definition. The "mental
expression" of instinct is unconscious phantasy... There is no impulse, no
instinctual urge or response which is not experienced as unconscious phantasy' (Isaacs,
1952, p. 83).
The first mental processes... are to be regarded as the earliest
beginnings of phantasies. In the mental development of the infant, however, phantasy soon
becomes also a means of defence against anxieties, a means of inhibiting and controlling
instinctual urges and an expression of reparative wishes as well... All impulses, all
feelings, all modes of defence are experienced in phantasies which give them mental life and show their direction and purpose (ibid.).
Donald Meltzer makes a similar point when he reviews the development of
Melanie Kleins ideas of the paranoid-schizoid and depressive positions. She first
put them forward as fixation points from which subsequent psychoses developed. She next
characterised them as developmental stages. In her later writings they became positions,
characteristic of all of us, part of the warp and woof of everyday unconscious thinking
(Meltzer, 1978, part 3, p. 22).
These examples from Riviere, Isaacs and Meltzer are expressions of a
position which I shall develop as we examine classical psychiatric nosology, and then
Freudian defence mechanisms and move on to look more carefully at Kleinian psychodynamics.
In the concluding chapter, offer a worked example of a syndrome characterised in a dynamic
way.
If this way of seeing the inner world is persuasive, then what is left
of the concept of psychopathology? In some we will find ourselves left with less that we
began with and in other ways quite a lot more.
REFERENCES
(Place of publication is London unless otherwise specified.)
Abelove, Henry (1986) Freud, Homosexuality and the Americans, Dissent Winter, pp. 59-69.
Anon, (1854). "Deluge." In Encyclopedia Britannica, 8th ed., vol. 7, pp.
710-23. Edinburgh: Black.
APA (1987) DSM III - R: Diagnostic and Statistic Manual of Mental Disorders, 3rd
ed., revised. Washington: American Psychiatric Association.
Cross, S. J. and Albury, W. R. (1987) 'Walter B. Cannon, L. J. Henderson, and the
organic analogy', Osiris 2nd ser. 3: 165-92.
Ashton, Rosemary (1991) G. H. Lewes: a Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Bain, Alexander (1855). The Senses and the Intellect. Parker; 3rd ed. (1868); 4th ed.
Longmans (1894).
Bain, Alexander (1859). The Emotions and the Will. Parker; 3rd ed. Longmans (1875).
Bainton
Baldwin, James Mark (1901)Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology. 3 vols. in 4,
2nd ed., 1925; reprinted 1960. Gloucester, Mass.: Smith.
Bernard, Claude
Berrios, German E.(1991) British Psychopathology since the Early 20th
Century, in G. E. Berrios and Hugh Freeman, eds., 150 Years of British Psychiatry
1841-1991. Gaskell, pp. 232-44.
_____ (1996) The History of Mental Symptoms: Descriptive Psychopathology since the
Nineteenth Century. Cambridge.
Bichat, Xavier ((1800) Recherches sur la vie et la mort. Paris.
Breuer, Josef and Freud, Sigmund (1895) Studies on Hysteria., in Freud
(1953-73), vol. 2.
Brown, E. R. (1979a) 'He who pays the piper: foundations, the medical profession and
medical education', in R. Leverby and D. Rosner, eds., Health in America: Essays
in Social History. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, pp. 132-54.
_____ (1979b) Rockefeller Medicine Men: Medicine and Capitalism in America. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Canguilhem, Georges (19xx) The Normal and the Pathological. Zone Books
Cannon, Walter B. (1932) The Wisdom of the Body, New York, Norton.
Condillac, Étienne Bonnet de (1754) Condillac's Treatise on the
Sensations, trans. G. Carr (Favil, London, 1930.
Coser, Lewis (1956) The Functions of Social Conflict. London, Collier-Macmillan.
Cruveilhier, Jean (1835-42) Anatomie pathologique. Paris.
Darwin, Charles (1859) On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or
the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. Murray; facsimile
reprint. New York: Atheneum, 1967; 6th ed. (1872a). Murray.
Darwin, Charles, and Wallace, A. R. (1958) NB: change to 1858 joint article (1958), in Evolution
by Natural Selection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Demerath, N. J. M. and Peterson, R. A. (eds.) (1967) System, Change and Conflict: A
Reader on Contemporary Sociological Theory and the Debate over Functionalism, London,
Collier Macmillan.
Descartes, René (1637) Discourse on the Method of Properly Conducting Ones
Reason and of Seeking the Truth in the Sciences, in Discourse on Method and The
Meditations. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968, pp. 25-91.
Durkheim, Émile. (1893) The Division of Labour in Society; reissued
Collier-Macmillan, 1964.
_____ (1895) The Rules of Sociological Method; reissued Collier-Macmillan, 1964.
English, Horace B. and Eva C. (1958) Dictionary of Psychological and
Psychoanalytical Terms: a Guide to Usage. Longmans, Green & Co.
Ewalt, Jack R, Strecker, E. A. and Ebaugh, F. G. (1957) Practical
Clinical Psychiatry, 8th ed., McGraw-Hill.
Fenichel, Otto (1945) The Psychoanalytic Theory of Neurosis. New York: Norton.
Feuchsterleben, E. F. von (1947) The Principles of Medical
Psychology. Sydenham Society
Figlio, Karl (1978) 'Chlorosis and Chronic Disease in
Nineteenth-century Britain: the Social Constitution of Somatic Illness in a Capitalist
Society', Internat. J. Health Services 8: 589-617.
_____ (1982) How Does Medicine Mediate Social Relations?
Workmens Compensation and Medico-Legal Practices 1890-1940, in P. Wright and
A. Treacher, eds., The Problem of Medical Knowledge: Examining the Social Construction
of Medicine. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 174-224.
______ (1985) 'Medical Diagnosis, Class Dynamics, Social Stability, in
L. Levidow and R. M. Young, eds., Science, Technology and the Labour Process: Marxist
Studies, Free Association Books, Vol. 2, pp. 129-65.
Freud, Sigmund (1891) On Aphasia: A Critical Study. N. Y.:
International Universities Press, 1953.
______ (1891a) Psycho-physical Parallelism, S. E. 14,
pp. 206-8.
______ (1895) Project for a Scientific Psychology, S. E. 1, pp. 283-397.
______ (1953-73) The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Works of Sigmund Freud, 24 vols. Hogarth (S. E.).
Gay, Peter (1988) Freud: A Life for Our Time. Dent.
Greenberg, Jay R. and Mitchell, Stephen A. (1983) Object Relations
in Psychoanalytic Theory. Harvard.
Greene, John C. (1959) 'Biology and social theory in the nineteenth
century: Auguste Comte and Herbert Spencer', in Clagett, M. (ed.) Critical Problems in
the History of Science, Madison, University of Wisconsin Press, pp. 419-46.
Gouldner, Alvin W. (1971) The Coming Crisis in Western Sociology. Heinemann Educational Books.
Hacking, Ian (1992) Multiple Personality Disorder and Its
Hosts, History of the Human Sciences 5: 3-31.
______ (1995) Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and the
Sciences of Memory. Princeton University Press.
Haraway, Donna (1989) Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in
the World of Modern Science. Routledge.
______(1990) Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. Free
Association Books.
Hartley, David, Observations on Man, His Frame, His Duty, and His
Expectations, 2 vols. Leake and Frederick, 1749..
Henderson, Lawrence J. (1913) The Fitness of the Environment: An
Inquiry into the Biological Significance of the Properties of Matter, New York,
Macmillan; reissued Boston, Beacon Press, 1958.
_____ (1970) L. J. Henderson on the Social System: Selected
Writings, London University of Chicago Press.
Heyl, Barbara (1968) 'The Harvard "Pareto Circle"', Journal
of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, . 4: 316-34
Holland, Henry (1852) Chapters on Mental Physiology. Longman,
Brown, Green & Longman.
Huxley, Thomas H. () Evolution in Biology, in The Encyclopaedia
Britannica, 9th ed., Edinburgh: Adam & Charles Black, 1979, vol. 8, pp. 744-51.
Isaacs, Susan (1952) The Nature and Function of Phantasy, in Klein et
al. (1952), pp. 67-121.
Klein, Melanie et al. (1952) Developments in Psycho-Analysis. Hogarth.
Kohler, Robert E. 1991) Partners in Science: Foundations and Natural
Scientists 1900-1945. Chicago.
Laplanche, Jean and Pontalis, J.-B. (1983) The Language of Psycho-Analysis. Hogarth; reprinted Maresfield.
Lemert, E. M. (1951) Social Pathology: A Systematic Approach to the
Theory of Sociopathic Behavior, New York, McGraw-Hill.
Levin, David M., ed. (1987) Pathologies of the Modern Self:
Postmodern Studies on Narcissism, Schizophrenia, and Depression. New York University
Press.
Littlewood, Roland (1996) Reason and Necessity in the
Specification of the Multiple Self, Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britan
and Ireland Occasional Paper No. 43.
______ (1998) From Demonic Possession to Multiple
Personality, in The Butterfly and the Serpet: Essays in Psychiatry, Race and
Religion. Free Association Books, pp. 277-97.
Locke, John, (1690) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, 5th edn. 1706; 2 vols., Dent, 1961.
Martindale, D. (ed.) (1965) Functionalism in the Social Sciences:
The Strengths and Limits of Functionalism in Anthropology, Economics, Political Science,
and Sociology, Philadelphia, American Academy of Political and Social Science.
Masserman, Jules H. (1946) Principles of Dynamic Psychiatry:
Including an Integrative Approach to Abnormal and Clinical Psychology. Philadelphia:
Saunders.
Maudsley, Henry
Mayo
______ (1978) The Kleinian Development Part I: Freuds Clinical
Development; Part II: Richard Week-by-Week; Part III: The Clinical Significance of the
Work of Bion. Strath Tay: Clunie.
Mills, C. Wright (1964) Sociology and Pragmatism: The Higher
Learning in America, New York, Paine-Whitman.
_____ (1970) The Sociological Imagination, Harmondsworth,
Penguin, first published 1959.
Noyes, Arthur P. and Kolb, Lawrence C. (1958) Modern Clinical
Psychiatry, 5th ed., W. B. Saunders.
Radcliffe, Brown, A. R. (1952) Structure and Function in Primitive
Society: Essays and Addresses. Cohen and West.
Rayner, Eric (1991) The Independent Mind in British Psychoanalysis. Free
Association Books.
Ribot, T. (1873). English Psychology. Trans. J. Fitzgerald. King.
Riviere, Joan (1952) 'On the Genesis of Psychical Conflict in Early
Infancy', in Klein et al. (1952), pp. 37-66.
Russett, Cynthia E. (1966) The Concept of Equilibrium in American
Social Thought. Yale University Press.
Searles, Harold F. (1979) Countertransference and Related Subjects. Madison, CT: International Universities Press.
Showalter, Elaine (1995) The Female Malady: Women, Madness and
English Culture, 1830-1980. N. Y.: Pantheon; reprinted Virago, 1987.
Silver, Daniel and Rosenbleuth, Michael, eds. (1992) Handbook of
Borderline Disorders. Madison, CT: International Universities Press.
Spencer, Herbert (1851) Social Statics. Chapman.
______ The Principles of Psychology. Longmans. 1855; 2nd edn., 2
vols. Williams and Norgate, 1870-2; 3rd edn., 2 vols., 1890.
_____ (1860) 'The Social Organism', Westminster Review (January); reprinted in Essays, Vol. 1, pp. 265-307; and in The Man versus the State: with Four Essays on
Politics and Society, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1969, pp. 195-233.
Sully, James (1879) Evolution in Philosophy, Encyclopaedia Britannica. Edinburgh:
Adam & Charles Black, vol. 8, pp. 751-73
Tarnopolsky, Alex (1992) ;The Validity of the Borderline Personality Disorder, in
Silver & Rosenbleuth, pp. 29-52.
_____ (1992a) Borderline Disorders: a British Point of View, IN ibid., pp.
177-202.
Taylor, F. K. (1966) Psychopathology. Butterworth.
Virchow, Rudolf (1858) Cellular-pathologie.
Warren, Howard C. (1921) A History of the Association Psychology. Constable.
Wolff, Heinz, Bateman, Anthony and Sturgeon, David (1990) UCH Textbook of
Psychiatry: an Integrated Approach. Duckworth
Wootton, Barbara (1959) Social Science and Social Pathology, London,
George Allen and Unwin.
Young, Robert M. (1968) 'The Functions of the Brain: Gall to Ferrier (1808-1886)', Isis 59: 251-68.
_____ (1970). Mind, Brain and Adaptation in the Nineteenth Century: Cerebral
Localization and Its Biological Context from Gall to Ferrier. Oxford: Clarendon.
_____ (1981) The Naturalization of Value Systems in the Human
Sciences, in Problems in the Biological and Human Sciences. Milton Keynes:
Open University Press, pp. 63-110.
_____ (1989) Scientism in the History of Management Theory, Sci. as Culture 8: 118-43.
_____ (1994) Mental Space. Process Press.
Copyright: The Author
Address for Correspondence: 26 Freegrove Road, London N7 9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk
|
|