SCIENTIFIC MEDICINE AND THE SOCIAL ORDER
by Robert M. Young
Wellcome Unit for the History of Medicine
University of Cambridge
I want to suggest that we begin to develop a critical
perspective on medicine. In particular, I want to suggest that we scrutinize our
own dream about the progress of science and medicine as they affect our images
of our selves and our patients' images of medicine and its practitioners. These
questions will be related on the one hand to the fundamental assumptions of
modern science and on the other hand to our social and ideological beliefs. In
order to gain a better perspective on ourselves, we might fruitfully turn to the
writings of social scientists who are not modelling their work on the approach
of the natural sciences but instead are attempting to enter sympathetically into
the perceptions of patients and who are critically analyzing the institutional
and social settings in which medicine is practised. I hope that the argument
will lend weight to the conclusion that it is impossible to separate the
scientific aspect of medicine from its conceptual, historical and social
dimensions.
British medical education is currently undergoing reform in
the wake of the Report of the Royal Commission on Medical Education — the 'Todd
Report', which was presented to Parliament in 1968. It is a fundamental document
which represents an extremely important change in the whole approach to medical
education and in the long run to medicine itself. Its main lesson is that it is
no longer possible to teach medicine: it's just too complicated. Instead, the
proposed aim is to produce people who can think critically and evaluate new
findings and procedures. This means that the whole approach must become more
abstract, leaving the doctor to find the relevant applications, to sort things
out for himself. The conception of medical education is-altered from a tendency
to be assimilable to the model of technological training to that of a broad
scientific and social education.
For example, Todd advocates a deeper approach to the subject,
stressing scientific method and principles, He speaks of acquiring a proper
grounding in and appreciation of the scientific basis of medicine. The approach
to the patient must be made in terms of a broader perspective, one which he
calls 'human biology', and includes the history and significance of family life,
love, play and aggression, along with the nature, origin and development of
communication between human beings. These recommendations lead us into an area
which has hitherto played almost no part in medical education, the so-called
'behavioural sciences'. The Royal Commission approvingly refers back to a report
by the General Medical Council of 1967: 'In the Council's view the study of
human structure and function should be combined with the study of human
behaviour. The Council considers that instruction should be given in those
aspects of the behavioural sciences which are relevant to the study of man as an
organism adapting to his social and psychological, no less than to his physical,
environment. Instruction in the biological and sociological bases of human
behaviour, and the principles of learning theory, should be included.'
One more quotation will help to convey the full import of the
fundamental reorientation of our approach to medicine which is being called for:
'Deliberate and sustained efforts should be made to show students the relevance
of social phenomena, whether treated conceptually, comparatively or
historically, to the roles and functions in society of doctors and of
organizations for medical care.'
In what follows, I shall suggest that we take a very
ambivalent approach to these recommendations. We must surely welcome the
teaching of medicine in a way which expands its scope to include conceptual,
comparative and historical approaches to its setting in society. At the same
time, I think we should take a very sceptical approach to the hope that we are
thereby being given a new scientific tool which is merely an extension of the
others in the physician's black bag. What I mean is that if we lean too heavily
on the 'behavioural sciences' and if we rush too fast to bring the human and
social dimensions into the domain of science, we will be attempting to use very
blunt instruments to operate on the delicate tissues of human relations in a
complex social and political context.
Putting the matter starkly, medicine is in danger of becoming
de-moralized. By this I do not mean the onslaughts of successive governments on
free prescriptions, the continuing crisis in the hospitals and other medical
institutions, or even the morale of doctors. Rather, in using the term
'de-moralized', I am pointing to the conventions of moral and ethical neutrality
which underlie the objective, value-free ideology of science, an objectivity
which is supposed to extend to science's maximum penetration into the community
— the practice of medicine. To lend credence to the claim that we are in danger
of being demoralized, we must consider the philosophical and methodological
context in which medical concepts lie: they are in a crucial mediating position
between science on the one hand and society on the other.
We must first look down the line from the practising
physician to hospital medicine and the university medical centre, on to the
Medical Research Council research laboratories, to scientific biology, and
finally to the physico-chemical sciences. Moving in the other direction, we can
travel back up the same path and cross the boundary between medicine and the
behavioural and social sciences and finally reach the non-scientific context of
the rough-and-tumble of personal, social and political life — the sort of life
which patients daily bring with them into the surgery and which physicians
encounter every day during house calls. (It is worth adding the physician brings
these contexts with him, however much they are mediated by his professional
role.) If we can explore these two perspectives, we may be able to begin to see
medicine in terms of both at once. If so, we will have a greater appreciation of
the conceptual niche which medicine occupies in its relations with biology and
the physico-chemical sciences. At the same time we can perhaps attain a healthy
scepticism toward the validity and the desirability of our present conventions
about scientific and medical objectivity. This second perspective could help us
to see the limits and pitfalls of too much faith in science. It can do this by
unmasking or demystifying its most extreme claims to accounting for man's place
in nature and society.
The purpose of this approach is not to glorify self-indulgent
subjectivity and irrationalism but to advocate as responsible an attitude toward
the relations between science and medicine on the one hand and moral, social and
political issues on the other, as doctors are trained to have in the use of
stethoscopes, drugs and scalpels. The point is not merely to exhort the medical
community to think more in moral and political terms — though that certainly is
part of the point — but to consider the proposition that willy-nilly we already
do that more or less covertly. It seems to me that it would be a real
improvement if we could acknowledge that dimension in medical work, and could
become self-consciously critical about the moral and political issues which
penetrate deeply into the allegedly objective aspects of medical science and
medical practice.
In holding out the promise of enlightenment from the
behavioural and social sciences, the planners of medical education have offered
us a potentially dangerous mixture of science and scientism. Scientism is the
illegitimate or premature extension of the methods and assumptions of science
into areas in which the relevant findings and theories are not available.
Scientism cloaks many ethical and political views in a specious aura of
scientific objectivity. Surely it would be better for us to discuss these issues
as such, rather than get swept away by the dreams of science at the expense of
our humanity.
In an important sense every general practitioner knows very
well what is being argued here, but he doesn't know that he knows it, because he
does not have a set of categories for talking about it. There is no technical or
scientific language for talking about moral and political issues as they arise
in medicine They are relegated to informal judgements — to the 'bedside manner'
or to a gift for dealing with 'the troublesome ones', to 'clinical judgment' or
to 'wisdom'. But the issues are not considered in a disciplined way: they are
the subject of informal discussions. I am arguing that we must learn to think in
a more self-conscious and disciplined way about the relation ship of medicine
with science and of medicine with its social and political context. This, of
course, is not a set of issues which one can get straight once and for all. The
boundaries between medicine and science and with society are uncertain and
shifting.
Now let us stand back and begin to take a reflective view of
the role of the doctor. The Todd Report has some helpful things to say about
this: 'There are certain matters of general social interest on which...to quote
from evidence we have received, "the doctor is still considered to he an
'oracle, and the student should recognise the responsibility this entails." We
do not think that medical education should encourage the doctor to assume an
authority beyond that implied by his profession or his responsibilities as a
citizen. We recognise, however, that there are many important matters of moral
and social controversy in which doctors inevitably become involved: abortion,
drug addiction and artificial prolongation of life are examples.' There are many
more — and more-subtle ones — such as the life styles of non-conformist or
'deviant' patients, which will be discussed below. Todd goes on: 'No doctor,
however remote from clinical practice, can detach himself entirely from such
questions and we agree that the student needs help in preparing to deal with
them.' The Report argues that medical students should not be segregated from
other sorts of students and that it is essential that they work out a personal
philosophy of life which will enable them to deal with such issues. The basis
for this must be provided by an informed understanding tutored in psychology,
sociology and social medicine. This passage, like much of the Report, raises
important issues and then retreats at the last moment into an effort to find a
strictly scientific way of considering them by means which are more in the
domain of scientism than science. But in addition to this point, I don't think
the Report gives sufficient weight to the tremendously highly-charged role which
the doctor plays. Let's ponder it for a moment.
People unclothe on request before a relative stranger. They
allow him (or her) to explore orifices which — in other contexts — are taboo
and/or only accessible in one's most intimate relationships. They allow him to
violate their integument with needles and knives. They swallow unknown
substances on trust and in conformity with a schedule laid down by the doctor.
They go to bed when they don't feel like it and get up when told, even if it
causes pain. They reveal their innermost secrets and fears and even allow
psychiatrists (as their critics put it) ’to plug them into the mains'. It is
largely because of this extraordinary role that physicians work within
highly-defined and emotionally-charged conventions which have evolved to protect
both the patient and the doctor. At the same time, the openness and
vulnerability of the patient have the effect of their placing tremendous trust
in the doctor in a whole range of areas which extend far beyond his technical
and professional competence. We cannot simply set those constraints aside or
escape from the obligations which they imply. We can, however, attempt to become
much more reflective about them.
Much of the argument of what follows has been adumbrated in
the above introductory remarks. The explicit form of the argument is in four
parts. First, an attempt to locate medicine in the scheme of the sciences and
society by examining a set of related concepts. Second, a brief consideration of
the dreams of scientific medicine will be given, to support the argument that we
will never reach a medical utopia and are therefore inevitably thrown back on
our own resources in facing complex moral and political questions. Third, I
shall give examples of the shifting boundaries between the scientific and the
scientized aspects of medicine and society. Finally, some examples from
psychiatry will help to illustrate the relationship between medical institutions
and social values. Throughout the discussion there is one central theme — the
difficulty in ever knowing when one is being legitimately scientific and when
one is being scientistic, i.e., expressing moral and political judgements
cloaked in the language of science.
In turning to certain key concepts in medicine, we are
engaged in an unfamiliar exercise in thinking about concepts which are so
commonplace that we seldom examine them. Rather, we think in terms of them, and
their fundamental role is only perceptible — and a critical attitude toward them
only recoverable — if we focus sharply on some of our most commonplace terms and
begin again to see the extent to which they shape our views of symptoms, of
health and disease, and beyond these, how they determine our whole views of
nature, man and society.
*
force
field
energy
OBJECTS ORGANISMS PATIENTS PERSONS
PHYSICAL SCIENCES BIOLOGICAL SCIENCES MEDICAL SCIENCES SOCIAL SCIENCES
matter structure health order- stability
motion (physiology) function disease disorder-instability
number (endocrin- adaptation normal norm-adjusted-deviant
ology) maladaptation pathological
(pharmacol (mental health)
ogy) (psychopathology)
(molecular
biology)
(electron
microscopy)
particles
elements
process..............................................................................................praxis
science..............................................................................................scientism
This chart requires considerably more elucidation than can be
given in a relatively short essay, so only its bare bones can be laid out here.
The goals of explanation of modern science which were developed in the sixteenth
and seventeenth centuries led (in the so-called Scientific Revolution) to the
definition of what would qualify as a scientific account. Such accounts were
thenceforward to be made in terms of matter, motion and number, and all other
phenomena were to be explained in terms of those three fundamental defining
concepts, which, in principle, could account for all of the natural world. All
scientific explanations aspire to the purity of physico-chemical explanations,
and the additional concepts of force, field, energy, particle and element have
been elaborated in the spirit of the physical reductionist programme which lies
at the basis of science. The historical figures whose work is most prominently
associated with laying down the model of explanation of modern science were
Galileo, Descartes and Newton.
There is, of course; an important gap between
physico-chemical explanations — ones which are concerned with objects - and all
of the other levels of explanation which we will consider. There are no
evaluative concepts allowed in physical explanations, but as soon as we move to
the domain of organisms, we encounter concepts which are fundamental but which
involve more or less explicitly evaluative concepts, the most basic being that
of 'function', the rock bottom conception for discussing living systems. Indeed,
the distinction between life and death itself (along with its more general
biological equivalents —survival and extinction) has no place in a purely
physical explanation. There is, of course, continuity between the methods of the
physical sciences and those of the biological, medical and human ones, but there
is, I maintain, a radical break in their philosophical status. (This depends on
the fundamental distinction between 'primary' and 'secondary' qualities and the
resulting fact-value distinction, but these matters cannot be considered here.)
The work of Harvey, Descartes and von Haller (the father of modern physiology)
provided the conceptual links between modern science and the categories of
biological explanation, while that of Malthus and Darwin played the central
roles in including man in the domain of biology. Men — whether simply as people
or in the particular role of patient — are seen as organisms as a result of the
theory of biological evolution. Similarly, a number of disciplines which
antedate the awareness of a general science of biology (a term which was coined
in 1802) as a related set of disciplines, have a firm conceptual niche as a
result of evolutionism. These (and their modern expressions) are traditionally
seen as medical, but their conceptual place is somewhere between the physical
and the biological sciences: anatomy (especially microscopic anatomy and the
visual study of molecules in electron microscopy), physiology, endocrinology,
and molecular biology. Aspects of pharmacology and pathology also lie close to
the work of physicists and chemists, but their main research is closely related
with the practice of medicine, and they are less 'purely' scientific in the
main.
There are direct analogies between crucial pairs of
biological, medical, and social concepts, and it is on the validity of these
analogies that the claim that medicine (and especially the scientific study of
man in society) depends for its legitimacy in treating patients and people — in all their aspects — as part of the domain of science. Once again, these
analogies depend on evolutionism, a theory which implies that man and all his
works are, in principle, part of the natural order and (again in principle)
subject to explanation in terms of scientific concepts and laws. Our basic
dilemma is to reconcile this generalization with the incomplete state of science
and the fact that actual men have conflicting values, goals, politics and
ideologies. We are in grave danger of allowing the general principle of
scientific naturalism to lead to premature claims which make my values or yours
produce premature, specious scientistic conceptions.
Thus, when it is argued that the biological concepts of
'adaptation' and 'maladaptation' provide a secure scientific foundation for the
medical concepts of 'normal' (= healthy) and 'pathological' (= diseased) and
that these, in turn, provide a secure basis for scientific evaluations of
individual, social and political behaviour, we are in grave danger of replacing
science with scientism. Moving from the medical concept of health to the social
ones of 'order' and 'stability' or from that of disease to that of 'social
disorder' or 'instability', leads us to assume that the status quo in
society is part of the natural order. In individual behaviour, the same analogy
is made between the biological concept of 'adaptation' and the medical concept
of 'normal' on the one hand and the social concept of 'adjusted' on the other.
The same, of course, is true of 'maladaptation - pathological' and psychological
or social 'maladjustment' or ’deviance’. The medico-social concepts of 'mental
health', 'psychopathology', and 'social pathology' illustrate the conflations
which I am suggesting we treat with grave reservations. Radical critics have
provided us with some useful terms for identifying these dangers, and they
suggest that the reduction of men's deliberate, principled actions to categories
of natural science is to reduce their 'praxis' to 'process', and the resulting
treatment of men as things is termed 'reification', The boundary between
legitimate explanation of biological and human phenomena in scientific terms and
the specious procedure of doing so in the name of science — thereby substituting
scientism for science — is so frequently difficult to draw, that we should be
very wary of relinquishing our moral and political categories to this new group
of so-called 'social sciences', with their experts who will provide 'scientific'
accounts of what is good and bad, possible and impossible, in individual, social
and political life. There is, of course, an opposite danger to this one which I
have called 'de-moralization': that of instant 're-moralization', Thus, in the
debate on abortion — particularly in the public statements of the Professor of
Obstetrics and Gynaecology at Birmingham — men appear in their roles as
professional experts, complete with the power to influence appointments to
hospital posts over a wide geographical area. They express their own moral and
political convictions ex cathedra. This won't do either, and we must
therefore find a way to engage in moral and political debates as such.
I want to turn now to a second topic: the dream of medical
utopia, holding out the promise that science will eventually relieve us of these
moral and political dilemmas. In doing his we must consider the patients'
perception of the doctor and their shared beliefs about science and medicine. Of
course, patients hope and fear more than doctors, but, on the whole, they share
a very optimistic view about the progress of medicine, based on the dramatic
advances in basic science and its applications. In my own lifetime the whole
gamut of antibiotic drugs, of effective insecticides and of ataraxic drugs have
come to the centre of medicine and public health. Each of these has turned out
to be a mixed blessing, but few would argue that they are no blessing at all.
Even more recently we have been blessed with dramatic improvements in
controlling the immune reactions which stood — and to a large extent continue to
stand — in the way of all sorts of surgical repair and replacement. And it is
only a matter of months since the staggering possibilities of genetic
manipulation have come onto the horizon.
Now I don't want to knock progress but only to put a
biological — and then a social and psychological — perspective on these
developments and the dreams which stem from them. In his excellent essay on The Dreams of Reason (Columbia paperback, 1961), Professor René Dubos has
put the issues very clearly: 'Granted the lack of precise information, it is
clear that there have been spontaneous ebbs and flows in the prevalence and
severity of many diseases. Plague invaded the Roman world during the Justinian
era; leprosy was prevalent in western Europe until the sixteenth century; plague
again reached catastrophic proportions during the Renaissance; several outbreaks
of the sweating sickness terrorized England during Tudor times; syphilis spread
like wildfire shortly after 1500; smallpox was the scourge of the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries; tuberculosis, scarlet fever, diphtheria, measles took
over when smallpox began to recede; today virus infections occupy the focus of
attention in our medical communities; and long before viruses had become
scientifically fashionable, pandemics of influenza at times added a note of
still greater unpredictability to the pattern of infection.' (pp. 66-7) 'Coming
now to our own times, who could have dreamed a generation ago that
hypervitaminosis would become a common form of nutritional disease in the
Western World; that the cigarette industry, air pollutants, and the use of
radiations would be held responsible for the increase of certain types of
cancer; that the introduction of detergents and various synthetics would
increase the incidence of allergies; that advances in chemotherapy and other
therapeutic procedures would create a new staphylococcus pathology; that
alcoholics and patients with various forms of iatrogenic diseases would occupy
such a large number of beds in the modern hospital?' (p. 69)
Dubos goes on to draw conclusions which are of fundamental
importance for our evaluation of the relationship between scientific progress
and moral and political issues: 'The belief that disease can be conquered
through the use of drugs deserves special mention here because it is so widely
held. Its fallacy is that it fails to take into account the difficulties arising
from the ecological complexity of human problems. Blind faith in drugs is an
attitude comparable to the naive cowboy philosophy that permeates the Wild West
thriller. In the crisis-ridden frontier town the hero single-handedly blasts out
the desperadoes who have been running rampant through the settlement. The story
ends on a happy note because it appears that peace has been restored. But in
reality the death of the villains does not solve the fundamental problem, for
the rotten social conditions which opened the town to the desperadoes will soon
allow others to come in unless something is done to correct the primary source
of trouble. The hero moves out of town without doing anything to solve this far
more complex problem; in fact, he has no weapon to deal with it and is not even
aware of its existence.
'Similarly, the accounts of miraculous cures rarely make
clear that arresting an acute episode does not solve the problem of disease in
the social body — or even the individual concerned... To state it bluntly... my
personal view is that the burden of disease is not likely to decrease in the
future, whatever the progress of medical research and whatever the skill of
social organizations in applying new discoveries. While methods of control can
and will be found for almost any given pathological state, we can take it for
granted that disease will change its manifestations according to social
circumstances. Threats to health are inescapable accompaniments of life.' (pp.
83-4)
These cautionary remarks help us to see two things. The first
is the importance of the biological perspective — seeing man and disease in
ecological terms as ongoing evolutionary processes in which man has decisively
intervened with controls which are, in the nature of the evolutionary process,
unlikely ever to be complete. More generally, if we are unlikely ever to be able
to replace the texture of physical disease and its moral implications, how much
less is science likely to find 'magic bullets' and cure-alls for our social and
political malaise, for exploitation, for injustice, and for the relations among
states.
Turning now to the topic of the shifting boundaries between
the scientific and the scientized aspects of science, medicine and
society, I want to move from somatic medicine to its relations with psychiatry
and the social sciences. Once again, the theory of evolution provides the key
link between somatic medicine and man's mental and social aspects. Evolutionism
provided the general framework within which psychiatry reached the general
conclusion that all abnormal behaviour has a scientific explanation. In its
nineteenth-century form, this thesis took the form that since the brain is the
organ of the mind, all mind disease is brain disease, Psychopathology thereby
becomes neuropathology. It was in this 'somaticist' atmosphere that Freud
elaborated his psychoanalytic theories, theories which began with the study of
brain disorders and moved on to express his new findings about people's troubles
in physicalist terms. Modern psychiatry has drawn heavily on his metaphorical
languages, and the following terms are commonplace: 'the anatomy of the mental
personality', 'the mental apparatus', 'mental energies', 'mental forces',
'mental structures'. From biology came the concept of instinct, an idea which in
its current form is providing the basis for a renewed biologization of social
and political philosophies. There are innumerable conceptions which move
uneasily between the somatic and the psychic realms. The concept of 'stigma'
which Erving Goffman discusses so perceptively, operates in both realms at once
(Stigma. Penguin paperback, 1968). The physical disabilities which
stigmata originally denoted, provide a bridge between medical and social
abnormalities and the conceptual shift from somatic pathology to social deviance
and labelling.
Going further, psychopathic behaviour provides an example of
a diagnostic category which jumps about from year to year. The majority of
people in prisons have been labelled as psychopathic or sociopathic
personalities. This must mean that they have been held responsible for their
actions. However, for a period it was strongly argued that these people were the
victims of deprivation in the crucial period when the social conscience is being
formed. They were then seen as suitable cases for psychiatric treatment, not
responsible for their actions. But when it turned out that they were not
responsive to treatment or that they required more psychiatric resources than
were available, they were placed again in prisons, this time because there was
no other place to keep these deviants whom we could not afford to help
sufficiently to learn to internalize obedience to society's norms. Then it was
thought that they suffered from an abnormality in the chromosomes. At this point
their behaviour was firmly linked with genetic inevitability — their behaviour
patterns were said to be innate. This evidence turned out to be equivocal, but
in the same period others argued that to identify psychopaths by genetic
screening, to subject them to eugenic prohibitions from breeding or to require
them to carry identity cards, or, finally, to incarcerate them for reasons of
preventative detention — that these procedures would be to treat people as
objects and to deny them their political rights. The case of psychopathy is an
extremely complex one, but it can be argued that it neatly illustrates the
dilemma of the scientific versus the moralistic and political models of our
approach to persons.
Turning to the social sciences, we find that quasi-scientific
terms are frequently employed. The concept of 'social pathology' appears in the
titles of two well-known books in the field, thereby scientizing a debate which
has traditionally been seen as a moral and political one. In one of them, Lady
Wooton's Social Science and Social Pathology, the very definition which
she adopts undermines the potentially scientific nature of the domain. Social
pathology turns rut to include anything the state spends money to prevent. Yet
when one looks in detail at the Todd Report, one finds the following in a
'Specimen Syllabus in Social Factors Related to Medicine': 'Social Pathology: Deviance and conformity in society; sociological, philosophical and legal
aspects of delinquency and crime, institutional neurosis, suicide, drug
addiction and alcoholism. Group behaviour and the role of the doctor and others
concerned in the prevention and treatment of behaviour disorders.' (p. 279) This
outline provides an intimate mixture of the scientific and the scientized, all
presented in the objective language of science. If we follow the spirit of the
Todd Report to the letter, we will find ourselves addressing moral, social and
political problems in terms of a set of concepts and assumptions which will
prematurely — and, I believe, illegitimately — draw them into the domain of
biology and somatic medicine.
My last arguments are drawn from psychiatry. I do this
because the points come out most clearly in that context, but every general
practitioner knows that questions which are assigned to the domain of psychiatry
are inextricably intermingled with all of his or her practice. Similarly, the
issues which are raised sharply in psychiatric examples arise on all sorts of
occasions in which people cast themselves in the role of patient to see other
people in the role of doctor: abortion, venereal disease, drugs, and other less
explicit aspects of non-conformist and unusual behaviour which gets labelled as
'deviant' and 'pathological', So, in turning to psychiatry, we are only
illustrating in a clear light issues which arise throughout medicine.
In his essay on 'The Moral Career of the Mental Patient', (Asylums, Penguin paperback, 1968), Goffman strips away the clinical and scientistic
language used in psychiatric practice and interprets the experience of the
patient in terms of his self-esteem and his relations with other people. All too
often his loved ones collude with the doctor, the doctors and staff patronise
him, and his social relations with the other people ('inmates', 'patients') in
the institution are unnecessarily restricted. The perspective which he provides
is very revealing. Few of us would be proud of behaving in our ordinary social
relations in the ways he describes, much less with people who were particularly
vulnerable and sensitive. But — and this seems to me the most important point —
these same medical people claim to be treating the patient in disinterested,
morally neutral ways. When Goffman turns to case notes, the gulf between the
self-image of psychiatry (and much the same can be said for other branches of
medicine) and the actual morally and ethically censorious language employed, is
very great: 'Armed with a neat appearance and natty little Hitlerian moustache
this 45 year old man who has spent the last five or more years of his life in
the hospital, is making a very successful hospital adjustment living within the
role of a rather gay liver and Jim-dandy type of fellow who is not only quite
superior to his fellow patients in intellectual respects but who is also quite a
man with women. His speech is sprayed with many multi-syllabled words which he
generally uses in good context, but if he takes long enough on any subject it
soon becomes apparent that he is so completely lost in his verbal diarrhoea as
to make what he says almost completely worthless.' (p. 145) Goffman dryly
observes that this, far from being morally neutral, is defamatory and is
characteristic of all levels of mental hospital staff. In my own experience with
case notes in mental hospitals, I have not seen this extreme language, but I
have often seen (and employed) language which is on the same continuum — more
morally evaluative than 'clinical'.
It is difficult to gain a perspective on the role which
psychiatry and psychiatric institutions play in our culture. In this respect,
historical analyses can be very illuminating. In particular, Michel Foucault's Madness and Civilization (Tavistock paperback, 1971) helps us to see that
the role of such institutions has always reflected certain basic issues in the
development of the economic and social assumptions, the prohibitions and
sequestrations of the societies in which they occurred. We find it easy to
criticise the incarceration of social and political nonconformists in the Soviet
Union, but we are less disposed to ask how much our own supposedly objective
criteria produce analogous results in our mental hospitals.
Returning to the present, I should like to conclude by
retailing some of the arguments of Professor Thomas Szasz, which I have chosen
as an antidote to excessive faith in the extendibility of scientific concepts
from biology and medicine to society. His strictures seem to me to apply to many
forms of deviance encountered in medicine and the ancillary medical services. In
his book of essays on Ideology and Insanity (Anchor paperback, 1970), he
begins by commenting on the psychiatric terms 'maturity' and 'immaturity',
'independence' and 'dependence', 'mental health' and 'mental illness', 'sanity'
and 'insanity': ’I believe all these psychiatric terms are inadequate and
unsatisfactory, for each neglects, or deflects attention from, the essentially moral and political character of human development and social
existence. The language of psychiatry thus de-ethicizes and depoliticizes human
relations and personal conduct... By seeking relief from the burden of his moral
responsibilities, man mystifies and technicizes his problems in living... on the
other hand, the demand for "help" thus generated is now met by a behavioral
technology ready and willing to free man of his moral burdens by treating him as
a sick patient.' (pp. 2-3) He continues, 'In contemporary social usage, the
finding of mental illness is made by establishing a deviance in behavior from
certain psychosocial, ethical, or legal norms... The discipline of medicine —
both as pure science (for example, research) and as an applied science or
technology (for example, therapy) — contains many ethical considerations and
judgements. Unfortunately, these are often denied, minimalized, or obscured, for
the ideal of the medical profession as well as of the people whom it serves is
to have an ostensibly value-free system of medical care.' (p. 17) He argues that
the concept of mental illness 'functions as a disguise: instead of calling
attention to conflicting human needs, aspirations, and values, the concept of
mental illness provides an amoral and impersonal "thing" — an "illness" — as an
explanation for problems in living... My aim... is to suggest that the phenomena
now called mental illness be looked at afresh and more simply, that they be
removed from the category of illnesses, and that they be regarded as the
expressions of man's struggle with the problem of how he should live.'
(p. 21) 'If moral values are to be discussed and promoted, they ought to be
considered for what they are — moral values, not health values. Why? Because
moral values are, and must be, the legitimate concern of everyone and fall under
the special competence of no particular group whereas health values (and
especially their technical implementation) are, and must be, the concern mainly
of experts on health, especially physicians.' (p. 41) I believe that Szasz
addresses a serious and basic issue but that his argument goes too far in
completely separating psychiatry from science. Conversely, his belief that
somatic medicine is unproblematic and can be neatly separated from ethical and
political issues seems to me to be naive and simplistic.
The problem in its general form, is that of attaining
objectivity in social issues which is analogous to that in the physico-chemical
sciences. The whole aim of this argument has been to show that the hopes held
out by the Todd Report and other attempts to turn to science for social and
political answers is at best a dangerous move and at worst a resignation from
our identities as people who can strive to achieve the sort of world we choose
to make. In his perceptive book on Beliefs in Society (Penguin paperback,
1971), Nigel Dennis makes the central point very clearly. 'Objectivity in social
questions can mean no more than a certain open-mindedness; a willingness to
acknowledge that one is oneself a party, or at least has priorities; a
willingness to examine all the information available, all the arguments, and a
willingness to answer them. It cannot mean presenting an answer over and above
the answers of the existing parties to a dispute, adopting the posture of God
who sees all things as they "really are". Of course, in practice mediation or
arbitration is sometimes useful, but this is an ad hoc procedure either
to split the difference or to strengthen one side; it is not revealing the true
nature of reality which has been obscured by fictional prejudice, for we are all
prejudiced. Thus, the question with which we began, "How can I know that I am
right?" is more easily reformulated as, "What purposes shall I pursue?"' (p.
225) In applying this approach to our roles as doctors who are attempting to
address ourselves to social issues, the same question arises, and no extension
of concepts from more nearly objective sciences will let us off the moral and
political hook. Thus the old, traditional moral, political and ideological
questions are not to be escaped in medicine or by medicine. It is no haven for
us or for our patients. And as we approach their reasons for coming to us, we
have an equally heavy burden in giving completely serious attention to their
definitions of health, as well as ours. They may feel that the doctor's job is
to help them achieve their own purposes and not ours. Then we must decide
whether or not we think it right to help them, and the answer does not lie in a
textbook of psychology or sociology.
Reading List
The works listed below provide a 'short-list' of writings
which consider the complex interrelations among concepts in the physico-chemical
sciences, biology, medicine, the social sciences, as these raise issues on
values, politics and ideology. All are available in inexpensive editions.
Abercrombie, M. L. J., The Anatomy of Judgment: An
Investigation into the Processes of Perception and Reasoning (London:
Hutchinson, 1960; also Penguin paperback) — an illuminating study of the role of
assumptions and biases in the perception, definition, and evaluation of evidence
drawn from discussions with medical students.
Dubos, R., Mirage of Health: Utopias, Progress and
Biological Change (London: Allen & Unwin, 1960) — a very perceptive study of
the relations between medical, biological and environmental conceptions by an
eminent bacteriologist.
_____ The Dreams of Reason: Science and Utopias (N.Y.
& London: Columbia, 1961; also Columbia paperback — an extension of the argument
to include the whole domain of science; see especially ch. 4 - 'Medical
Utopias'.
Fuller, W. (ed.), The Social Impact of Modern Biology (London: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1971; also RKP paperback) — twenty short papers
which consider the social and ethical problems raised by biology and medicine,
with particular emphasis on the implications of genetics and immunology;
contributors include, in many cases, the discoverers of the relevant findings
and techniques.
Goffman, E., Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled
Identity (New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1963; also Penguin-paperback) — a
sociologist considers the relations between medical and other handicaps on the
one hand and social identity on the other and relates these to the problem of
deviance.
______ Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental
Patients and Other Inmates (N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor, 1961; also Penguin
paperback) — considers the problems of manipulation and self-perception of
people who find themselves in 'total institutions'; very incisive about the
relations among the doctor, the patient and his family; see especially chapter
on 'The Moral Career of the Mental Patient'.
Szasz, T. S., Ideology and Insanity: Essays On the
Psychiatric Dehumanization of Man (N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor Original
paperback, 1970) — provocative essays on the problem of relating medical
and psychiatric conceptions of man with ethical and political issues; although
occasionally overstating his case, Szasz provides an important corrective,
helping us to see the emotional problems of patients as problems of how to live
rather than as purely value-neutral medical disorders.
Foucault, M., Madness and Civilization: A History of
Insanity in the Age of Reason (London Tavistock, 1967; also Tavistock Social
Science paperback) a difficult but brilliant interpretation of the relations
between conceptions of insanity and the changing economic and political contexts
since the seventeenth century; particularly revealing about the uses which
society makes of confinement in institutions.
Weiss, P., The Persecution and Assassination of Marat as
Performed by the Inmates of the Asylum of Charenton under the Direction of the
Marquis de Sade (London: Calder paperback, 1965) — a highly successful play
which relates Foucault's argument to current social and political issues by
means of a play within a play set in a not-so-different time.
Whitehead, A. N., Science and the Modern World (Cambridge, 1925; also Cambridge paperback) — an interpretation of the
fundamental assumptions of modern science and the problems which they raise for
man's place in nature.
Douglas, M., Purity and Danger: An Analysis of Concepts of
Pollution and Taboo
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1966; also Penguin
paperback) — an anthropological interpretation of the ways in which concepts of
health and disease, clean and dirty, etc. play a central role in ordering
society, regardless of their utilitarian value; provides an important
perspective on biological and medical conceptions of man and nature.
Titmuss, R. M., The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to
Social Policy (London: Allen & Unwin, 1970; also Allen & Unwin paperback* —
beginning with the medical problem of obtaining supplies of blood for medical
use, sociologist of social policy relates it to a series of wider issues of
economics, altruism and the economics of health services and of technological
societies, especially Britain and America.
Harris, N., Beliefs in Society: The Problem of Ideology (London: Watts, 1968; also Penguin paperback) — a politically committed
sociologist relates the social context of men's beliefs to the different
ideological perspectives on man and society held in Britain, Russia, China and
the Third World; his argument shows how the most mundane and apparently
apolitical beliefs are related to complex assumptions about the order of
society.
Recent works on medical
history and medical sociology (not available in cheap editions):
McLachlan, Gordon and Thomas McKeown (eds.), Medical
History and Medical Care: A Symposium of Perspectives (London: Oxford,
1971).
Mechanic, David, Medical Sociology- A Selective View (London: Collier-Macmillan,
Friedson, Eliot, Profession of Medicine: A Study of the
Sociology of Applied Knowledge (N.Y.: Dodd, Mead, 1970).
______ Professional Dominance: The Social Structure of
Medical Care (N.Y.: Atherton, 1970).
Eckstein, Harry, The English Health Service: Its Origins.
Structure and Achievements (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard, 1964).
Contrasting interpretations
of the deviant behaviour of students and other young people:
Bettleheim, B., 'Obsolete Youth: Towards a Psychology of
Adolescent Rebellion', Encounter 33 (1969), 29-42 (Sept.)
Erikson, E. H., 'Reflections on the Dissent of Contemporary
Youth', International Journal of Psycho-analysis 51 (1970), 11-22.
Primary sources on the
history of relations among natural science, biology, medicine, and society:
Harvey, W., An Anatomical Disquisition on the Motion of
the Heart and Blood in Animals (1628; London, Everyman's Library cheap edition).
Descartes, R., Discourse on Method (1637; Penguin
paperback) — see especially Part V, in which Descartes relates his
philosophy of biology to Harvey's discovery and, by deducing the motion from
first principles, gets the relationship between systole and diastole backwards;
compare Harvey's answer to Descartes in his 'Second Disquisition to John Riolan,
Jun.', reprinted in Everyman edition (above). Important issues about the
relationship between biology and the physical sciences are reflected in this
debate.
von Haller, A., Dissertation on the Sensible and Irritable
Parts of Animals (1752), with an introduction by 0. Temkin, Bulletin of
the History of Medicine 4 (1936), 651-699. Von Haller's Dissertation is an
important explicit statement of the ways in which biological concepts deviate
from the insistence on physico-chemical reductionism.
Malthus, T. R., An Essay on the Principle of Population (1798; Penguin paperback, with an introduction by A. Flew — a central document
in the history of attempts to apply the methods and categories of science to the
study of man, Malthus' Essay provided the rationalization of most subsequent
social and political and economic views on man's relationship to society and to
nature. At the same time, he provided the key analogy for Darwin's theory of
evolution by natural selection.
Darwin, C., On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural
Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (1859;
Penguin paperback, with an introduction by J. W. Burrow) — the fundamental
argument relating man and society to the laws of biological nature. Although man
is only mentioned in one cautious sentence at the end, Darwin's theory provided
the basis for biological theories of man and society, theories which underlie
the uncertain position of medicine and medical practice at the intersection of
scientific, moral, legal, social and political pressures.
7745 words
This is a modified version of a lecture given in a General
Practitioners' Refresher Course at the Postgraduate Medical School, University
of Cambridge in July 1971. An abbreviated version was published in Science or
Society? 'Special Issue on Medicine and Society' No. 4 (Nov. 1971), pp.
7-12.
Copyright: The Author
Address for corresponndence: 26 Freegrove Road, London, N7
9RQ
robert@rmy1.demon.co.uk