Home What's New
Psychoanalytic Writings
Psychotherapy Service Email Forums and Groups
Process Press Links |
Darwin's Metaphor:
Nature's Place in Victorian Culture
by
[ Introduction | Preface |
Chapter: 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | 6 | Notes | Bibliography | Index ]
CHAPTER II
MALTHUS AND THE EVOLUTIONISTS:
THE COMMON CONTEXT OF BIOLOGICAL AND SOCIAL THEORY
I
Among some historians of science a new awareness is developing, and its sense is that
our work is much less unlike that of other historians than we have hitherto supposed. Both
historians of science and other sorts of historians are coming to see that their interests
cannot be compartmentalized, that - to put it crudely science happened in history and has
influenced historical events increasingly. That there was a need for these changes in
attitude implies that both historians of science and other sorts of historians have tended
to make two related assumptions: first, that scientific ideas and findings can be dealt
with as relatively unequivocal units with fairly sharply defined boundaries and clear-cut
linear influences; and second, that "nonscientific" factors played relatively
little part in shaping the development of scientific ideas. There have been reactions
against these assumptions, which have, however, led to a rather polarized situation with
"internalists" and "externalists" conducting relatively unconnected
studies. What has not been evident is an approach which considers that varied influences
and varying interpretations coming from inside and outside the "scientific"
community as traditionally defined are the rule and not the exception. Rather than having
internalists versus externalists in the history of science, with both of these
groups relatively separated from other sorts of historians, an approach might be developed
which routinely considers social and political factors in scientific research and
scientific factors in social, economic, and political history. What have been seen as
peripheral or specialist
.
24
interests for both historians of science and other historians might come to be seen as
constitutive of the studies of both.
This essay attempts to break down barriers, in one small area, between the history of
science and other branches of history. For Malthus was undoubtedly important in the
history of political, economic, and welfare theory and was at the same time a crucial and
acknowledged influence in the evolutionary debate. In considering his influence I also
want to show just how available his theory was for interpretation in very different senses
both by various evolutionists and by others whose views were markedly different. In a
sense I want to marry history of socioeconomic theory and history of biology or - to alter
the metaphor - to show that Malthus, Paley, Chalmers, Darwin, Charles Lyell, Herbert
Spencer, A. R. Wallace, and others were part of a single debate. Indeed, even some aspects
of Marxist apologetics and Soviet biological theory can be included in this common
context. In doing this I hope to counter at least two sorts of analyses which have
attempted either to absorb Darwin into social theory or to diminish Malthus' role in the
development of evolutionary theory. Instead of seeing Malthus as an influence outside of
biology, I should like to indicate the ways in which his theory and its assumptions about
nature were at once pervasive in the biological literature of the first decades of the
century and a part of an ongoing debate within natural theology which was at least as
important to Darwin and Wallace as the question of the mechanism of evolution. Finally, I
want to suggest that the distinction between social and biological issues - which was in
turn based on the distinction between man and animals which evolutionary theory was
supposed to break down from 1859 onwards - was broken down in principle well before the
turn of the century.
II
When one looks back at Malthus from a post-Darwinian vantage point, his principle of
population - the Malthusian law that population, when unchecked, increases geometrically
while at most the food supply can increase arithmetically - can be seen as a natural law
about man. It is an important step in the series of developments which overcame the belief
that man and his environment were in harmony, and it resulted in man's being seen as an
animal
25
- a part of nature in mind and body. From this point of view then, Malthus was a
biologist, a human ecologist. Indeed, it was evolutionism which brought the
distinction between mind and body into question: if man is considered a person for social
purposes, he remains an organism from a biological point of view. Looking back once again,
one sees Malthus as the source of the view of nature which led to Social Darwinism - the
social struggle for existence, the survival of the fittest.
In the writings of Condorcet and Godwin, Utopian speculation had reached a stage which
contemplated indefinite progress toward the complete absence of struggle among men: no
illness, no sexual urge, no cares. William Godwin's place in the history of economics,
social theory, and literature has been assessed. In the history of evolutionary theory,
however, his role has, as far as I know, received no attention. It was essentially a
negative one, but it was significant nonetheless. His views on the indefinite
perfectibilty of man beyond all the constraints of the earth, animal nature, and social
conflict provided the limiting case of eighteenth-century optimism. In the early editions
of his Political Justice, Godwin argued that man could transcend both inorganic and
organic nature as well as his own passions. Reason was supreme, birth and death could
conceivably cease to occur, and society could approach perfect harmony. The significance
of this view for the history of evolutionary theory is that it so affronted Malthus' sense
of reality that it occasioned his Essay. Even though Malthus softened his doctrine
in later editions, it altered the image of nature from benign harmony to an inexorable
imbalance between nature's supply of sustenance and man's need for both food and sex. It
was this doctrine which served as an important catalyst for the development of
evolutionary theory. Godwin had gone too far in removing man from nature. Malthus'
reaction provided the essential change of perspective for putting man into nature once and
for all. As William Hazlitt put it, Malthus' Essay "made Mr. Godwin and the
other advocates of Modern Philosophy look about them."
The second major occasion of Malthus' reaction was another version of belief in
inevitable progress, that of Condorcet, whose Esquisse d'un tableau historique des
progrès de l'esprit humain was composed while revolutionary Paris was at the height
of the Terror and its author was under sentence of death and in hiding. These
26
circumstances help to highlight the incongruity between man's hopes as described in his
optimistic essay and the actual environment in which he found himself. Condorcet believed
that reason and science would lead to indefinite perfectibility. Free inquiry, liberty,
and justice would increasingly triumph over tyranny, superstition, and prejudice, and
science provided the model for man's enlightenment. Human life would be prolonged
indefinitely, and both the physical and mental constitution of man would undergo limitless
improvement. Slavery and war would cease, and the acquired perfections of an individual
might be transmitted to the next generation by inheritance. Improvements in domesticated
animals lent credence to this hope. There was a possibility that the population might
exceed the means of subsistence, but this day was far away and posed no threat to the
indefinite perfectibility of the human race.
Malthus observes, in the additions made to the Essay in 1817, that
it is probable, that having found the bow bent too much one way, I was induced to bend
it too much the other, in order to make it straight. But I shall always be quite ready to
blot out any part of the work which is considered by a competent tribunal as having a
tendency to prevent the bow from becoming finally straight, and to impede the progress of
truth.
Malthus concentrates first on the impediments to progress, and the perspective
on man's place in nature was radically changed.
III
Malthusianism played a central role in a debate in which social and biological ideas
were part of a common intellectual context. Smith points out that nearly every issue of
the Quarterly Review and Edinburgh Review contains an article on or
reference to the Malthusian debate. Malthus' biographer says that it rained refutations of
Malthus for thirty years. The resulting controversy sprouted everywhere. Malthus' ideas
were as commonplace in the first half of the nineteenth century as Freud's were in the
twentieth. One partial bibliography of the controversy (1793-1880) is thirty pages long.
In 1825, Hazlitt reported that Godwin was something of a living ghost, while
Malthus was one of those rare men who "has not left opinion where he found it."
Robert Wallace, Godwin, Condorcet, and even Paley, among
27
many others, had acknowledged some version of potential disproportion between
population and food supply, but the perspective within which they viewed it
prevented them from taking it seriously as a genuine prospect for mankind. The problem was
absorbed in the general aura of optimism, and lingering doubts were put to sleep with the
promise of progress overcoming the obstacle should it arise.
William Paley considered the issue more directly. That is, he accepted the fact of the
conflict, but he placed it in a perspective which was still fundamentally optimistic. He
reacted in a way which was to become characteristic of sophisticated theologians'
responses to scientific findings: not to deny the fact but to absorb it in a
generalization which was once again comforting. The ways of God were reconciled to man.
The earlier generation had not felt the need for reconciliation so acutely. Paley
addressed himself to Malthus' theory in his Natural Theology (1802). The last
chapters are concerned with the personality, natural attributes, unity, and goodness of
the Deity. He begins this part of his argument by rejecting the gradual origin of species
by natural means. It is when he turns to the "Goodness of the Deity" that he
defends design: "Nor is design abortive. It is a happy world after all."
"But pain, no doubt, and privation exist. . . ." "Evil, no doubt, exists;
but it is never, that we can perceive, the object of contrivance." Animals
devouring one another is, however, a worrying case. Can this be deemed evil? No, since
immortality would otherwise be out of the question; pursuing prey affords pleasure to the
pursuer; and a quick death is preferable to a slow one. Nature is very fecund; indeed it
displays "superfecundity." Think of gnats and plagues of mice. This
excess is easy to regulate, much easier than it would be to replenish a scarcity. Even so,
nature cannot receive and support all her progeny. Superabundance requires destruction,
otherwise any animal could overrun the world. "It is necessary, therefore, that the
effects of such prolific faculties be curtailed. In conjunction with other checks and
limits, all subservient to the same purposes, are the thinnings which take place
among animals, by their action upon one another." Species keep one another within
bounds. "Though there may be the appearance of failure in some of the details of
Nature's works, in her great purposes there never are." Paley concludes quite
comfortably: "We have dwelt the longer on these considerations, because the subject
to which they
28
apply, namely, that of animals devouring one another, forms the chief, if not
the only instance, in the works of the Deity, of an economy, stamped by marks of design,
in which the character of utility can be called in question." But, of course, the
contrivances are beneficial if only we take a broad view. He provides benevolent
justifications for private property, bodily pain (noting the comfort that derives from the
cessation of the latter), disease, mortal disease ("The horror of death proves the
value of life"), and death ("All must be changed"). When Paley arrives at
an explicit statement of the Malthusian doctrine, it is expressed in the same perhaps even
more - reassuring terms, under the heading of the evils of civil life. Paley says that
these
are much more easily disposed of than physical evils: because they are, in truth, of
much less magnitude, and also because they result from a kind of necessity, not only from
the constitution of our nature, but from a part of that constitution which no one would
wish to see altered. The case is this: Mankind will in every country breed up to a
certain point of distress. . . . The order of generation proceeds by something like a
geometrical progression. The increase of provision, under circumstances even the most
advantageous, can only assume the form of an arithmetic series. Whence it follows, that
the population will always overtake the provision, will pass beyond the line of plenty,
and will continue to increase till checked by the difficulty of procuring subsistence.
([fn.] See a statement of this subject, in a late treatise upon population.) Such
difficulty therefore, along with its attendant circumstances, must be found in
every old country: and these circumstances constitute what we call poverty, which
necessarily imposes labour, servitude, restraint.
He argues that this process may hurt some but increases the mean happiness of
all, and goes on to extol the benefits of good government, religion, clean living, and
"the possession of well-directed tastes and desires, compared with the dominion of
tormenting, pernicious, contradictory, unsatisfied, and unsatisfiable passion." The
chapter concludes with gentle defenses of distinctions in civil life, distribution of
money, station, and property. He says, for example, "The distinctions of civil life
are apt enough to be regarded as evils, by those who sit under them; but, in my opinion,
with very little reason." Nature's harmony and man's moral agency are the universal
reassurances for Paley.
A contemporary said of Malthus: "We have repeatedly heard him say that the two
converts of whom he was most proud were
29
Dr. Paley and Mr. Pitt." Pitt did drop his bill for extending poor relief
to larger families. He grasped Malthus' point: God would not provide food for all the
mouths but more than enough mouths for all the food. Paley was a less clearheaded convert.
Although he accepted the words of Malthus' theory, he saw it in a context which was very
different from the one which was generated as a result of Malthus' influence on others. In
Paley's hands and in those of many scientists who tried to include Malthus within a
complacent natural theology, the Malthusian principle was a means for periodically
reestablishing the harmony of nature. Far from being a mechanism for change, it was a
defense of the status quo both in nature and in society. The Malthusian law led to
suffering and death, and even to extinction of species, but not to a change in the
constitution of nature. I am not suggesting that Malthus felt that his Essay could
not be reconciled with natural theology. In fact, the first edition (which Paley read)
contained two concluding chapters which were explicitly concerned with the relationship
between his view and "our ideas of the power, goodness and foreknowledge of the
Deity" - Malthus' attempt, as he put it, to "Vindicate the ways of God to
man." His intention is to look the actual phenomena of nature full in the
face. If this view gives, as he says "a melancholy hue" to human life then this
view must be explained and justified. It is explained in terms of the necessity for evil
in order to produce exertion, exertion to produce mind, and mind to produce progress.
"Necessity has with great truth been called the mother of invention." Man is
sinful, inert, sluggish, and averse to labor, unless compelled by necessity. "Had
population and food increased in the same ratio, it is probable that man might never have
emerged from the savage state." Once man reached the civilized state, the Malthusian
law became a check upon further progress. Paley almost exclusively stressed harmony and
benevolence at the expense of the unpalatable facts. Harmony, not struggle, was the
keynote. The disharmony between man and nature which Malthus had made the basis of his
antidote to optimism was not prominent in Paley. He did not go to the extremes of
Condorcet and Godwin in arguing that men were indefinitely perfectible and could live
indefinitely long, but he did emphasize that pain and death and extinction were
adjustments in order to reestablish harmony.
Lest these views be considered the ultimate in sanguine approaches
30
to pain and suffering, it is worth noting that they represent a considerable
modification of Paley's earlier ideas on population. Seventeen years earlier, in his Principles
of Moral and Political Philosophy, he had argued that the quantity of happiness
in a given district depends on the number of people and that ". . . the collective
happiness will be nearly in the exact proportion of the numbers, that is, twice the number
of inhabitants will produce double the quantity of happiness . . . consequently, the decay
of population is the greatest evil that a state can suffer; and the improvement of it [is]
the object which ought, in all countries, to be aimed at in preference to every other
political purpose whatsoever." He noted that food supply was an "insuperable
bar" but that the bar never operates, since there is so much fertile land, and man is
such an industrious cultivator. Increase of population was an unqualified good, and his
argument is devoted to means of furthering this end. In the light of Paley's earlier
views, the statements in his Natural Theology are temperate.
Since Darwin was strongly influenced by both Malthus and Paley, this is the appropriate
place to make the point that their respective roles in the development of his evolutionary
theory were strikingly different. Although Paley accepts Malthus' theory, he does so in a
way which was unlikely to draw Darwin's attention to the significance of conflict in
nature. Darwin read Paley's Natural Theology while an undergraduate at Cambridge
(indeed, everyone did: it remained a set book for all undergraduates until 1921). He
tells us in his autobiography that the logic of Paley's Evidences and his Natural
Theology
gave me as much delight as did Euclid. The careful study of these works, without
attempting to learn any part by rote, was the only part of the Academical Course which, as
I then felt and as I still believe, was of the least use to me in the education of my
mind. I did not at that time trouble myself about Paley's premises; and taking these on
trust I was charmed and convinced by the long line of argumentation.
Although a strong case can be made for the influence of Paley on Darwin's view of
adaptation, it would be extremely difficult to maintain that Paley's version of Malthus
could have influenced or did influence Darwin when he was casting about for a mechanism
for evolutionary change seven years later. It was when he read Malthus in 1838 that he was
struck by an interpretation of nature
31
which reinforced that gained from Lyell (who also uses Malthus to explain problems of
ecology and extinction) and from the study of domesticated animals. Thus, Paley and
Malthus influenced Darwin in very different ways. Paley stresses perfect adaptation;
Malthus stresses conflict. These were, at one level, antithetical. Darwin synthesizes
them. Struggle both explains and produces adaptation.
Many of Darwin's examples in On the Origin of Species are the same as Paley's.
Where Paley had considered each adaptation to be a separate proof of God's wisdom, power,
and goodness, Darwin considered it a problem requiring a natural explanation.
Nevertheless, Darwin retained the requirement that each adaptation must be beneficial:
"Natural selection will never produce in a being anything injurious to itself, for
natural selection acts solely by and for the good of each. No organ will be formed as
Paley has remarked, for the purpose of causing pain or for doing an injury to its
possessor."
IV
Malthus dropped the chapters on natural theology from the second edition of his Essay, although it is still possible to see his original theodicy at work. He also
acknowledged his authorship, increased its bulk many times, and changed the subtitle. The
first subtitle had referred to the principle of population "as it affects the future
improvement of society, with remarks on the speculations of Mr. Godwin, M. Condorcet, and
other writers." The second edition (1803) referred to "a view of its past and
present effects on human happiness; with an inquiry into our prospects respecting the
future removal or mitigation of the evils which it occasions." Malthus turns his
attention from speculations on the perfectibility of man and society to amassing data on
the effects of the principle and to a new check on population which does not come under
the head of either vice or misery. He softens some of the harshest conclusions of the
first essay by including this factor of "moral restraint" from marriage. As with
the exclusion of natural theology, the distinction between editions is not complete. The
doctrine of moral or prudential restraint from marriage until one could support a wife and
family was not absent from the first edition, but it was not stressed. Even so, Malthus
was right to
32
distinguish the second edition as "a new work." Another important change in
the second and later editions was that the Essay became less of a personal and
polemical tract. The criticisms of Godwin and Condorcet remained, but the attack on the
poor laws, which was secondary in the Essay of 1798, usurped the position of
the attack on perfectibility. The doctrine of "moral restraint" and the
criticism of public charity provided the source for a very different interpretation of
Malthus which replaced Paley's harmonious view of nature based on a deist's view of God
with a Calvinist interpretation of the Deity as an implacable Old Testament Judge.
Paley's Natural Theology provided the inspiration for a series of remarkable
works which - in eleven volumes - bored the public with a dropsical version of the thesis
that all of nature shows design and that the argument is cumulative, case by case. The
Earl of Bridgewater left £8,000 for a work
On the Power, Wisdom, and Goodness of God, as manifested in the Creation; illustrating
such work by all reasonable arguments, as for instance, the variety and formation of God's
creatures in the animal, vegetable, and mineral kingdoms; the effect of digestion, and
thereby of conversion; the construction of the hand of man, and an infinite variety of
other arguments; as also by discoveries ancient and modern, in arts, sciences, and the
whole extent of literature.
The intentions of the will were carried out by the President of the Royal Society, the
Archbishop of Canterbury, and the Bishop of London, who, in turn, chose the Rev. Thomas
Chalmers, Professor of Divinity in the University of Edinburgh, to write the first of the
eight works, entitled On the Power, Wisdom and Goodness of God as Manifested in
the Adaptation of External Nature to the Moral and Intellectual Constitution of
Man, which appeared in two volumes in 1833, and went through six editions. The
Bridgewater Treatises on the Power Wisdom and Goodness of God as Manifested in the
Creation are of interest, because they constituted an encyclopedia of preevolutionary
natural history. They were commissioned and appeared while Darwin was on the 40,000-mile
voyage of the Beagle around the world, during which he studied the distribution of
fossils, of live animals, and of South American species. These were the facts which led
him to believe that species might be mutable. Chalmers' treatise is particularly
interesting for two reasons. First, it was one
33
of two on man (N. B. nature was adapted to man, not the other way around): a
separate one was commissioned on man's body; and, second, because Chalmers was besotted
with the Malthusian Law, which he interpreted very differently from Paley. Sin and moral
restraint were the most important concepts in Chalmers' natural theology. Where Malthus
had stressed a dismal law of nature alleviated by moral restraint, Chalmers focused on
moral restraint itself.
Chalmers saw his life's work as the unification of religious doctrine and laissez-faire
economic theory. His writings embraced natural theology, political economy, and geology (a
combination that was not unusual in the period). In his Political Economy (1832) he
argued that "the right economic condition of the masses is dependent on their right
moral conditions, that character is the parent of comfort, not vice versa." Since at
least 1808 he had been arguing in particular against state charity on Malthusian grounds.
He claimed that more state charity meant an end to individual industry. If there were more
charity, the demand would rise to exhaust it. He said that Malthus' theory would have
convinced him even without examples. "But it seldom happens that a speculation so
apparently paradoxical is so well supported by the most triumphant exemplifications."
It is quite vain to think that positive relief will ever do away the
wretchedness of poverty. Carry the relief beyond a certain limit, and you foster the
diseased principle which gives birth to poverty........ The remedy against the extension
of pauperism does not lie in the liberalities of the rich; it lies in the hearts and
habits of the poor. Plant in their bosoms a principle of independence - give a high tune
of delicacy to their characters - teach them to recoil from pauperism as a degradation.
The panacea was that men should reform their habits by means of the influence of the
Scriptures. Only 10 percent of pauperism could be attributed to genuine misfortune; the
rest was moral sloth. "The shame of descending [into pauperism] is the powerful
stimulus which urges them to a manly contest with the difficulties of their situation; and
which bears them through in all the pride of honest independence."
Chalmers' Political Economy, published a year before his Bridgewater
Treatise, repeated this point ad nauseam. Its subtitle conveys the context: On
Political Economy, in Connection with the Moral State
34
and Moral Respects of Society. Chalmers' litany is represented by the following
passage:
It is not by means of economic enlargements, but of moral principles and restraints,
that the problem of our difficulties is at length to be fully and satisfactorily resolved.
No possible enlargement from without will ever suffice for the increasing wants of a
recklessly increasing population. We look for our coming deliverance in a moral change,
and not in any, or in all, of those economic changes put together, which form the great
panacea of so many of our statesmen. Without the prudence, and the virtue, and the
intelligence of our common people, we shall only have a bulkier, but withal as wretched
and distempered a community as ever; and we repeat, that a thorough education, in both the
common and Christian sense of the term, forms the only solid basis, on which either the
political and economic wellbeing of the nation can be laid.
The criticisms of a contemporary reviewer help to illustrate this use of the moral
theory in Malthus in an extreme form (in contrast with Paleyan harmony on the one hand and
with Darwinian naturalism on the other). G. Poulett Scrope, who had distinguished careers
in both political economy and geology, begins his review of Chalmers' Political Economy in the Quarterly by praising Chalmers as a pastor but adds that
we cannot pretend to rate him so highly as a political arithmetician....... We shall
not be suspected of undervaluing the efficacy of a Christian education, when we hesitate
to believe that this is the only desideratum in our civic and national economy, or the
only remedy for the existing evils of our social conditions capable of affording us the
least glimpse of hope.
(Where some feared education lest the poor read Tom Paine, Malthus advocated the study
of political economy, and Chalmers the Bible.) Scrope points out Chalmers' well-known
inveterate hostility to any public provision for the poor - his adherence to the
Malthusian theory of population, and the Malthusian remedy for its apparent excess,
"the prudential check."
The one main principle to which every argument on every subject is there referred, and
by which every question is decided, is the Malthusian axiom..... From this axiom the
obvious deduction is, that all enlargements of the means of subsistence do more harm than
good..... that all improvements in agriculture are curses and that we should not increase
subsistence but check the increase of the persons to be subsisted!
35
Economic remedies for improving the condition of the lower classes only generate
further misery "for the very reason that they are immediately beneficial" -
thereby encouraging breeding.
It is, indeed, [Scrope continues] an extraordinary monomania which affects these
gentlemen. The idea of an ultimate limit to the globe's possible productiveness tyrannizes
over their imaginations, and gives rise to the strangest opinions and rules of conduct.
Dr. Chalmers overtops them all: his whole soul is absorbed by the frightful prospect of
the time when every rood of soil on the face of the earth shall maintain its full
complement of human beings . . .
Scrope feels that "to persuade us to have recourse to it [the Malthusian specific]
NOW, is indeed right midsummer madness - the ne plus ultra of moonstruck, Laputan
philosophy." In the concluding passages he says, "We submit, therefore, that the
true policy deducible from the Malthusian premises, is, that we should not merely abolish
the poor laws, but go on to dispatch the surplus population as it appears."
Recovering himself, Scrope grants that Chalmers, having himself exhausted all other
palliatives as selfdefeating,
brings us in triumph to the "argal" at which he has been all along
straining, viz. that since nothing can make food keep pace with population, all our
efforts should be turned to make population keep pace with food; and the only specific for
this is "prudential restraint upon marriage" self-imposed by each individual,
and inculcated by a Christian education.
This has the effect, he concludes, of freeing the government "from all
responsibility for the sufferings of the mass of the community, by throwing the blame
entirely on Nature and the improvidence of the poor themselves, and declaring the
evil to admit of no remedy from any possible exertions of the legislature."
Chalmers' natural theology removes Malthus' theory from the status of something to be
explained away à la Paley and places it at the center of a different interpretation of
nature. Indeed, to turn now to his Bridgewater Treatise, Chalmers explicitly takes
Paley to task for stressing God's natural attributes at the expense of his moral ones.
Academic natural theologians like Paley, he continues, are apt to stress God's benign
virtues and "to overlook the virtues of the Lawgiver and Judge."
When we take this fuller view of God's moral nature - when we make account of the
righteousness as well as the benevolence - when we yield
36
to the suggestion of our own hearts, that to Him belongs the sovereign state, and, if
needful, the severity of the lawgiver, as well as the fond affection of the parent - when
we assign to Him, the character, which, instead of but one virtue, is comprehensive of
them all - we are then on firmer vantage-ground for the establishment of a Natural
Theology, in harmony, both with the lessons of conscience, and with the phenomena of the
natural world.
When we consider only the infinite benevolence of the Deity, we produce a natural
theology which cannot explain "the numerous ills, wherewith the world is
infested." It remains a complete mystery why "there should be any suffering at
all." Chalmers has no such problem: ". . . it will be found," he says,
"that the vast amount of human wretchedness, can be directly referred to the
waywardness and morbid state of human will - to the character of man, and not to the
condition which he occupies." Thus, the Malthusian law becomes the center of both
political economy and natural theology.
Two passages convey the full force of Chalmers' rendering of Malthus:
... for throughout, political economy is but one grand exemplification of the alliance,
which a God of righteousness hath established, between prudence and moral principle on the
one hand, and physical comfort on the other. However obnoxious the modern doctrine of
population, as expounded by Mr. Malthus, may have been, and still is, to weak and limited
sentimentalists, it is the truth which of all others sheds the greatest brightness over
the earthly prospects of humanity - and this in spite of the hideous, the yet sustained
outcry which has risen against it. This is a pure case of adaptation, between the external
nature of the world in which we live, and the moral nature of man, its chief occupier.
There is a demonstrable inadequacy in all the material resources which the globe can
furnish, for the increasing wants of a recklessly increasing species. But over and against
this, man is gifted with a moral and a mental power by which the inadequacy might be fully
countervailed; and the species, in virtue of their restrained and regulated numbers, be
upholden on the face of our world, in circumstances of large and stable sufficiency, even
to the most distant ages. The first origin of this blissful consummation is in the virtue
of the people; but carried into sure and lasting effect by the laws of political economy,
through the indissoluble connection which obtains between the wages and the supply of
labor - so that in every given state of commerce and civilization, the amount of the
produce of industry and the produce of the soil, which shall fall to the share of the
37
work-men is virtually at the determination of the work-men themselves, who, by dint of
resolute prudence and resolute principle together, may rise to an indefinitely higher
status than they now occupy, of comfort and independence in the Commonwealth. This opens
up a cheering prospect to the lovers of our race; and not the less so, that it is seen
through the medium of popular intelligence and virtue - the only medium through which it
can ever be realised. And it sheds a revelation, not only on the hopeful destinies of man,
but on the character of God - in having instituted this palpable alliance between the
moral and the physical; and so assorted the economy of outward nature to the economy of
human principles and passions. The lights of modern science have made us apprehend more
clearly, by what steps the condition and the character of the common people rise and fall
with each other - insomuch, that, while on the one hand their general destitution is the
inevitable result of their general worthlessness, they, on the other, by dint of wisdom
and moral strength, can augment indefinitely, not the produce of the earth, nor the
produce of human industry, but that proportion of both which falls to their own share.
Their economic is sure to follow by successive advances in the career of their moral
elevation; nor do we hold it impossible, or even unlikely - that gaining, every
generation, on the distance which now separates them from the upper classes of society,
they shall, in respect both of decent sufficiency and dignified leisure, make perpetual
approximations to the followship and enjoyments of cultivated life.
The rule of God is the rule of a steadfast Malthusian. The moral order depends on it:
It enters into the very essence of our conception of a moral government, that it must
have sanctions - which could not have place, were there either to be no dispensation of
rewards and punishments; or were the penalties, though denounced with all the parade and
proclamation of law, to be never executed. It is not the lesson of conscience, that God
would, under the mere impulse of a parental fondness for the creatures whom He had made,
let down the high state and sovereignty which belong to Him; or that He would forbear the
infliction of the penalty, because of any soft or timid shrinking from the pain it would
give to the objects of His displeasure. There is nothing either in history or nature,
which countenances such an imagination of the Deity, as that, in the relentings of mere
tenderness, He would stoop to any weak or unworthy compromise with guilt. The actual
sufferings of life speak loudly and experimentally against the supposition; and when one
looks to the disease and the agony of spirit, and above all the hideous and unsparing
death, with its painful struggles and gloomy forebodings, which are spread universally
over the face of the earth - we cannot but imagine of the God who
38
presides over such an economy, that He is not a being who will falter from the
imposition of any severity, which might serve the objects of a high administration. Else
all steadfastness of purpose, and steadfastness of principle were fallen from. God would
stand forth to the eye of His own creatures, a spectacle of outraged dignity. And He of
whom we image that He dwells in an unviolable sanctuary, the august monarch of heaven and
earth - with a law by subjects dishonoured, by the sovereign unavenged - would possess but
the semblance and the mockery of a throne.
There is a perfectly good basis in Malthus' Essay for Chalmers' reading:
"Hard as it may appear in individual instances, dependent poverty ought to be held
disgraceful. Such a stimulus seems to be absolutely necessary to promote the happiness of
the great mass of mankind; and every general attempt to weaken this stimulus, however
benevolent its intention, will always defeat its own purpose." Malthus' specific
proposals reflected no hesitation over applying strong sanctions: "To this end, I
should propose a regulation to be made, declaring, that no child born from any marriage,
taking place after the expiration of a year from the date of the law, and no illegitimate
child born two years from the same date, should ever be entitled to parish
assistance." The Dickensian workhouse was, in part, a consequence of the views which
Malthus and Chalmers shared.
Chalmers does not shrink from the existence of evil, suffering, and struggle, but all
are absorbed into a moral context. This is what is most remarkable about his treatise. The
choice of author and his treatment of the subject in terms of a stern, Old Testament,
judicial, and vengeful God, instead of the psychological and even the ethical discussions
of the day, are significant. Indeed, the failure to discuss the data of man's relationship
to nature is also significant. In spite of the title of the treatise, man is considered
neither naturalistically nor psychologically. (Aspects of the psychological theories of
Thomas Brown are discussed but only those which are concerned with the conscience.)
In complaining about the redundancy of the Bridgewater Treatises, another
reviewer of Chalmers says that
Dr. Chalmers is in fact the only writer amongst the eight who occupies a territory
which he may call his own. But the manner in which he came into the possession of it will
not, perhaps, be deemed perfectly legitimate. That able divine was requested to point out
the adaptation of
39
external nature to man's intellectual and moral constitution. This certainty must be
admitted to be a task of extreme difficulty in the execution. We all perceive the relation
of external nature, composed of the fertile earth, its varied produce, the sea, the
atmosphere, the sun, and especially our own satellite, to our physical necessities; but
their adaptation to the intellect, which seeks higher objects of contemplation, is not so
obvious. Dr. Chalmers was, therefore, reduced to the necessity of considering men in
general as "external nature," in relation to an individual of the species; by
this contrivance he has been enabled to shape his theme to his own studies, and to furnish
us with two volumes on metaphysics and ethics! The books will doubtless have their
admirers, but we apprehend that they are not of the class of literature which the Earl of
Bridgewater had in his view when he made his will.
He goes on to say that Chalmers' work in the pulpit, the professorial chair, and the
closet of the political economist is admirable and worthy of respect for his genius.
Nevertheless, these volumes are disappointing. Ordinary ideas are complicated by endless
mazes of language and neologisms. In sum, an unworthy work. However, in the context of a
study of the uses to which Malthus' theory was put, Chalmers' view represents the extreme
of an anti-naturalist interpretation in a sense which was different from his
contemporaries. The most relevant contrast is with the eighteenth-century optimists. Where
Godwin and Condorcet predicted indefinite progress by means of reason and the effort of
thought, Chalmers held out the same hope if men would only obey their consciences and
engage in the requisite moral struggle: if they failed to do so they would suffer the
penalties of a Stern Judge.
V
Paley emphasized nature's harmony, and Chalmers concentrated on the wars of nature and
society in an entirely moral context. Darwin took Paley's answers and converted them into
questions. Adaptations needed explaining: they were not each evidence of piecemeal
designs; they came to be. How? It is here that Darwin removed "moral restraint"
from the Malthusian doctrine, which he then applied in the first instance to animals, not
to man, and used as an answer to the question of how Paley's beautiful adaptations came to
be. The Malthusian doctrine is then, secondarily,
40
reapplied to man. In the crucial passage in Darwin's Autobiography, written
thirty years after the event, he gives the proper emphasis to his reading of Malthus:
In October 1838, that is, fifteen months after I had begun my systematic inquiry, I
happened to read for amusement Malthus on Population, and being well prepared to
appreciate the struggle for existence which everywhere goes on from long-continued
observation of the habits of animals and plants, it at once struck me that under these
circumstances favourable variations would tend to be preserved, and unfavourable ones to
be destroyed. The result of this would be the formation of a new species. Here, then, I
had at last got a theory by which to work; but I was so anxious to avoid prejudice, that I
determined not for some time to write even the briefest sketch of it.
In order to demonstrate this influence, it is worth exploring Darwin's remarks on
Malthus, moving backward from his mature work to his earliest evolutionary
notebooks. In The Variation of animals and Plants under Domestication (1868), he
recalls the genesis of his theory. As he pondered the evidence gathered in his travels in
South America, he was left with an
inexplicable problem [of] how the necessary degree of modification could have been
effected [for evolution to have occurred], and it would have thus remained forever,
had I not studied domestic productions, and thus acquired a just idea of the power of
Selection. As soon as I had fully realized this idea, I saw, on reading Malthus on Population, that Natural Selection was the inevitable result of the rapid increase of all organic
beings; for I was prepared to appreciate the struggle for existence by having long studied
the habits of animals.
In the first edition of On the Origin of Species (1859) Darwin introduces his
argument by reviewing the order of presentation. His first chapters are devoted to the
subjects of variation under domestication and under nature. The summary continues,
"In the next chapter the Struggle for Existence among all organic beings throughout
the world, which inevitably follows from their high geometrical powers of increase, will
be treated of. This is the doctrine of Malthus, applied to the whole animal and vegetable
kingdoms." More are born than can survive. This leads to struggle for existence; any
slight favorable variation will lead to a better chance of survival and be naturally
selected, and this new form will be
41
propagated to future generations. In 1859 he wrote to A. R. Wallace, as follows:
You are right, that I came to the conclusion that selection was the principle of change
from the study of domesticated productions; and then, reading Malthus, I saw at once how
to apply this principle. Geographical distribution and geological relations of extinct to
recent inhabitants of South America first led me to the subject: especially the case of
the Galapagos Islands.
In the passage in his autobiography in which he mentions the effect of reading Malthus,
he continues, "In June 1842 I first allowed myself the satisfaction of writing a very
brief abstract of my theory in pencil in 35 pages; and this was enlarged during the
summer of 1844 into one of 230 pages, which I had fairly copied out and still
possess." In the 1844 Essay, he writes:
It is the doctrine of Malthus applied in most cases with ten-fold force. As in every
climate there are seasons for each of its inhabitants of greater and less abundance, so
all annually breed; and the moral restraint, which in some small degree checks the
increase of mankind, is entirely lost. Even slow-breeding mankind has doubled in
twenty-five years, and if he could increase his food with greater ease, he would double in
less time. But for animals, without artificial means, on an average the
amount of food for each species must be constant; whereas the increase for all organisms
tends to be geometrical, and in a vast majority of cases at an enormous ratio.
In the pencil sketch of 1842, written as cryptic notes, Darwin again stresses the
importance of removing moral restraint from Malthus' doctrine in order to arrive at his
own theory:
But considering the enormous geometrical power of increase in every organism and
as every country, in ordinary cases, must be stocked to full extent, reflection will show
that this is the case. Malthus on man - in animals no moral [check] restraint - they breed
in time of year when provision most abundant, or season most favourable, every country has
its season - calculate robins - oscillating from years of destruction.... the pressure is
always ready . . . a thousand wedges are being forced into the economy of nature. This
requires much reflection; study Malthus and calculate rates of increase and remember the
resistance - only periodical.... In the course of a thousand generations infinitesimally
small dilterences must inevitably tell...
42
If one looks closely at Darwin's working notebooks, which he began in 1837 as a place
to put all his notes and reflections on the "species question," there is
unequivocal evidence for Malthus' role in the actual formation of Darwin's idea. Sometime
between 28 September and 12 October 1838, he read Malthus. One can often go
directly to Darwin's marginal notes in assessing the role of some of the influences on
him, but in this case he was in London and almost undoubtedly read his brother's copy. In
his notebook "D" he wrote (at a later date), "Towards close I first thought
of selection owing to struggle." Among the pages excised by Darwin for use in writing
his great work entitled Natural Selection, one finds the following passage:
[Sept] 28th. We ought to be far from wondering of changes in numbers of species,
from small changes in nature of locality. Even the energetic language of Decandolle does
not convey the warring of the species as inference from Malthus - increase of brutes must be prevented solely by positive checks, excepting that famine may stop desire. - in
nature production does not increase, whilst no check prevail, but the positive check of
famine and consequently death. I do not doubt every one till he thinks deeply has assumed
that increase of animals exactly proportionate to the number that can live. - . . .
Population is increase at geometrical ratio in FAR SHORTER time than 25 years - yet
until the one sentence of Malthus no one clearly perceived the great check amongst men. -
there is spring, like food used for other purposes as wheat for making brandy - Even a few years plenty, makes population in man increase & an ordinary crop causes a
dearth. take Europe on an average every species must have some number killed year with
year by hawks by cold &c. - even one species of hawk decreasing in number must atfect
instantaneously all the rest. - The final cause of all this wedging, must be to sort out
proper structure, and adapt it to change. - to do that for form, which Malthus shows is
the final effect (by means however of volition) of this populousness on the energy of man.
One may say there is a force like a hundred thousand wedges trying [to] force every kind
of adapted structure into the gaps in the oeconomy of nature, or rather forming gaps by
thrusting out weaker ones.
In notebook "E," begun in October 1838, Darwin writes, "Epidemics seem
intimately related to famine, yet very inexplicable." (This refers to the chapters on
epidemics in Malthus' essay.) Darwin goes on quoting Malthus and adds his own italics and
exclamations; the sense of excitement is palpable:
43
"It accords with the most liberal! spirit of philosophy to believe
that no stone can fall, or plant rise, without the immediate agency of the deity [Malthus
wrote "divine power"]. But we know from experience! that these operations
of what we call nature, have been conducted almost! invariably according to fixed
laws: and since the work began, the causes of population & depopulation have been
probably as constant as any of the laws of nature with which we are acquainted." -
This applies to one species - I would apply it not only to population & depopulation,
but extermination and production of new forms - this number and correlations.
On the next page Darwin mentions "my theory" and the small changes involved
in the slow process; subsequent pages mention "the theory" and "my
theory."
It appears, then, that it was the removal of Malthus' idea of "moral
restraint" and an emphasis on the concept of "population pressure," which
left a natural law about plants and animals, that characterized Darwin's interpretation.
He was, in effect, reverting to the purity of the inescapable dilemma of Malthus' first
edition. It is "the strong law of necessity" which Malthus emphasizes repeatedly
in both editions, even though in the second it lies side by side with the partial
palliative of "moral restraint." References with this deterministic basis appear
in tens of places in both editions and might themselves have influenced Darwin's
application of the principle to man: for example, "Elevated as man is above all other
animals by his intellectual faculties, it is not to be supposed that the physical laws to
which he is subjected should be essentially different from those which are observed to
prevail in other parts of animated nature." One could go on to cite Malthus'
analogies of population studies with the laws of mechanics and ballistics and the
invocation of Newton, as well as his opposition to miraculous explanations, but there are
sources enough for these elements of Darwin's view. In particular, Charles Lyell's Principles of Geology, the work which most influenced Darwin (as it did Wallace and Spencer),
contains many references of this kind, including innumerable passages on struggle: for
example, "In the universal struggle for existence, the right of the strongest
eventually prevails; and the strength and durability of a race depends mainly on its
prolificness, in which hybrids are acknowledged to be deficient." Without working
systematically I have seen fifteen other references to struggle in volume two alone.
Indeed, Lyell used the
44
concept of struggle to explain many of the facts of geographical distribution and of
extinction but refrained from applying it to the problem of the origin of new species. It
seems that Malthus legitimated the idea of a law of struggle, impressed Darwin with the
intensity of struggle, and provided a convenient natural mechanism for the changes which
Darwin was studying in the selection of domesticated varieties. It gave Darwin the analogy
he needed to move from artificial to natural selection. He tell us that this was an
essential step in his reasoning: indefinite variation and natural selection could produce
new species.
VI
Whereas Darwin had returned from six years of fieldwork with the question of evolution
in his mind, Alfred Russel Wallace had gone to the field convinced that evolution occurs
and attempted to find out how. He had been led to this conclusion by Robert Chambers' Vestiges
of the Natural History of Creation and George Combe's phrenological doctrines, along
with Lyell's Principles and Darwin's Journal of Researches. The fact that he
came to these questions about ten years after Darwin, and as a result of reading Chambers
and Combe, gave a different emphasis to his inquiries. It was man's place in nature which
interested him most. Recall that Darwin wrote more on plants than on animals and more on
animals than on man. His The Descent of Man was, as he said, unoriginal. With
Wallace it was different. The ubiquitous Malthusian principle operates as a benevolent
dispensation to keep man in touch with the laws of nature in the influential works of
Chambers and Combe. But, in the same period 1844-5, Wallace read Malthus' Essay itself.
Speaking of this period Wallace says in his autobiography:
But perhaps the most important book I read was Malthus's "Principles of
Population," which I greatly admired for its masterly summary of the facts and
logical induction to conclusions. It was the first work I had yet read treating of any of
the problems of philosophical biology, and its main principles remained with me as a
permanent possession, and twenty years later gave me the long-sought clue to the effective
agent in the evolution of organic species.
Wallace was then in his early twenties. A few pages later he refers to the reading of
Malthus as one of the two events which formed
45
the turning point in his life, "without which work I should probably not have hit
upon the theory of natural selection and obtained full credit for its independent
discovery." Indeed, Wallace first uses the concept of struggle as applied to man, in
a Malthusian context. In 1853, he wrote, "It is the responsibility and
self-dependence of manhood that calls forth the highest powers and energies of our race.
It is the struggle for existence, the 'battle of life,' which exercises the moral
faculties and calls forth the latent spark of genius." Similarly, in his 1855 paper
in which Wallace advocates evolution without supplying a mechanism, he quotes a passage
from Lyell describing the struggle for existence. But his theory still lacked the
essential ingredient, the concept that only the fittest survive the struggle for
existence. When Wallace did hit upon the idea of survival of the fittest, it was in the
context of ethnological investigations into the origin of human races in the Malay
Archipelago. We have four accounts of this from Wallace, and they all exhibit the feature
of beginning with Malthus' theory applied to the human species and then extended to other
species.
... while again considering the problem of the origin of species, something led me to
think of Malthus' Essay on Population (which I had read about ten years before), and the
"positive checks" - war, disease, famine, accidents, etc. - which he adduced as
keeping all savage populations nearly stationary. It then occurred to me that these checks
must also act upon animals, and keep down their numbers, and as they increase so much
faster than man does, . . . it was clear to me that these checks in their case must be far
more powerful.... While vaguely thinking how this would affect any species, there suddenly
flashed upon me the idea of the survival of the fittest ...
The second account, written in 1903, also contrasts animals and man in degree of
effect. The locus classicus for Wallace's version of the theory (and indeed, one of
the most dramatic descriptions of a scientific discovery) occurs in his autobiography and
shows clearly that recalling Malthus' theory was the crucial experience in the formulation
of his own hypothesis.
At the time in question [1858] I was suffering from a sharp attack of intermittent
fever [malaria], and every day during the cold and succeeding hot fits had to lie down for
several hours, during which time I had nothing to do but to think over any subjects then
particularly interesting me. One day something brought to my recollection Malthus's
46
"Principles of Population", which I had read about twelve years before. I
thought of his clear exposition of "the positive checks to increase" - disease,
accidents, war, and famine - which keep down the population of savage races to so much
lower an average than that of more civilized peoples. It then occurred to me that these
causes or their equivalents are continually acting in the case of animals also; and as
animals usually breed much more rapidly than does mankind, the destruction every year from
these causes must be enormous in order to keep down the numbers of each species, since
they evidently do not increase regularly from year to year, as otherwise the world would
long ago have been densely crowded with those that breed most quickly. Vaguely thinking
over the enormous and constant destruction which this implied, it occurred to me to ask
the question, Why do some die and some live? And the answer was clearly, that on the whole
the best fitted live. From the effects of disease the most healthy escaped; from enemies,
the strongest, the swiftest, or the most cunning; from famine, the best hunters or those
with the best digestion; and so on. Then it suddenly flashed upon me that this self-acting
process would necessarily improve the race, because in every generation the
inferior would inevitably be killed off and the superior would remain - that is, thefittest
would survive. Then at once I seemed to see the whole effect of this, that when
changes of land and sea, or of climate, or of food-supply, or of enemies occurred - and we
know that such changes have always been taking place - and considering the amount of
individual variation that my experience as a collector had shown me to exist, then it
followed that all the changes necessary for the adaptation of the species to the changing
conditions would be brought about; and as great changes in the environment are always
slow, there would be ample time for the change to be effected by the survival of the best
fitted in every generation. In this way every part of an animal's organization could be
modified exactly as required, and in the very process of this modification the unmodified
would die out, and thus the definite characters and the clear isolation of
each new species would be explained. The more I thought over it the more I became
convinced that I had at length found the long-sought-for law of nature that solved the
problem of origin of species. For the next hour I thought over the deficiencies in the
theories of Lamarck and of the author of the "Vestiges", and I saw that my new
theory supplemented these views and obviated every important difficulty. I waited
anxiously for the termination of my fit so that I might at once make notes for a paper on
the subject. The same evening I did this pretty fully, and on the two succeeding evenings
wrote it out carefully in order to send it to Darwin by the next post, which would leave
in a day or two.
47
I wrote a letter to him in which I said that I hoped the idea would be as new to him as
it was to me, and that it would supply the missing factor to explain the origin of
species. I asked him if he thought it sufficiently important to show it to Sir Charles
Lyell, who had thought so highly of my former paper.
... I was, of course, very much surprised to find that the same idea had occurred to
Darwin, and that he had already nearly completed a large work fully developing it.
A real gent.
Three years later (and sixty-four years after the event) Wallace took the trouble to
reread the sixth edition of Malthus' essay and to supply the Linnean Society with his
recollection of the chapters which had, as he recalled, impressed him most. It was not the
passages on natural law or the strictures on improvability and the hope from the exercise
of "moral restraint" of the second volume but the cumulative effect of chapters
three to twelve, especially three to eight, of volume one. These contain 150 pages of
excruciatingly detailed travelers' accounts and histories of the checks on the population
of primitive societies, parts of the world outside Europe and Scandinavia, and ancient
Greece and Rome. It is a catalogue of details of bestial life, sickness, weakness, poor
food, lack of ability to care for young, scant resources, famine, infanticide, war,
massacre, plunder, slavery, cold, hunger, disease, epidemics, plague, and abortion.
Wallace goes on to list passages which particularly struck him and concludes:
I then saw that war, plunder and massacres among men were represented by the attacks of
carnivore on herbivore, and of the stronger upon the weaker among animals. Famine,
droughts, floods and winter's storms would have an even greater effect on animals than on
men; while as the former possessed powers of increase from twice to a thousand-fold
greater than the latter, the ever-present annual destruction must also be many times
greater..... Then there flashed upon me . . .
and so on, including a ringing debt of gratitude to Lyell's "Immortal Principles
of Geology" which impressed him even more deeply. Wallace had been working as a
naturalist and pondering the problem of the origin of species for thirteen years; he had
published a paper on the theory sans mechanism three years earlier. As
48
a naturalist he needed no more facts. He needed a new perspective, and an ethnology
steeped in struggle provided it to his fitful mind.
Wallace's later views can also serve to introduce the negative side of Malthus'
influence in biological and social theory. While his interest in man and the origin of
races had led to his codiscovery of the mechanism of natural selection, Wallace's belief
in the perfectibility of man led him to turn away from the all-sufficiency of the survival
of the fittest. He came to make exceptions about man's brain, and his aesthetic and moral
faculties and to turn increasingly to the anticipation of human needs by some force
transcending nature. Having rejected the principle of utility as an adequate explanation
of human evolution, it is not surprising that he went further and rejected its Malthusian
source. He wrote to Darwin in 1881 that Henry George's Progress and Poverty had
convinced him that Malthus' law did not apply at all to human evolution. George argued
that nature could not be blamed for man's failure to distribute her bounty fairly.
Voluntarist cooperation and reform replaced struggle as the mechanism for social change.
Wallace came to agree with George that Malthus' theory has no bearing "whatever on
the vast social and political questions which have been supported by reference to
it." He saw Progress and Poverty as "making an advance in political and
social science equal to that made by Adam Smith a century ago." George had been
called "arguably the most potent socialist influence in his generation." By the
time he wrote The Wonderful Century in 1898, Wallace's socialist hopes for the
future of society led him to reject social struggle completely, and to embrace a belief in
inevitable progress with no mechanism specified. When, near the end of his life, Wallace
reconsidered the question "Is Nature cruel?" and discussed the purpose and
limitations of pain, he provided a neat way of reconciling Malthusian struggle in the
animal world with a non-Malthusian view of human progress. His solution was almost
Cartesian in its simplicity. Animals felt much less pain than men - almost none at all.
Indeed, uncivilized races felt less than civilized ones.
VII
Before venturing further into the relations between Malthus, evolution, and socialism,
I want to turn to the last of the three
49
most eminent evolutionists. While Wallace drew away from Malthus and the
all-sufficiency of the mechanism for human evolution suggested by "the survival of
the fittest" (as his interest in social issues developed), Herbert Spencer provides
the penultimate case which I wish to consider. His main interest was always man and
society. According to John Burrow's Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social
Theory, Spencer, like Darwin and Wallace, drew his mechanism of evolution from
Malthus' population theory. Burrow is mistaken but in an interesting way. In 1851 Spencer
published his first book, a defense of laissez-faire social theory in opposition to the
manipulations of the Benthamites. Social Statics contained views (derived in part
from phrenology) which served as the basis of his later evolutionary thinking. In 1852 he
wrote an essay entitled "The Development Hypothesis" in which he advocated
evolution but provided no detailed discussion of the mechanism by which evolution
occurred. The main thesis of his brief argument was that "continual modifications due
to change of circumstances" was much more plausible than special creation. In the
same year he published an essay entitled "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the
General Law of Animal Fertility." The natural inference is that belief in evolution
combined with the population theory and applied to animal fertility, produced the same
result as it had in the theories of Darwin and Wallace. On the contrary, there was no such
synthesis in Spencer's theory. The Malthusian law is not mentioned until a few pages
before the end, where pressure on population is called the proximate cause of progress.
The principle of natural selection is also mentioned but not developed or extended beyond
human society.
After pointing out these passages in retrospect, Spencer remarks in his autiobiography:
It seems strange that, having long entertained a belief in the development of species
through the operation of natural causes, I should have failed to see that the truth
indicated in the above-quoted passages, must hold, not of mankind only, but of all
animals; and must everywhere be working changes among them....... Yet I completely
overlooked this obvious corollary - was blind that here was a universally-operative factor
in the development of species.
The reasons which he gives for this oversight are ignorance of the phenomena of
variation and his belief in the inheritance of
50
acquired characteristics. Lyell had attempted to refute Lamarck's theory (which
included "use-inheritance") in the Principles of Geology, and this
refutation was almost universally accepted. With characteristic perversity, Spencer
rejected Lyell's refutation and became a convinced Lamarckian. The main feature of
Spencer's explanation was not population pressure but Progress itself. Spencer agreed with
Lamarck that nature had an inherent progressive tendency. He garbled the Lamarckian theory
and considered the mechanism of this progress to be the inheritance of learned
modifications. Indeed, his next work, begun almost immediately, was on psychology.
Inspired by G. H. Lewes' Biographical History of Philosophy and informed by
a copy of J. S. Mill's Logic which George Eliot gave him, Spencer abandoned the
psychological theory of phrenology and became an associationist. Spencer's Principles
of Psychology, published in 1855, contained a consistent evolutionary
interpretation of all learning and an extension of associationism from the tabula rasa of
the individual to that of the race. Habits are inherited as built-in dispositions in the
nervous system.
In the introduction, in his collected Essays, to an essay written two years
later and entitled "Progress: Its Law and Cause" Spencer says, "Though the
idea and illustrations contained in this essay were eventually incorporated in First
Principles, yet I think it well here to reproduce it as exhibiting the form
under which the General Doctrine of Evolution made its first appearance." The works
under review in the original essay in the Westminster Review were von Humboldt's Cosmos, the ninth edition of Lyell's Principles of Geology, and the fourth
edition of William Carpenter's Principles of Comparative Physiology. Thus,
Spencer's topics are the universe, the earth, and life - typical Spencerian subject
matter. He does not ignore struggle, but he certainly subordinates it to his own
explanatory factor: Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics, the concept of
physiological division of labor, and that mysterious process which seems to be the key to
all change - the transformation "from homogeneity to heterogeneity." Within this
framework the idea of struggle is mentioned with no special emphasis. For example, he
says, "The authority of the strongest makes itself felt among a body of savages as in
a herd of animals, or a posse of schoolboys." He had made similar statements in Social
Statics. This is not related to Malthusianism or described as a
51
force for change in its own right but is an example of the transformation from
homogeneity to heterogeneity, resulting in division of labor in society. He says at an
earlier stage that the law of organic progress is the law of all progress - in the
development of the earth, life, society, government, manufacture, commerce, language,
literature, science, art. "From the earliest traceable cosmical changes down to the
latest results of civilization, we shall find that the transformation of the homogenous
into the heterogenous, is that in which Progress essentially consists." His litany is
"Progress is not an accident, not a thing within human control, but a beneficent
necessity."
In 1886 Spencer pointed out that although he had been heavily criticized for continuing
to believe in the inheritance of acquired characteristics, Wallace had abandoned the
survival of the fittest as a mechanism for human evolution, and in his later writings
Darwin was allowing an increasingly greater role for mechanisms other than natural
selection in the evolution of animals. Indeed, the closer he got to mind and society, the
more Darwin employed use-inheritance. Spencer says in the preface to a separately
published edition of 1887 that the reason he had clung so tenaciously to the inheritance
of acquired characteristics in biological theory was because it had such important
implications for psychology, ethics, and sociology. These implications led him to write
the essay, which was entitled "The Factors of Organic Evolution." He granted
that the Malthuslan factor might operate in mental phenomena of simpler kinds, but
"use and disuse" was the chief factor in the development of man and society.
Unless this were so, he pointed out, we could not be assured that society would progress en
masse as quickly as it is seen to be doing. Progress on the Malthusian model was too
indirect and too slow. Far from being an application of Malthus, the sanguine belief in
inexorable evolutionary progress which was characteristic of Spencer was more reminiscent
of the doctrines which prompted Malthus to write the polemical first edition of his Essay
on the Principle of Population. Spencer's laissez-faire optimism is far closer to
Rousseau, Condorcet, and Godwin than to Malthus. True, Spencer had a place for struggle,
but it basked in the light of Progress. This must be the real source of nature's energy.
Thus, Spencer's evolutionary theory provides a negative case: it was fundamentally
anti-Malthusian. Although he considered the Malthusian mechanism
52
in the same period when he was working out his evolutionary theory, he passed it by,
for it did not provide a sufficient guarantee of social progress, and he had turned to
biology in search of that certainty.
VIII
There are a number of ways one could develop this progression involving the uses to
which Malthus was put, the most obvious being to attempt a British version of Hofstadter's Social Darwinism in American Thought. Malthus, Darwin, and Spencer provided
some rationalizations for British imperialism as well as for the American robber barons.
But a tidier solution is to recall the Marxist view of Malthus and of the mechanism of
evolution. As noted in Chapter 1, when Marx first read Darwin's Origin of Species in
1860, he wrote to Engels that "although it is developed in the crude English style,
this is the book which contains the basis in natural history for our view."
For all their enthusiasm over Darwin's naturalistic interpretation of man, Marx and
Engels found themselves embarrassed by Darwins avowed debt to 'Malthus' population theory,
since they had denounced the latter as a libel against the human race and Malthus as a
plagiarist, a bought advocate, a shameless sycophant of the ruling classes who had
well-earned the hatred of the English working class. In the Dialectics of Nature, Engels
wrote that "Darwin did not know what a bitter satire he wrote on mankind and
especially on his countrymen, when he showed that free competition, the struggle for
existence, which the economists celebrate as the highest historical achievement, is the
normal state of the animal kingdom."
Marx and Engels were attempting to prize Darwin and Malthus apart. This has remained
the Marxist line on Malthus, as Ronald Meek's edition of Marx and Engels on Malthus shows.
An article in the Modem Quarterly illustrates the position: Fyfe argues that Marx
exposed Malthus as a bourgeois fraud and that Malthusian theories "serve to disguise
the fact that human suffering is due to the defects of a political system, by seeking to
explain it as due to the operation of natural phenomena." The value of neo-Malthusian
theories to the capitalist and imperialist is "to deflect attention from the real
causes of desperately low living standards by setting up pseudo-scientific 'laws."'
Why do Marxists oppose Malthus'
53
theory? For the same reason that earlier meliorists had done so: it limits human
self-improvement and stresses struggle as an almost inescapable impediment to
progress rather than as a mechanism for inevitable progressive change. Fyfe argues that in
the USSR "within our lifetimes the unlimited possibilities of man's control over his
environment, once an assertion of a reasoned belief, a prediction, are being realized in
actuality."
Twentieth-century expressions of the intimate fusion of social and evolutionary theory
which characterized the nineteenth-century debate were not confined to the pages of the Modern
Quarterly. Indeed there was a smooth transition to very recent debates on the laws of
biological inheritance. (It would be misleading to suggest that there are many simple
recent examples in biology which support my thesis as easily as the following.) G. H.
Lewes and Herbert Spencer were the inspiration of I. P. Pavlov's classical research on
conditioned reflexes, and it is only very recently that the Darwinian version of
evolution, including the Watson-Crick solution of the genetic code, could be taught, and
the relevant scientific subjects could be studied, in the Soviet Union. The belief in
changing animal (and human) nature by the "Lamarckian" inheritance of acquired
characteristics was an orthodoxy. A statement by the Presidium of the USSR Academy of
Sciences claimed in 1948 that the Russian version of "Lamarckianism" - the
Lysenko-Michurin theory of inheritance - was the only acceptable one, "because it is
based on dialectical materialism and on the revolutionary principle of changing nature for
the benefit of the people." Ten years later, as Soviet geneticists began an orderly
retreat from this position, a reviewer of the waning orthodoxy pointed out that the
proponents of Michurinism "assert that [the] gene theory of heredity opposed to it is
a pseudo-scientific, idealistic conception of development associated with the reactionary
ideology of the imperialistic bourgeoisie." The disagreement between
Lysenko-Michurinist believers in inheritance of acquired characteristics and the
neo-Darwinian geneticists was "not the conflict of two points of view in a single
system; it is a class struggle between two systems, two ideologies." The ideology
"of bourgeois scientists makes it utterly impossible for them to discover objective
laws of nature, and they are, so to speak, forced consciously or unconsciously to distort
these laws in accordance with the class interests of the bourgeoisie, to create a
'pseudo-scientific reactionary' genetics - the gene theory of heredity." This
54
is a blatant example of the dominance of political ideology over well-attested
scientific findings in the twentieth century, but it was also an international scandal.
When it became clear that Watson and Crick were likely to win the Nobel Prize for their
allegedly pseudoscientific reactionary findings, modern genetics was finally allowed to
begin developing in the Soviet Union. Nevertheless, it is not unlikely that a future
historian will find that the neat division between biological and social science which
most current scientists believe to have been established is less absolute than it now
appears.
IX
I have tried to show how five aspects of Malthus' Essay on the Principle of
Population were developed by different by figures in the debate on "man's place
in nature" in the nineteenth century. First, his on theodicy was muted by Paley, who
(as the eighth edition of the Britannica put it in 1859) absorbed struggle
in a "higher illumination than Reason alone affords us." Second, the palliative
of "moral restraint" which was added to the second edition of Malthus' Essay became
a scourge for the punishment of the sinful in the hands of Thomas Chalmers. Both Paley and
Chalmers had interests in the established order of society and of nature. Third, Darwin
tells us that he seized on the image of nature as at war and used Malthus' view of natural
law as applied to man as his authority for extending the principle of selection from the
breeders' wishes to nature, that is, from artificial to natural selection. Once
"moral restraint" was discounted, the law of struggle became the source of the
marvelous adaptations of the natural theologians. Fourth, Wallace was impressed by the
actual phenomena of human suffering in the environment, and having grasped this with
respect to man, he applied it analogously to all of nature. Wallace also serves as a
transitional figure for the fifth reading of Malthus. Progress became a watchword for his
later writings on man and society. As this occurred, Malthus was progressively abandoned.
Spencer's preoccupations with social progress were such that Malthus never found a place
in his evolutionary theory, since Malthus had stressed the impediments to Godwin's and
Condorcet's belief in indefinite progress. These impediments were also anathema to the
social philosophy of Marx and Engels, who wanted to
55
embrace Darwin while rejecting Malthus. Similarly, and perfectly appropriately, their
Russian interpreters embraced the theory of learning and its extension to the race which
was furthest from the Malthusian doctrine. They, like Spencer, wanted evolution only as a
scientific guarantee for indefinite social progress.
It is hoped that this argument may have provided some evidence for the theses that
influences in the history of science can be exploited as variously as in political and
social history and that claims for progressive separation of "objective" natural
science and woolly social science can find no support in the history of evolutionary
theory. The integration of the history of science with other aspects of history is now
established in seventeenth-century studies. It would appear that historians of the
nineteenth century could well apply this approach to their period with similar interesting
results.
|
|