Darwin's Metaphor:
Nature's Place in Victorian Culture
by
[ Introduction | Preface |
Chapter: 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | 6 | Notes | Bibliography | Index ]
CHAPTER V
NATURAL THEOLOGY, VICTORIAN PERIODICALS, AND THE FRAGMENTATION OF
A COMMON CONTEXT
I
This chapter presents a hypothesis about the nature of a common intellectual context in
the Victorian periodical literature, the role of natural theology in that milieu, and what
happened when the relatively integrated common culture of issues and publications broke
up. I want to ruminate some of the problems which arise when one tries to write
convincingly about such large-scale relationships in history.
My general line of research is concerned with the problem of doing science about
people. My first approach to the problem was to investigate theories of the relationship
between mind and brain, centered on attempts to localize functions in the brain. As this
work developed I became increasingly interested in the intellectual context within which
various concepts of the functions of the brain were conceived. This led away from
relatively internalist preoccupation with the histories of psychology, psychiatry,
neurology, and neurophysiology to the development of evolutionary theory in Britain. This,
in turn, led to a much wider inquiry into the nineteenth-century debate on man's place in
nature. When I began to look for response to developments in psychology and the study of
the nervous system in the debate, I found very little. Instead, the monographs,
periodicals, and lives and letters were much more concerned with geology, natural
theology, Malthusianism, that is, with the role of nonmaterial causes in nature and with
the relationships among God, man, and nature. Thus, instead of detailed debates on
psychology and brain physiology, there was a much more general debate on the uniformity of
nature,
127
miracles, free will, and the status of man in nature. Psychology played a much deeper
role, but the most accessible and explicit arenas for discussing man's place in nature
were not, it turned out, the sciences which seemed to me to be the most relevant from my
vantage point inside current disciplinary boundaries. Instead, geological and biological
theory attracted the attention of the main participants in the debate.
However, two features of the debate soon became very clear. First, although the
particular sciences of psychology and neurophysiology (as we now define them) were not
explicitly at the center of controversy, it was almost impossible to make any demarcations
between disciplines over a wide range of subjects as twentieth-century scholars would
define them. Second, at least for the first five or six decades of the century, natural
theology provided the general context for the debate. That is, new and controverted
scientific findings and theories were taken up in the general culture as bearing on the
demonstration of the existence and attributes of God as drawn from the book of nature (as
distinct from revelation). In the course of the period, the structure of the debate
changed progressively from a relatively undifferentiated one in which specialist studies
were seen as parts of that very general theistic context in the early decades of the
century, to one in which disciplines were increasingly demarcated, and the relationship
between science and theology became - at least at one level - one of conflict. At another
level that relationship became one of identifying the new claims for the laws of nature
with God's governance of the universe at a level of abstraction that was virtually
meaningless.
If I am right about these very general features of the debate, the problem becomes one
of relating three issues: (1) the common intellectual context, (2) natural
theology, and (3) the body of writings in which the debate occurred. In attempting to
understand the development of the debate I have found myself employing a number of related
hypotheses:
1. There was a common intellectual context (one could put that anachronistically as
"a rich interdisciplinary culture") in the early decades of the nineteenth
century in Britain, and this was reflected in the periodical literature, monographs, lives
and letters, and in a wide range of other writings.
2. There was a relatively homogeneous and satisfactory natural
128
theology, best reflected in William Paley's classic Natural Theology (1802) and innumerable works reflecting the same point of view. These works were reviewed
enthusiastically and at length in the periodical literature in the first four decades of
the century. The Bridgewater Treatises (1833-6) were an attempt to codify this
tradition in the light of detailed findings in the several sciences, but they reflect the
fact that an attempt to spell out the Paleyan point of view in detail led to difficulties
which natural theology could not overcome without considerably modifying its view of the
relationships among God, man, and nature.
3. The impact of scientific findings progressively altered this coherent natural
theology until it was virtually devoid of content as a discipline in its own right.
4. The common intellectual context came to pieces in the 1870s and 1880s, and this
fragmentation w was reflected in the development of specialist societies and periodicals,
increasing professionalization, and the growth of general periodicals of a markedly lower
intellectual standard.
It is at this point that my troubles begin. It would be folly to argue that the impact
of science on natural theology provides an adequate cause for the alleged breakup
of the (putative) common intellectual culture of the intelligentsia. Stated baldly, the
hypothesis only replaces internalist history of science with internalist intellectual
history and offers a monocausal explanation. Surely this is simplistic in the extreme. For
example, if one uses circulation figures and the growth of new periodicals with lower
intellectual standards as a partial index, what weight should one attach to such factors
as the emergence of serialized novels, the growth of literacy, the appeal of middle-brow
periodicals to former readers of the heavier Edinburgh Review and Quarterly Review? A
more candid way of putting the problem is that I have come up against the limits of the
legitimate explanatory power of the history of ideas, no matter how widely one casts the
net into bodies of literature and their reception. The questions I have raised cry out for
consideration from the point of view of social, political, and economic historical
research. These are perspectives which historians of science have yet to adopt in a
serious and sustained way on most topics and certainly with respect to Victorian science.
In order to carry my own research further I now realize that I must embark
129
on a process of self-education for which there has been no preparation in eleven years
as a student (and five as a teacher) of philosophy, science, medicine, and history and
philosophy of science - all of which were taught without reference to the historical
forces at work in the socioeconomic order.
There is, of course, a complementary omission. Social, political, and economic
historians have been no less remiss, since they have failed to take seriously the
structure and texture of the intellectual debates which fundamentally altered the
perception of "man's place in nature" and the role of science and technology in
the productive, social, and intellectual spheres. So I am not tempted to renounce
intellectual history and plunge, amnesic, into other specialist studies in history. I hope
that students of the period will eventually be able to bring these approaches together as
aspects of a totality, perhaps to reintegrate the fragments whose origins I am considering
here.
Short of that long-range ambition, I should like to gather together the work I have
done so far and put forward some evidence in support of the working hypothesis that the
impact of science on natural theology was a factor, one which I believe was
significant. That is, I wish to draw attention to a concomitant variation for the present,
without in any way wanting to beg the question of what factors would add up to a
satisfying causal account.
The remainder of the chapter is in five parts: (1) historiographic issues in
connection with my approach to the problems mentioned above, with some remarks on the
discipline of "Victorian Studies"; (2 and 3) two case studies in the changing
interpretation of natural theology; (4) a case study, which I find symptomatic, of the
attempt to retain a common intellectual context; and (5) some manifestations of the
fragmentation of that common context, resulting in disciplinary and topic boundaries
recognizable to our own demarcations.
II
First, some methodological problems involved in the definition of my domain and the
problem of relating its constituent parts. My research on the debate on man's place in
nature is related to at least eight sources of evidence in historical scholarship (which
can be indicated by books which I have found more or less useful):
130
1. The use of literature to illuminate the history of ideas and assumptions in the
period;
2. The history of scientific ideas, particularly in geology and biology;
3. The history of religion and theology;
4. The history of philosophy;
5. The history of popular opinion and related issues;
6. Works attempting to build bridges between the history of scientific and philosophic
ideas on the one hand and the history of political and social ideas on the other (these
approaches are closest to my own current understanding);
7. General political and historical context;
8. The history of ideas in psychology, study of the nervous system, psychiatry and
medicine, developments which were occurring in the period, no matter how small a place
they found in the nonspecialist Victorian periodicals.
Of course, this list could be extended indefinitely to embrace specialist studies in
the histories of behavioral and social sciences on the one hand and the history of the
periodical press on the other, but the purpose of making a list will have been served if
it is obvious that the problem is that these are relatively isolated bodies of research,
with occasional borrowings of the loosest generalizations from related disciplines. These
are usually added on as rather desperate gestures in the direction of fields whose
literature one simply cannot master.
An obvious book to use for this purpose is Gillispie's seminal work, Genesis and
Geology: The Impact of Scientific Discoveries upon Religious Beliefs in the Decades
before Darwin. In doing so, a nonspecialist would be very likely to remain unaware
that Gillispie has a very rudimentary grasp of the fine texture of the geological debate
on which so much hung in the period 1820-50. This is not a trivial point, since it turns
out that the detailed proceedings of the Geological Society appeared in the quarterlies
throughout this period, and every important geological work was reviewed in the major
intellectual periodicals throughout the century. Geology was central to the debate on the
relationship between God and nature, the status of the Bible, and man's place in nature.
Thus, although Gillispie may not have exposed himself to these documents, the Victorian
intelligentsia did.
131
Is there any way out of this mess short of reading and sifting everything or collecting
short essays from a wide variety of specialists, e.g., Ideas and Beliefs of the
Victorians? In my opinion, Houghton, in The Victorian Frame of Mind, has shown
us that the attempt to do everything need not be disastrous, while his bibliographical
work since completing that book makes it a great deal more orderly, if no less daunting,
process.
The approach which I have in mind is to focus on a rather loosely defined issue and to
rely heavily on the Victorian periodicals, especially the quarterlies. Of course, as
Ellegard has shown (without intending to) in his ambitious study of the reception of
Darwin's theory of evolution in the British periodical press, 1859-72, this approach
brings its own risks. Foremost among these is the likelihood that one will have so many
documents and such a vast network of related issues that the result is an impressively
annotated bibliography, whereas one had set out to illuminate the ideas and assumptions of
the period by a different method. Ellegard encountered these difficulties in dealing with
two books - Origin of Species and Descent of Man - and Millhauser did an even less
satisfactory job on the reception of Chambers' Vestiges of Creation. With these
examples before us, it really does seem absurdly ambitious to attempt to provide an
interpretation of the debate within which these works and the controversies surrounding
them played a very significant but (if one is considering the bulk of the literature)
still relatively small part.
The way I have attempted to get around this difficulty is to be at once more and less
ambitious. That is, one resigns oneself to diminishing the number of essays and reviews
which are to be considered with respect to a given work and at the same time to increasing
the number of works considered. I would argue that this does not lead to an inevitable
reduction of sense of nuance and depth. Rather, it points to the mindlessness of being
excessively inclusive. Thus, this method requires a casualty at an early stage, i.e., the
social history of ideas conceived as the study of low-brow popular opinion. There is some
evidence that this sacrifice is not a crippling one; scholars who have studied certain
aspects of the popular reactions are very reassuring. For example, Susan Budd read through
the biographies of 150 members of the Secularist movement and found that ideas from
geology, evolution, and scientific historiography were, on the available evidence,
influential
132
in only three cases of loss of religious faith. Tom Paine and the comparison of the
Bible with the institutions of church and society were much more important. Similarly,
Jenifer Hart and Edward Norman, respectively, have looked at the sermons of country
parsons and the debates among the ecclesiastical Lords and assure me that insofar as
scientific ideas were mentioned, this occurred at a level of crude, clichéd
unsophistication which would not repay detailed study. Finally, when Millhauser studied
the writings of the Scriptural Geologists in the early decades of the century, he
concluded that they did not illuminate the issues in the geological debate on miracles
versus the uniformity of nature which were significant in the wider controversy on the
impact of scientific ideas on the conception of nature and man's place in it.
I am not suggesting that there is nothing to be learned from the history of popular
opinions. On the contrary, I would do much to encourage detailed studies of popular
phrenology, the ideology of the Mechanics' Institutes, and the activities of provincial
literary and philosophical societies. I only want to argue that it is legitimate to
demarcate this sort of activity from the study of the views of the intelligentsia. Thus, I
have chosen to confine my attention to certain major works and the debates surrounding
them in the more sophisticated periodicals and intellectual circles. The hard core of
works which I consider central to the issue of man's place in nature and which I have been
investigating are the writings of Malthus, Paley, William Buckland, George Combe, Lyell,
the authors of the Bridgewater Treatises (some more than others), Adam Sedgwick,
William Whewell, Baden Powell, Robert Chambers, Darwin, Spencer, Wallace, Alexander Bain,
Huxley, Tylor, Lubbock, and Tyndall.
Once one has made this decision and eliminated the certainty of being inundated by
every conceivable opinion, it becomes impossible to retain certain other very convenient
demarcations - those of subject and of specialized interests. The existence of a
considerable number of scholars who call their discipline "Victorian Studies"
implies all that I am about to say, but I feel that we are all very slow to appreciate the
intellectual consequences of this: we are dealing with a common context of issues which
diminishes the importance of divisions between science and arts, economic and political
and biological theory, poetry and geology, psychology and theology, education and the
novel - indeed, any combination of twentieth-century academic divisions which we care to
name.
133
Of course, this situation drops us back into the morass which we attempted to avoid by
setting out to study the views of the intelligentsia on scientific topics. However,
certain aspects of Victorian Studies are relatively advanced; indeed, the field is
dominated by students of literature, with social and political historians running second.
This situation may make it possible to attempt to assess the role of scientific ideas in a
body of literature which is already relatively well studied from other points of view.
It is acknowledged on all sides that scientific developments were at the center of
Victorian intellectual life, but it remains the case that eminent scholars on the period,
e.g., Knoepflmacher, Hillis-Miller, Ward, Haight, and Houghton give little evidence of
having read, e.g., Lyell, Chambers, and Darwin, even though their works are utterly
dependent on the reactions to these and related works which the Victorians about whom they
write did read. To put this point even more contentiously, I doubt that Kitchel,
Everett, or Haight have read the works of Gall, Spurzheim, Combe, Bray, and Spencer on
phrenology and psychology, but the subjects of their students - George Eliot and George
Lewes - took these works seriously enough to read them aloud to each other by the fire,
and they included some of the authors among their most intimate friends. It is said that
George Eliot even had her head shaved in order to obtain a more precise
phrenological delineation. The activities of George Eliot and George Lewes perfectly
exemplify the common context to which I refer. All of the following interests - and more -
were intimately intermingled in their lives and works: drama, theater, literature,
philosophy, Positivism, zoology, psychology, the novel, the study of the nervous system,
poetry, political journalism, and biblical criticism. Similarly, the study of the impact
of science requires a much fuller appreciation of the congeries of ideas which is evoked
by the terms "empiricism, associationism," "Utilitarianism,"
"Philosophical Radicalism," and "Positivism." When one speaks of the
impact of science on the intellectual culture of the period and sets out to examine the
journals which provided a platform for scientific naturalism (e.g., the Westminster
Review, the Leader, the Fortnightly Review, and the Nineteenth Century) it is
important to look much further into the relevant scientific and philosophical works. These
issues fail to figure prominently in the standard histories of the period. When they are
discussed, they appear much more in the form of political programs than as manifestations
of a philosophy of nature which
134
gave rise to the political, social, and aesthetic movements which form the subjects of
so many works in "Victorian Studies." Instead of burrowing deeper into the
minutiae of critical receptions of Victorian novels, it might be worthwhile to pay closer
attention to the works and the movements which evoked so much Victorian writing.
In attempting to do this, it seems to me that we could do worse than to center our
studies in the Victorian periodicals and the members of the intellectual milieux who edited and wrote for them. It turns out that this network of journals, authors, and
friends includes everyone whose opinion seems relevant. Thanks to Professor Houghton's Wellesley
Index we can now begin to identify the authors of the essays and reviews in the major
periodicals. As a result of an immense labor, we have a simple catalogue of tables of
contents and authors which allows us to illuminate the issues from a wide variety of
perspectives. This activity was formerly almost impossible because of the practice of
anonymous reviewing. The first volume of the Wellesley Index identifies the authors
of 97 percent of the articles in eight of the major reviews, and the subsequent volumes
attempt to do the same for a further thirty-two periodicals. The contents of the main
reviews and the activities of their (now identified) contributors confirm one's belief in
the existence of a common intellectual context which poured out controversy at an
astonishing rate and a most surprising level of sophistication. Neither the periodicals
nor their regular contributors made significant distinctions among science, literature,
philosophy, theology, political economy, etc. Thus, I heartily agree with Brown, who
argues that "the history of the English mind and English public opinion cannot be
written without careful attention to the influence and history of periodical
literature."
There was no dearth of organs for discussing these issues. Between 1800 and 1900 more
than 1,000 new magazines of various kinds were started in London, and in the year in which On the Origin of Species appeared, 115 new periodicals were begun in
Britain. What were they reviewing? In the period in which I believe that natural theology
was playing an important integrative function in the intellectual culture, theological
works were pouring out at a great rate. Of the roughly 45,000 books published in England
between 1816 and 1851, well over 10,000 were religious, far out-
135
distancing the next largest category - history and geography -with 4,900, and fiction
with 3,500. There was also an immense circulation of religious periodicals and tracts.
III
Turning now to the relationship between the periodicals, the common context, and
natural theology, I can only indicate a conclusion from detailed reading of many of the
periodicals and cite some examples which indicate the general development as I see it. In
the period from about 1800 to about 1880, the role of theology seems to change from that
of providing the context for the debate to that of acting as one point of view in a
conflict. In the early debate the effort is to retain harmony between science and
theology; after about 1850 increasing efforts are made to separate them or to make
the claims of theology so abstract that they cannot come into conflict with the
discoveries of science.
I would now like to move from these general hypotheses to a particular case. Much of
the debate on man's place in nature can be interpreted in terms of the principle of the
continuity or uniformity of nature. As this conception was applied to successively larger
domains, the role of non-material causes was increasingly diminished - miracles,
geological catastrophes, special creation of species, special vital laws in biology, as
well as a separate realm of mind, were challenged by scientific developments in the middle
two quarters of the century. Of course, there was vehement opposition to each of these
moves, and they were hotly debated in the quarterlies, in monographs, in newspapers, in
the pulpit, the universities, literary and philosophical societies, Mechanics' Institutes,
letters, and drawing rooms. To concentrate on the views of the intelligentsia, the
opponents of uniformitarian ideas in geology and biology who were most respected were (in
increasing order of sophistication) William Buckland, Adam Sedgwick, and William Whewell.
Their opponents were (with variations on particular issues) Lyell, Chambers, Spencer,
Huxley, and Darwin, among others, but the most sophisticated philosopher of the principle
of uniformity was Baden Powell.
John Burrow has observed that "Much in nineteenth-century thought can be
interpreted on the assumption that the Uniformity of Nature had acquired for many
intellectuals a logical status and
136
a numinous aura which made it a substitute for the idea of God." In his
recollections on the intellectual atmosphere at Oxford in the period 1856-9, John Morley
wrote, "The forces of miracle and myth and intervening Will in the interpretation of
the world began to give way before the reign of law." Morley was later the editor of
the Fortnightly Review. Its first editor, G. H. Lewes, wrote in 1866 that science
also offered "a cure for souls. . . . Formerly the best indication of a nation's
progress was in its religious conceptions. Now the surest indication is in its scientific
conceptions." In its first ten years the Fortnightly contained an article on
the relations between science and theology in almost every issue. In the first number,
George Eliot set the tone by pointing to "the gradual reduction of all phenomena
within the sphere of established law, which carries as a consequence the rejection of the
miraculous . . ." These views, along with those of Spencer, Huxley, and Tyndall,
represent the advance of the positivist, phenomenalist, nominalist group. That is, they
represent the impact of science. My object here is to lend plausibility to the hypotheses
(1) that as theology moved toward the identification of God with the uniformity of
nature (under pressure from science), there came to be little to choose between the devout
and the agnostic, and (2) that theology ceased to serve the unifying function which it had
in the early decades of the century.
The case studies which I have chosen are not concerned with the views of those who come
under the heading of "the impact of science." Rather, I should like to draw
attention to the changing views of polymath theologians who were attempting to interpret
the challenge from science. Since the writings of William Whewell extend over the crucial
period 1830-60 and beyond, it will help to illustrate my view of the development of
natural theology if we consider his writings in some detail and briefly contrast his views
with those of Baden Powell, who argued for a very different view of the relations among
God, man, and nature.
William Whewell was the most articulate and sophisticated interpreter of the
providential view which was associated with the belief that God intervened in the course
of nature with catastrophic alterations of its geology and its complement of species. He
was also very influential in the community of scholars which embraced science, philosophy,
and theology as an integrated discipline and which was beginning to show signs of strain.
Indeed, his life and work provide an excellent, if extreme, example of the
137
common intellectual context which was characteristic of the period. He wrote sixty-four
scientific papers, in addition to books .and shorter works which are listed in five
columns in the Dictionary of National Biography. He wrote on mechanics,
dynamics, electricity, theory of the tides (his most original scientific work),
mathematics, geology, architecture, theology, education, poetry, logic, ind political
economy. He also wrote poetry and translated classical and German poetry and Plato. When
he wrote on the question of life on other worlds an unkind epigrammatist claimed
that he wrote it to prove that "through all infinity there was nothing so great as
the Master of Trinity." In his spare time from his writing, Whewell held posts as
Tutor, then Master, of Trinity, was :twice Vice-Chancellor, and successively held chairs
in Mineralogy and Moral Philosophy at Cambridge. He was also largely responsible for the
introduction of both the Moral Science and the Natural Science Triposes in Cambridge
(1848). He was a founder member of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, Fellow and
President (1837) of the Geological Society and successively Secretary (1833),
Vice-President (1835), and President (1841) of the British Association. He twice essayed
on the whole field of science - first in his Bridgewater Treatise (1833, the most
popular of the series: it went through ten editions by 1864) and in his five-volume
(continually revised) History and Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (1837-40,
etc.). Lyell once said that he regretted that Whewell had not concentrated his energies as
a specialist in one science but later decided that he was most effective as an eminent
"universalist." A less kind observer commented that "Science is his forte,
omniscience his foible."
It is worth recalling that Whewell's position on the question of miracles in geology
and biology was consistent with his general philosophical position, according to which the
operations of nature required the constant sustenance and occasional direct intervention
of the Deity: all force is will force and leads ultimately to God's efforts. This position
on the philosophy of nature was intimately related to his views on the philosophy of
scientific discovery, which led to a direct and protracted conflict between him and J. S.
Mill, in which Mill argued that science investigated regularities in nature and could not
provide ultimate explanations. Mill's empiricism is much closer to the positions of the
Young Turks of scientific positivism - Huxley and Tyndall - than Whewell's views, which
can be characterized as deeply antinaturalist and
138
even idealist. As a philosopher, Whewell set out to introduce an anti-Lockean
philosophy to Cambridge. His views were influenced by Kant and can be described as
transcendental and intuitionist.
Whewell played a prominent part in the debates on geology and evolution and their
relationship with theology, and his writings in the periodicals, his own works, and his
letters shed light on the reception of Lyell, Chambers, and Darwin. He reviewed the first
volume of Lyell's Principles of Geology in the British Critic and the second
volume in the Quarterly. In the former he pointed out that Lyell's principle of
uniformity as applied to the history of the earth had implications for the question of the
origin of species. If Lyell was going to "give even a theoretical consistency to his
system, it will be requisite, that Mr. Lyell should supply us with some explanation by
which we pass from a world filled with one group of species to one which contained
different species." Since Lyell could not supply such an explanation, Whewell
confidently concluded that it was "undeniable that we see in the transition from an
earth peopled by one set of animals, to the same earth swarming with entirely new forms of
organic life, a distinct manifestation of creative power, transcending the operation of
known laws of nature: and, it appears to us, that geology has thus lighted a new lamp
along the path to natural theology."
Later, in his History and Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, Whewell set out
to ajudicate the debate between uniformitarians and catastrophists in geology and the
bearings of these positions on the origin of species. (Indeed, it was Whewell who dubbed
the respective positions "uniformitarian" and "catastrophist," thereby
polarizing the debate in a way which was not so neatly divided in the minds of most
practicing geologists.) In what follows, it is noteworthy that Whewell is arguing his case
in the light of the existing scientific evidence. This was already becoming a very risky
strategy by the time that he wrote: the evidence could go either way. Thus, the roles of
the advocates of the principle of the continuity of nature and naturalist explanation on
the one hand and those who advocated divine intervention in the course of nature on the
other were curiously reversed by Whewell when he argued that "Nothing has been
pointed out in the existing order of things which has any analogy or resemblance, of any
valid kind, to that creative energy which must be exerted in the production of a new
species. And to assume the introduction of new species as a part
139
of the order of nature, without pointing out any natural fact with which such an event
can be classed, would be to reject creation by an arbitrary act." There being no such
natural means by which new species come to be, Whewell concludes that a creative power is
exerted at the beginning of each cycle of new species. "Thus we are led by our
reasonings to this view, that the present order of things was commenced by an act of
creative power entirely different to any agency which has been exerted since. None of the
influences which have modified the present races of animals and plants since they were
placed in their habitations on the earth's surface can have had any efficacy in producing
them at first. We are necessarily driven to assume, as the beginning of the present cycle
of organic nature, an event not included in the course of nature." Material science
cannot offer any explanation of the origin of species. An abyss interposes itself between
us and any intelligible beginning of things.
Having convinced himself that science can say nothing of the origins of states of the
earth or of the introduction of new species, Whewell turns to the topic of the
relationship between the sciences of geology and biology on the one hand and the
traditional biblical account on the other. Man keeps records, but the sacred narrative is
inevitably difficult to interpret. Science constantly changes the language for describing
facts, while the language of Scripture is always the same and was written for the common
man. "Hence the phrases used by Scripture are precisely those which science soon
teaches man to consider as inaccurate." In this, and the next four sections of his
analysis, Whewell places the relations between the Book of God's Word and the Book of
God's Works on a slippery slope which could only lead to science claiming more and more as
its legitimate domain, while interpretation of Scripture became increasingly abstract.
He chooses as his example the conflict between Galileo and the Church (not,
significantly, an issue in the contemporary debate). This episode taught that it was in
the highest degree unjustifiable to extract astronomical or any other doctrines from the
Scriptures and that any attempt to do so could lead "to no result but a weakening of
the authority of Scripture in proportion as its credit was identified with that of these
modes of applying it. And this judgment has since been generally assented to by those who
most reverence and value the study of the designs of Providence as well as that of the
works of nature." He then protects himself by flatly
140
asserting that science can teach us nothing about creation: "The thread of
induction respecting the natural course of the world snaps in our fingers, when we try to
ascertain where its beginning is. Since, then, science can teach us nothing positive
respecting the beginning of things, she can neither contradict nor confirm what is taught
by Scripture on that subject; and thus, as it is unworthy timidity to fear contradiction,
so it is ungrounded presumption to look for confirmation in such cases. The providential
history of the world has its own beginning, and its own evidence; and we can only render
the system insecure, by making it lean on our material sciences."
This passage is a straightforward abandonment of one of the traditional aims of natural
theology - to illuminate revelation by science. The trouble was, of course, that zealous
scientist-theologians had claimed to find evidence which confirmed the biblical
account. When this evidence was found to be erroneous, the consequences for the biblical
story were alarming. Just this had happened in the case of William Buckland, Professor of
Geology at Oxford, whose dramatic evidence in support of the biblical Deluge had been
proudly proclaimed in the 1820s, only to be quietly withdrawn in a footnote in his Bridgewater
Treatise in 1836. Whewell saw that supporting Scripture by scientific evidence could
not be separated from loss of support from new evidence.
From this position he might well have gone on to argue that science and theology should
never be mingled, as Bacon had urged. Instead, he placed the Scriptures in danger of
constant reinterpretation in the light of new scientific findings. He makes this point in
a complacent, reassuring spirit, little suspecting that in his own lifetime this faith
would let him down, and by ten years after his death this doctrine had been hardened into
the aggressive thesis that as science advances, religion retreats.
8. Scientific views, when familiar, do not disturb the authority of Scripture. -There
is another reflection which may serve to console and encourage us in the painful struggles
which thus take place, between those who maintain interpretations of Scripture already
prevalent and those who contend for such new ones as the new discoveries of science
require. It is this; that though the new opinion is resisted by one party as something
destructive of the credit of Scripture and the reverence which is due, yet, in fact, when
the new interpretation has been gradually established and incorporated with men's current
thoughts, it ceases to disturb their views of the authority of the Scripture or the truth
of its teaching. When the
141
language of Scripture, invested with its new meaning, has become familiar to men, it is
found that the ideas which it calls up are quite as reconcileable as the former ones were
with the most entire acceptance of the providential dispensation. And when this has been
found to be the case, all cultivated persons look back with surprise at the mistake of
those who thought that the essence of the revelation was involved in their own arbitrary
version of some collateral circumstance in the revealed narrative. At the present day, we
can hardly conceive how reasonable men could ever have imagined that religious reflections
on the stability of the earth, and the beauty and use of the luminaries which revolve
around it, would be interfered with by an acknowledgement that this rest and motion are
apparent only. And thus the authority of revelation is not shaken by any changes
introduced by the progress of science in the mode of interpreting expressions which
describe physical objects and occurrences; provided the new interpretation is admitted at
a proper season, and in a proper spirit; so as to soften, as much as possible, both the
public controversies and the private scruples which almost inevitably accompany such an
alteration.
As he says in another place, "The results of true geology and astronomy cannot be
irreconcileable with the statements of true theology." Whewell only warns that
theology should not overhastily accept a new interpretation of Scripture, once again, lest
it have to reverse its new interpretation when the scientific findings are shown to be
unsound. Nevertheless, he goes on to say that ". . . when a scientific theory,
irreconcileable with its ancient interpretation, is clearly proved, we must give up the
interpretation, and seek some new mode of understanding the passage in question, by
means of which it may be consistent with what we know; for if it be not, our conception of
the things so described is no longer consistent with itself." "It is
impossible," he concludes, "to over look the lesson which here offers itself,
that it is in the highest degree unwise in the friends of religion, whether individuals or
communities, unnecessarily to embark their credit in expositions of Scripture on matters
which appertain to natural science. By delivering physical doctrines as the teaching of
revelation, religion may lose much, but cannot gain anything."
The problem was to determine just what pertained to natural science. Whewell felt
confident that certain major changes in the history of the earth, the origin of species,
the appearance of man, and his moral nature were not within the domain of science. Within
four years, Robert Chambers' anonymous work The Vestiges
.
142
of the Natural History of Creation appeared and argued that astronomy, geology,
te origin of species, man's moral nature, and his social behavior were all subject to
natural law - that there was no distinction between the physical and the moral. Chambers
claimed that mind (and therefore morality) thereby passed into the category of natural
law. Seven years later this interpretation was reinforced by Spencer's advocacy of
evolution, massively backed up three years after that by a work interpreting psychology in
evolutionary terms. There rapidly followed a rash of books interpreting the Scriptures
themselves in scientific terms, followed by the works of Darwin and Wallace on evolution
and those of others on the applications of evolutionary ideas to history, sociology,
anthropology, and, finally, all mundane things.
Whewell was invited to review the Vestiges of Creation in the Edinburgh
Review. He declined (the review was written by Adam Sedgwick, whose career and views
might have served as a case study to complement Whewell's). Instead, Whewell published a
reply to Vestiges which took a curious form (no less curious, however, than
Sedgwick's writings on the subject): he simply republished extracts from the History
and Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences in a slim volume with a preface which alludes
to the doctrine of Vestiges without mentioning the book! In a letter he
acknowledges that the selections, under the title Indications of the Creator, "was
published with some reference to the Vestiges,..... and as an answer to it so far
as truth must in some measure be an answer to falsehood on the same subject. . . . I have
attempted to show that, dim as the light is which science throws upon creation, it gives
us reason to believe that the placing of man upon the earth (including his creation) was a
supernatural event, an exception to the laws of nature. The Vestiges has, for one
of its main doctrines, that this event was a natural event, the result of a law by which
man grew out of monkey." The appeal of the book, he felt, lay in its "bold,
unscrupulous, and false scientific generalisations" which are attractive to the
ignorant, while they enrage scientists.
In the preface to the second edition, Whewell does refer to a defense of Vestiges,
Explanations, and to the offending book itself. Once again, his position depends on
the state of contemporary science: " . . . according to the best scientific views
hitherto obtained, the Origin of Man, and the Origin of Life upon the earth, were events
of a different order from the common course of nature. The Origin of Man is the Origin of
Language, of Law, of
143
Social Relations, of Intellectual and Social and Moral Progress; and though in all
these characteristics of humanity we can trace a constant series of changes and movements,
we can discern in them no evidence of a beginning homogeneous with the present order of
changes. If Science does not positively teach that man was placed upon the earth by a
special act of his Creator, she at least shews no difficulty in the way of such a belief?
She leaves us free to hold that the placing of man upon the earth was not an ordinary step
in the natural course of the world; but an extraordinary step, the beginning of a
providential and moral course of the world. She negatives the doctrine that men grew out
of apes, that language is the necessary development of the jabbering of such creatures,
and reason the product of their conflicting appetites." Where Lyell and the author of Vestiges, respectively, had referred the history of the earth and of life to the
uniform action of the same natural causes which were then operating, Whewell says that
this is a gratuitous assumption, while his views are the "result of scientific
investigations." If we try to account for these changes by causes now in action, we
fail.
Whewell notices Chambers' claim that his system denies human agency and human virtue
but need not shake one's faith in God, but argues that this is simply inconsistent with
the doctrine of Vestiges. Fortunately, these doctrines are fantastical, have been
repudiated by all those competent to judge them, and can appeal only to the most
credulous. If the doctrine of Vestiges be false, what then is true? Whewell
replies, "To this question, men of real science do not venture to return an
answer." "Since, as I have endeavoured to show in the following pages, the chain
of existing causes does not, in any case, conduct us back to its origin; - not in the
history of the mass of the earth, nor of its strata, nor of animal life, nor of man; - I
must necessarily confess that we can not obtain from science a complete view of the
history of the universe. That human reason should thus be unable to fathom and comprehend
the acts of the Creator and Governor of the world, is no surprise nor humiliation to me;
and I think that those do well who learn, from the study of the sciences, this lesson of
humility."
Looking back from the vantage point of the addresses by Huxley and Tyndall at the
Belfast meeting of the British Association in 1874, these passages read like a dare. Find
the mechanism of evolution, and you can be as arrogant as you please. And they were:
Tyndall claimed that science had unrestricted right of search
144
in all of nature, and Huxley argued that both men and animals are conscious automata. A
year later, William Draper's provocative book The History of the Conflict between
Religion and Science appeared in the popular International Scientific Series. This
book accurately represents the state of the debate as it appeared by 1875. Whatever else
one might wish to say about the results of Whewell's interpretation of the relationship
between religion and science, it cannot be said that following it had the effect of making
theology secure and scientists humble. Even earlier - in 1872 - statistical inquiries were
being undertaken on the efficacy of prayer.
Whewell's response to Darwin's theory has an unvigorous air about it, in marked
contrast to his spirited treatments of Lyell and Chambers. He wrote a polite note to
Darwin, saying, ". . . I cannot, yet at least, become a convert. But there is so much
of thought and of fact in what you have written that it is not to be contradicted without
careful selection of the ground and manner of the dissent." Darwin was so pleased
that he sent the letter to Lyell, noting that Whewell "is not horrified with
us." In the next four years many wrote on the question of the origin of species, the
antiquity of man, and man's place in nature. Whewell fell back on the claim that the
arguments in his Indications of the Creator still held. "It still appears to
me that in tracing the history of the world backwards, so far as the palaetiological
sciences enable us to do so, all the lines of connection stop short of a beginning
explicable by natural causes; and the absence of any conceivable natural beginning leaves
room for, and requires, a supernatural origin. Nor do Mr. Darwin's speculations alter this
result. For when he has accumulated a vast array of hypotheses, still there is an
inexplicable gap at the beginning of his series." Darwin, of course, never denied
this. His doctrine, like those of Hutton and Lyell before him, was not concerned with the
origin of the earth or of life. Whewell had been making much stronger claims in the 1830s
and 1840s for repeated miraculous, wholesale creations of species. Now he is reduced to
arguing for a miraculous beginning to the series, a point which Darwin concedes in the
last paragraph of the Origin of Species. Whewell continues rather feebly: "To
which is to be added, that most of his hypotheses are quite unproved by fact. We can no
more adduce an example of a new species, generated in the way which his hypotheses
suppose, than Cuvier could." (Again, a point conceded by Darwin, Huxley, and
Tyndall.) Finally, Whewell, now badly out of touch, claims that his earlier
145
conception of a uniformitarian-catastrophist debate still reflects the state of
geological controversy: "And though the advocates of uniformitarian doctrines in
geology go on repeating their assertions, and trying to explain all difficulties by the
assumption of additional myriads of ages, I find that the best and most temperate
geologists still hold the belief that great catastrophes must have taken place; and I do
not think that the state of the controversy on that subject is really affected
permanently. I still think that what I have written is a just representation of the
question between the two doctrines." He went on to say that he did not believe that
any cause would be served by his writing further on the subject; what he had written over
twenty years earlier still seemed to him to apply to most of the questions under
consideration in 1863. Finally, he says, he simply does not have the detailed knowledge to
ajudicate the contemporary controversy.
Three months later Whewell turned his attention to the question of the antiquity of
man, which was then at the center of the debate as a result of the appearance of Lyell's
work on that subject and Huxley's collection of essays entitled Man's Place in Nature. There
are signs in Whewell's remarks of a man who is simply out of touch and feeling nostalgic
for a time when science and theology were more simply and reassuringly related.
I have myself taken no share in the discussions on the antiquity of man; but I will not
conceal from you that the course of speculation on this point has somewhat troubled me. I
cannot see without some regrets the clear definite line, which used to mark the
commencement of the human period of the earth's history, made obscure and doubtful. There
was something in the aspect of the subject, as Cuvier left it [Cuvier died in 1832], which
was very satisfactory to those who wished to reconcile the providential with the
scientific history of the world, and this aspect is now no longer so universally
acknowledged. It is true that a reconciliation of the scientific with the religious view
is still possible, but it is not so clear and striking as it was. But it is weakness to
regret this; and no doubt another generation will find some way of looking at the matter
which will satisfy religious men.
He adds that he should be glad to see his way to such a view and is hoping to do so
soon. He lived for two more years, and it is a rather pathetic footnote to his career that
his last gesture in thegreat debate on the relations among God, man, and nature was to
146
refuse to allow a copy of Darwin's Origin of Species to be placed in the Library
of Trinity College.
IV
I should now like to contrast the views of Whewell with those of Baden Powell. Where
Whewell was involved in a rather tired and increasingly disorderly retreat, Powell was
running headlong into the arms of the enemy. He was a sort of diminutive Whewell. He held
only one Chair, that of Geometry at Oxford. As a scientist he wrote on light and radiant
heat and elementary books on curves and on differential calculus. He wrote chiefly on
optical questions and managed only one slim volume on the entire history of science. He
was active in doctrinal questions from a latitudinarian point of view and took part in
university reform. (He also sired thirteen children, one of whom founded the Boy Scouts.)
In spite of his obscurity in recent secondary literature, Powell was the most
clear-sighted of the interpreters of the uniformitarian point of view and wrote a series
of monographs, essays, and reviews which nicely parallel Whewell's works from the
interventionist or catastrophist point of view. Lest it be thought that I am rescuing an
obscure figure for my own polemical purposes, I should add that his essays were commonly
reviewed with Darwin's Origin of Species, and he was one of the contributors
to Essays and Reviews -a work in the naturalist tradition which was causing more
controversy in 1860 than Darwin's. (Essays and Reviews went through six editions by
1865.) Darwin also acknowledges Powell's work in the preface to later editions of the Origin.
Powell suits us, because he interpreted Lyell in the 1830s in a monograph entitled On
the Connection of Natural and Divine Truth, defended Vestiges in "The
Philosophy of Creation," and was an early advocate of Darwin in his "Study of
the Evidences of Christianity," his contribution to Essays and Reviews (which
evoked a flood of replies). Powell promptly died, thereby missing out on the prosecution
of some of his fellow contributors and giving rise to snide remarks about his punishment
for blasphemy from one quarter and about his being blissfully free from a lot of
Bibliolaters from the other.
Powell's position throughout his writings was consistent: the only rational and safe
solution to the problem of reconciling science and theology is to keep them completely
separate and to give up
147
entirely the concept of miracle as having anything to do with science. This was a
radical, uncompromising solution to the problems posed for natural theology by science:
the physical and moral departments of nature should be divorced once and for all. The
Bible was an inspirational document, having nothing to do with science. Any attempt to
stretch Scripture to accommodate science would harm both faith and reason. In 1855 he
wrote that any solution short of this had always resulted "either in a lamentable
antagonism and hostility, or in futile attempts to combine them in incongruous union, upon
fallacious principles." The foundations of scientific and religious truth are, he
insisted, entirely separate.
One might feel that the complete separation of moral and physical phenomena hardly solves one of the problems of natural theology: it either abrogates the discipline or merely
restates its main problem. However, this was the solution which he, along with Combe and
Chambers, proposed, and this view provoked Adam Sedgwick's fulminations against phrenology
and the doctrine of Vestiges. Powell's essay made him much angrier than Darwin's
hypothesis, since it explicitly advocated the very separation of moral and physical
phenomena which Sedgwick said was implied by Darwin's book. It could be argued that
Sedgwick and Wilberforce had clearer heads - that the only consistent theological position
which did not entail slow, deliberate theological suicide was to stand and fight. However,
the constraints which operate on a given thinker in a given historical context do not
always - or even usually - lead to his holding an internally consistent position. Thus,
Combe argued that the brain is the organ of the mind but that this did not imply
materialism and fatalism. Chambers claimed that phrenology and social statistics did imply
fatalism and annulled the distinction between the physical and the moral and then blithely
argued that physical and moral laws are independent. Powell supported uniform natural laws
in all of geology and biology but considered man's mental and spiritual nature
independent. Surely this was what was at issue in the evolutionary debate! In any case,
Powell claimed that there can be no real hiatus in the physical operations of nature and
that all of science depends on this assumption.
The complete separation of science and theology was cold comfort, and it avoided the
crucial claims of science to account for mental and moral phenomena and for the status of
the Bible as a
148
historical document. Nevertheless, this was the line that was taken as an alternative
to Whewell's idea of an orderly withdrawal. It is in this context that one can make sense
of Huxley's claim that the theory of evolution "is neither Antitheistic nor Theistic.
It simply has no more to do with Theism than the first book of Euclid has." "The
doctrine of Evolution, therefore, does not even come into contact with Theism, considered
as a philosophical doctrine. That with which it does collide, and with which it is
absolutely inconsistent, is the conception of creation, which theological speculators have
based upon the history narrated in the opening of the book of Genesis." If evolution
has nothing to do with theism but merely contradicts the creation of the world by God,
Huxley's laissez-faire view does not seem to have carried him as far as the end of the
next sentence. Huxley, of course, goes on to claim the domain which Powell had reserved
from the principle of uniformity. He did not deny that men and (pace Descartes)
animals are conscious: they are conscious automata. Similarly, the term
"creation" came increasingly to be used in an utterly emasculated sense to imply
ignorance of the natural mode of production of a phenomenon. It is not surprising, on this
account, that Lyell, Chambers, and Darwin could argue that their theories implied a grander view of the Creator - One who operated by general laws. Granting this cost them nothing as
scientists. We know that Darwin had imperceptibly lost his religious faith somewhere along
the way, but he could still be quite conventionally pious in On the Origin of Species. For all practical purposes this view was indistinguishable from positivism and
agnosticism. It had been anticipated in Charles Babbage's uninvited Ninth Bridgewater
Treatise, in which the inventor of the calculating engine (the lineal ancestor to the
modern computer) argued that a miracle was equivalent to a sequence of numbers which the
Programmer had instructed the calculating engine to produce and which only appeared to be
an exception to the orderly sequence. This well-meaning offer of help to those troubled by
the relationship between natural laws and miracles had the effect of making the claims of
theism vacuous by making them so abstract that they had no empirical reference. By the
time, fifty years later, that Frederick Temple argued in his Bampton Lectures that
theology had nothing to fear from the evolutionary theory, the author was somewhere
between being the writer of one of the theologically shocking Essays and Reviews and
149
being Archbishop of Canterbury. (This change in Temple's status is, I repeat, as
remarkable a fact as Darwin's burial in Westminster Abbey.) Perhaps theologians had become
convinced that they had nothing to fear at the expense of making no claims for theism.
This situation is reminiscent of seventeenth-century developments in which the
exponents of a mechanical view of nature claimed that this involved no threat to theism.
Commenting on these "Mechanick Theists," John Ray wrote in The Wisdom of God (1690), "Wherefore these Atomick Theists utterly evacuate that grand argument for a
God, taken from the phenomena of the artificial frame of things, which hath been so much
insisted upon in all ages, and which commonly makes the strongest impression of any other
upon the minds of men &c. the atheists in the mean time laughing in their sleeves, and
not a little triumphing to see the cause of Theism thus betray'd by its profess'd friends
and assertors, and the grand argument for the same totally slurred by them, and so their
work done, as it were, to their hands."
Now, to review. The tension between theodicy and the requirements of the scientific
method had been harmonized in Paley by means of simple examples and the device of begging
all questions having to do with origins. As detailed findings of science in areas which
bore directly on the history of the earth, of life, and of man were brought into contact
with natural theology, the theologians and theologian-scientists made three sorts of
moves:
1. Separate the moral from the physical (Combe, some passages in Chambers, and Powell);
2 Reinterpret Scripture in the light of new scientific findings (Buckland, Sedgwick,
Whewell - even some of the most ardent literalists, e.g., William Kirby and Thomas
Chalmers, did this to some degree);
3. Make the concept of God more abstract until He is identified with the Uniformity of
Nature.
Whatever move was made (and there are innumerable intermediate positions), one result
was common: these adaptations involved the abandonment of the traditional claims of
natural theology by emasculating its theodicy. It was no longer a strong enough doctrine
to serve a unifying function in the intellectual culture of the period. If the
justification of the ways of God to man is that God works by general laws and/or that His
intention
150
was that moral and physical laws should be separate, then this would seem to guarantee
God's indifference to a careless man of piety who, while praying fervently, stepped over a
cliff and perished while obeying the laws of gravity. (Combe actually used this example.)
Of course, this view of God's relationship to nature does not preclude a very personal God
serving essentially psychological functions of inspiration and consolation, but it was
necessary to confine claims for His efficacy to the afterlife, since science, scientific
historiography, and statistics eliminated the claims of divine creation and the efficacy
of prayer.
V
At the outset I was very tentative about the relationship between three issues: (1) the
common context of ideas, the periodicals in which they were discussed, and the individuals
who wrote about them; (2) the impact of science on natural theology; (3) the breakdown of
the common context in the 1870s and later. One way of providing evidence for a causal
relationship between these would be to show that the principal figures who wrote on
various aspects of the debate were so concerned that they banded together to discuss the
influence of science on the philosophy of nature and the implications for theology,
literature, ethics, legislation, etc. If these developments are related, these men should
find increasing difficulty in communicating with one another and should eventually lose
interest and go their separate ways. Of course, it would help if this fantasy discussion
group included the editors of, and the most distinguished contributors to, the major
periodicals. They should be very interested in the aims of the group but should draw the
lesson that they could no longer meet on common ground and go away to found new,
specialized (or less sophisticated) societies and periodicals. We could then argue with
some confidence that natural theology had become too abstract and/or too separated from
scientific and moral issues to act as a cohesive force in the intellectual life of the
period.
It would be very obliging of, say, Huxley, Cardinal Manning, Gladstone, William
Carpenter, Walter Bagehot, Tyndall, Froude, Frederic Harrison, R. H. Hutton, A. R Stanley,
Leslie Stephen, J. S. Mill, Darwin, Wallace, and Spencer to find time to conduct this experimentum crucis for us, but unfortunately my list is a tiny bit overambitious.
That is, Mill and Spencer declined to join the
151
Metaphysical Society, and Darwin and Wallace were not members, but perhaps we can be
reconciled to their absence by the presence of Tennyson, Ruskin, James Martineau, F. D.
Maurice, James Knowles, James Fitzjames Stephen, the Duke of Argyll, Sir John Lubbock, A.
J. Balfour, W K. Clifford, Mark Pattison, J. R. Seeley, Henry Sidgwick, George Croom
Robertson, James Sully, and St. George Mivart, among others, making up sixty-two of the
most eminent thinkers, churchmen, editors, men of affairs, writers, and scientists of the
period.
Just about everything concerning this society realizes a historian's daydreams,
including the fact that someone has done a very informative but not very incisive study of
it. There are some minutes, almost all their papers were printed and are preserved in some
form (many in Victorian periodicals), and the activities of the society can be illuminated
by various lives and letters. It is true that one cannot attend the meetings, but members
thoughtfully recorded their views in the Nineteenth Century in a series entitled
"A Modern Symposium." Finally, several of the papers are reflections on the
society itself, and R. H. Hutton has written a very evocative reminiscence on the origins
of the society, including a typical meeting. The Metaphysical Society was founded in 1869,
a year after one of the great holdouts on evolutionism had reluctantly accepted Darwin's
view. In reviewing Lyell's final acceptance of evolution, A. R. Wallace, as I have pointed
out, told the readers of the Quarterly Review that he was excepting some aspects of
man from the process of evolution by natural selection. Things were getting very messy
indeed, and the enunciation of the doctrine of papal infallibility a year later did little
to improve the atmosphere.
Ninety meetings were held, and the Metaphysical Society voluntarily disbanded - for
lack of interest - in 1880. It was first conceived as a Theological Society, but A. P.
Stanley argued for rapprochement with the scientists, and the conception was
broadened and the name was changed to "Metaphysical and Psychological Society"
(the "Psychological" was soon dropped). The form was adopted from an amalgam of
practices drawn from scientific societies and the Cambridge Apostles. The initiative came
from the theological side, but there was a successful campaign to recruit scientists. The
terms of reference of the society are just what one would hope. They set out to
investigate "mental and moral phenomena, the faculties of lower animals, the grounds
of belief, the
152
logic of the physical and social sciences, the immortality and identity of the soul,
the existence and personality of God, conscience, and materialism." I wish that there
was space to go through the papers read before the society in detail, but I can really
only mention one or two and refer you to A. W. Brown's account, to which I am heavily in
debt for this portion of my essay. At the first meeting, Tennyson's poem "The Higher
Pantheism" was read by Knowles. It is characteristic in that many of the lines
referring to the Deity end in queries, and it concludes,
God is law, say the wise; Oh Soul, and let us rejoice,
For if He thunder by law the thunder is yet His voice.
Law is God, say some; no God at all, says the fool,
For all we have power to see is a straight staff bent in a pool;
And the ear of man cannot hear, and the eye of man cannot see;
But if we could see and hear, this Vision - were it not He?
This uncertainty about the faith which can be based on such a pale God nicely reflects
my general point. Sixteen years later, in a passage I have already quoted, R. H. Hutton
makes the same point, with the same ambiguity: "The uniformity of nature is the veil
behind which, in these latter days, God is hidden from us." Indeed, he chose as the
paper read at his imaginary meeting of the society, "Can Experience Prove the
Uniformity of Nature?" Between these two quotations lie ninety papers, beginning with
Hutton's "On Mr. Spencer's Theory of the Gradual Transformation of Utilitarian into
Intuitive Morality by Hereditary Descent." I am tempted simply to reproduce the
titles, since they convey the troubled and irreconcilable views of the members. They might
have clashed and hammered out something. Indeed, Ward expressed Christian horror at
Huxley's views in an early meeting, and in reply Huxley mentioned the intellectual
degradation which would result from general acceptance of Ward's views, but from that time
on, no words of that kind were heard.
Brown diagnoses the disintegration in a number of ways, but they add up to a surfeit of
tolerance coupled with such irreconcilable views that the various persuasions slipped past
one another and never grappled. Huxley claimed that the society died of too much love,
while Tennyson thought that it perished because, after years of strenuous effort, no one
had succeeded even in defining the term "metaphysics." The only common ground
available to
153
them, as I have tried to show, was too abstract to be of any use. Where they used the
same terms, they lacked common meanings. Let me cut the analysis short and say that they
simply lacked a common context of ideas, and they were the last generation to attempt to
maintain one. In a way it is remarkable that they spent eleven years arriving at the
conclusion.
I should like to draw attention once again to the periodicals and other manifestations
of the intellectual and cultural consequences of the Metaphysical Society. First, let us
note the ages of the members at the time of its dissolution. Of the total membership since
1869, eight were dead, six were over seventy, eighteen were over sixty, fourteen were over
fifty, ten were over forty, and six were over thirty (five of these elected in the last
year), i.e., a waning generation.
It seems to me that the Metaphysical Society was something of a turning point. It
attracted some of the most influential members of the cultural and political elite, men
who were attempting to embrace all of the aspects of culture and society. At the same time
it was the cradle of a number of specialized societies and periodicals which, on my
reading of the evidence, were symptoms of the fragmentation of the common intellectual
context of the early decades of the century. Its most active members included an
astonishing group of editors and contributors: Hutton, Spectator; Alford,
Contemporary; Knowles, Contemporary and Nineteenth Century; Ward, Dublin;
Bagehot, National and Economist; Froude, Fraser's; Leslie Stephen, Cornhill and Dictionary of National Biography; and Robertson, Mind. A. C. Fraser
had edited the North British (1850-7), and two relatively inactive members edited
other major periodicals: Grove (Macmillan's) and Morley (Fortnightly 1867-82
- and later, for brief periods, Pall Mall Gazette and Macmillan's). Among
the prominent and prolific contributors were Stanley, Huxley, Mivart, Argyll, Harrison,
Tyndall, Carpenter, Pattison, Gladstone, J. Martineau, Tennyson, and Ruskin.
Before turning to some symptoms of the breakdown of the common context, I should like
to cite some statistics which strike me as interesting and significant. Between 1860 and
1870, 170 new periodicals were launched in London (an average of one about every three
weeks; most were short-lived); 140 between 1870 and 1880; 1880-90, 70; 1890-1900, 30 (less
than in 1791-1800). There was also a great increase in the availability of cheap books in
154
the last decades of the century. Meanwhile, the great quarterlies were in decline. The
circulation of the Edinburgh Review was 13,500 in 1818 and about
7,000 between 1860 and 1870; the analogous figures for the Quarterly were 14,000
and 8,000. The Westminster Review (the third of the great quarterlies) was founded
in 1824, never had a large circulation, and averaged 4,000 in the period 1860-70.
Scientific and religious monthlies and quarterlies sold 1,000 to 2,000 copies,
while the general monthlies sold 3,000 to 20,000, although the Cornhill sold 80,000
in 1860 (2,500 in 1871 and later 12,000) and Cassell's Magazine sold 200,000 in
1870. Macmillan's and the Cornhill sold 100,000 in their best years. The
weeklies had circulations of up to 300,000, but 40,000 to 60,000 was more usual. The Fortnightly (the main platform for radical opinion) sold 2,500 in 1873. Radical
periodicals never had large circulations.
In order to make sense of these figures beyond saying that a lot of periodicals were
being sold (and presumably read), one would have to make detailed studies of which popular
novelist wrote for which periodical in which year. One would also need to take account of
a number of other forces at work, whose combined effects would be difficult to analyse.
Here are some which were mentioned in a contemporary series of articles. Stamp duty on
paper was reduced in 1836 and abolished in 1855. Cheaper paper was therefore available. It
was available to a rising population whose literacy was increasing. Periodicals could be
printed on new steam presses; they were marketed with greater commercial sophistication.
Authors were paid higher fees and wrote for a more differentiated audience. A larger
audience allowed publishers to cater to more diversified interests. However, one can draw
the unsurprising conclusion that the lower the intellectual standard, the higher the
circulation. At the same time, growing literacy did not swell the circulation figures of
the Edinburgh and Quarterly. The new formula for success lay with the Nineteenth
Century, and this does seem significant, since its editor, James Knowles, persuaded
very eminent contributors to write in a more popular style, with great success. It would
be interesting to examine the circulation figures of the Contemporary Review, since
it was founded as an organ making the same kind of appeal to liberal opinion in the church
that the Fortnightly made to a more secular audience and then underwent a
transformation in Knowles' hands before he
155
founded the Nineteenth Century. However, I have been unable to find any
figures.
VI
In this concluding section I should like to indicate briefly a number of things which
seem to me to be symptoms of the fragmentation of the common intellectual context which
was thriving in the early decades of the century and which the Metaphysical Society was
attempting to maintain. The examples which I have chosen are the decline of the British
Association, a confused book which was much praised by Darwin, the founding of Nature as
a general scientific periodical outside of the context of the quarterlies, and the
founding of a number of specialist journals and societies which emerged from the matrix of
the Metaphysical Society.
The British Association was founded partly as a protest against corruptions in the
Royal Society and partly as an attempt to give science the sort of status in Britain which
it had on the Continent, but its main function was to interpret science to the intelligent
layman. The level of exposition of its general and specialist papers, and the interest
which its meetings generated on the part of the public (as shown by their attending
meetings and by the detailed reports of meetings in the newspapers and periodicals), shows
that the association was playing an important part in the common intellectual culture. In
the same period that the "heavy" quarterlies ceased to reflect a common culture,
the British Association was ceasing to serve the function of the expositor of the best
science to a glittering audience. After an uncertain start the first fifty years (since
1831) had been the best. A jubilee meeting was held at York in 1881; three years
later the first overseas meeting was held in Montreal, and somehow by this time the
association had become the "Ass". Thus a verse from "Red Lions"' songs
entitled "The Travelled Ass":
At York they thought she was sure to die
For she didn't seem to enjoy age;
But at last the doctors bade her try
The effects of an ocean voyage.
In the same year that the Metaphysical Society was founded, and at the time when the
British Association was ceasing to serve
156
as the main vehicle for communication between specialists in the various sciences and
for the dissemination of their findings to the general public, a periodical was founded,
the existence of which, it seems to me, was very significant. Nature, a general
scientific weekly, began publication soon after the Metaphysical Society began meeting.
The appearance of Nature diluted the role of science in the general periodical
literature and diverted the attention of scientists from the general periodical culture.
Coupled with the decline of the British Association and the development of much more
popular expositions of science in the Nineteenth Century a few years later, the
existence and popularity of Nature among increasingly professional scientists
represent a withdrawal from the common matrix in which important scientific findings found
their main reviews and discussions in the quarterlies.
In the 1870s and 1880s there were still long essays in the quarterlies on scientific
monographs, but the range of monographs which were being reviewed was narrower, and the
authors of the reviews were no longer the most eminent scientists. Similarly, if one looks
at the lives and letters of the leading scientists, they were no longer tremulously
awaiting the reviews in the quarterlies and discussing them in detail. Perhaps it is not
too great an exaggeration to say that "Nature" had withdrawn from the common
intellectual culture and had joined medicine as a domain for specialists.
Who was left to interpret science to the layman and to discuss the large issues raised
by science? There were, as I have said here, still reviews in the quarterlies, but their
authors were less competent than, e.g., Lyell, Whewell, Sedgwick, and Herschel had been in
the earlier decades. Those who still wrote for a nonspecialist audience, e.g., Huxley,
Wallace, and Tyndall, were self-consciously involved in popularization. The field was left
to pretentious hacks and to more or less competent amateurs. A detailed study of this new
sort of interpreter needs to be made, but it will be apparent that in the period after
1875 it is impossible to follow the methodology outlined in the first sections of this
essay. That is, in this period one is perforce involved in the study of popularizations.
Confining one's attention to the haute intelligentsia no longer works, and this
discovery has played a significant part in developing the line of argument used in this
essay. What is required is a study analogous to Millhauser's essay on popular
geology in the earlier decades, but the difference is that these writings
157
are not complemented by extended essays for the intelligentsia written by the relevant
specialists. Thus, one should begin looking at the writers who played the role, in the
period 1870-1900, which Wells and Eddington played in the early decades of the twentieth
century. (A study of the International Scientific Series would seem a promising place to
begin, and Becker's Scientific London [1874] can serve as a guide to the scientific
scene.)
One example of the sort of book which I have in mind is The Creed of Science,
Religious, Moral and Social, by William Graham. The author was Professor of
Jurisprudence at Belfast and set out to review the implications of physical, evolutionary,
and psychological science and to consider "the old eternal, questions in their
present aspect." The book was aimed especially at the general reader who was troubled
by the threat of "intellectual and moral nihilism." The point about the book is
that it was muddled but reassuring. As one reviewer put it, "...his efforts to save
the remnants of older speculations seem almost willful perversity. . . . [He] seems to
have a fondness for raising spectres in order apparently to have the satisfaction of
laying them. . . . His Transcendentalism and his Experimentalism are not harmonised; they
are simply juxtaposed, and he slips from the critical to the dogmatic vein almost without
knowing it." These remarks, by W. C. Coupland, appeared in the new professional
philosophical journal, Mind (of which more later) and represent the way in which
the book strikes the modern reader. However, the popular audience of the period welcomed
the book (a second edition soon appeared), and the author wrote popular books on the
philosophical, social, and political aspects of the new wave of science, including a
volume for the exceedingly popular International Scientific Series. My point is that the
public craved such works and that the sort of overview which Graham attempted was achieved
by means of casuistry. Yet Darwin took comfort from the book.
Another aspect of the apparent fragmentation of the common context is the change of
status of various specialist societies. It is very difficult to be sure about such things,
but one has the impression that a number of societies which had been in existence for many
decades began to become more self-consciously professional. This had the effect of making
amateurs less at home and led the professionals to devote more of their energies to a
narrower conception of their interests. Once again, detailed study of
158
indivdual societies is required, and a number of other variables are surely involved. I
will cite one example which will help me to say something which I want to say at the end.
In 1869 various disparate societies and publications in anthropology came together as a
self-conscious discipline merging the Journal of the Ethnological Society, the Memoirs
Read before the Anthropological Society, and the Anthropological Review. More
recently, the Journal of the Anthropological Institute has been renamed Man.
When the Metaphysical Society disbanded, it left its residual funds to a new journal, Mind, whose foundation in 1876 seems to me to reflect the fact that psychology and
philosophy of mind had never really found a home in the common context. I've said that
works on psychology had been reviewed - beginning with a fulminating attack on phrenology
by Thomas Brown in the second volume of the Edinburgh Review (1803) which was
followed by others in 1815 and 1826 by John Gordon and Francis Jeffrey. The first fair
hearing for the phrenologists came in 1828 in the Foreign Quarterly Review. For
the most part, however, there was no debate on psychology in the quarterlies. I believe
that this was so because the allowance of such a debate would involve conceding the point
at issue - that there could be a science of psychology. Instead one finds
characteristic fulminating paragraphs in reviews of the major evolutionary works. This
belief is linked with another hypothesis - that concentrating on geological and biological
issues constituted a holding action against the real issue: Is mind a part of the natural
world, subject to scientific laws? In any case, Mind was conceived in the year of
Tyndall and Huxley's Belfast Addresses and first appeared in the year (1876) in which
David Ferrier summarized the experimental findings on the physiological basis of mind, a
study which had been developing dramatically since 1870. The founder of Mind was
Alexander Bain, who had done more than any other scholar to establish the identity of
psychology as an academic discipline, relatively free from the epistemological, logical,
educational, and social issues which had preoccupied earlier writers, e.g., Locke,
Hartley, Brown, J. Mill, J. S. Mill.
Mind was the first professional journal in the field in any country, and the
prefatory words in the first number included these remarks (which should be familiar from
Chapter 3):
Even now the notion of a journal being founded to be taken up wholly with metaphysical
subjects, as they are called, will little commend itself to those who are in the habit of
declaring with great confidence that there
159
can be no science in such matters, or to those who would only play with them now and
again [a reference to the Metaphysical Society?] ... MIND intends to procure a decision on
this question as to the scientific standing of psychology.
These declarations represent the growing specialization of a putative science of
psychology, a discipline related to philosophy and physiology but not dependent on either.
More important, it reflects an attitude which was antithetical to that of Chalmers' Bridgewater Treatise of 1833, in which the moral and intellectual constitution of
man was wholly absorbed by natural theology. Mind went on to become - and remains -
the most distinguished philosophical periodical. Its first editor was George C. Robertson,
a pupil of Bain and an active member of the Metaphysical Society.
It is worth noting in passing that Brain, a separate journal for the study of
neurology and neurophysiology, was founded in 1878, reflecting the relative independence
of these studies from general medicine on the one hand and from psychology on the other.
Two years earlier, a separate Physiological Society was founded, with T. H. Huxley, David
Ferrier, and G. H. Lewes on its council.
In 1879, the Aristotelian Society for the Systematic Study of Philosophy was founded.
Shadworth Hodgson was the prime mover, with generous advice from the Positivist Frederic
Harrison. Hodgson had also been one of Croom Robertson's most active supporters in the
establishment of Mind, and the two ventures remained closely connected. (Since 1918
they have met jointly once a year.) The members of the Aristotelian Society included Baln,
Romanes (the heir to Darwin in the study of comparative psychology), William James (the
prime mover in American psychology), J. M. Cattell, L. T. Hobhouse - and later, Bertrand
Russell, Alfred North Whitehezd, and G. E. Moore - bringing us to recent work. In the
first twelve years (i.e., until 1890-1, when its proceedings were first published),
psychological and methodological problems dominated the fortnightly meetings of the
society, and philosophy proper occupied a comparatively small place, even though its study
was the main purpose of the society. The executive committee complained in this vein in
1891-1.
The decline of the "heavy" general quarterlies and the growth of specialized
journals and societies were complemented by the success of a self-consciously
"middle-brow" periodical; the Nineteenth Century was founded in 1877 and
catered to a more popular
160
audience. Its editor, James Knowles, was able to persuade a number of eminent men to
change their loyalties and write for it. Indeed, the members of the Metaphysical Society
contributed a quarter of the articles in the first four volumes and a fifth of the next
four: in the first eight volumes there were twenty-three articles by Gladstone, thirteen
by Huxley, nine by Froude, and eight poems by Tennyson. Huxley also devoted a good deal of
energy to the popularization of science in its pages. The Nineteenth Century was
the most widely respected of the monthly reviews and remained so until the end of the
century. Its success lay in its presenting a different level of analysis and
exposition, not unlike that exhibited in our own time in Encounter, the New York
Review of Books and the London Review of Books, with perhaps an element
of something between New Scientist and Scientific American.
After the disbanding of the Metaphysical Society, the only soclety which was very like
it was the Synthetic Society, founded in 1896. However, its aims were really those of the
initial conception of the Metaphysical Society before the scientists were invited to join;
it was specialized in its own way and was frankly theological. So little did its members
disagree that they came to be known as the "Sympathetic Society." The attempt to
maintain a common context of ideas had failed, and the theologically minded had joined
their other specialized colleagues in recognizing a separation. Theology was no longer the
context; it was but one element in a fragmented culture.
Thus, by the 1880s Mind, Brain, Nature, Man (anthropology), and philosophy had
separated themselves off. These are examples pointing to the breakup of a common
intellectual context and its associated literature, leading to the development of
specialists' careers, societies, and periodicals.
Secularization and specialization are, of course, but a small part of the wider process
of enclosures which together led to the modern, professional intellectual and the academic
organization of knowledge within disciplinary boundaries. In our own time the division of
labor leads an intellectual to respond to the wide and deep questions which natural
theology and Victorian periodicals asked with, "That's not my field."
Gladstone epitomized the completion of preparing the ground for these arrangements in a
conversation with Tennyson, Froude, and Tyndall in 1881: "Let the scientific men
stick to their science,
161
and leave philosophy and religion to poets, philosophers, and theologians."
What remained common was popularization, uncertain generalization, and the
narrowed vision of the modern expert, who would blush to say or even think, "How
manifold are thy works O Lord; in wisdom hast thou made them all." In any case, what
would be the point? No reputable journal could be found to publish such ideas.
The growing indifference (coupled with arrogance) of scientists to theology is nicely
reflected in the spread of the designation "agnotic". Huxley's account of its
origina conveys the change of atmophere very well:.
When I reached intellectual maturity and began to ask myself whether I was an atheist,
a theist or a pantheist; a materialist or an idealist; a Christian or a freethinker; I
found that the more I learned and reflected, the less ready was the answer; until, at
last, I came to the conclusion that I had neither art nor part with any of these
denominations, except the last. . . . This was my situation when I had the good fortune to
find a place among the members of that remarkable con fraternity of antagonists, long
since deceased, but of green and pious mernory, the Metaphysical Society. Every variety of
philosophical and theological opinion was represented there, and expressed itself with
entire openness; most of my colleagues were -ists of one sort or another; and,
however kind and friendly they might be, I, the man without a rag or a label to cover
himself with, could not fail to have some of the uneasy feelings which must have beset the
historical fox when, after leaving the trap in which his tail remained, he presented
himself to his normally elongated companions. So I took thought, and invented what I
conceived to be the appropriate title 'agnostic.' It came into my head as suggestively
antithetic to the 'gnostic' of Church history, who professed to know so much about the
very things of which I was ignorant; and I took the earliest opportunity of parading it at
our Society, to show that I, too had a tail, like other foxes. To my great satisfaction,
the term took; and when the Spectator had stood godfather to it, any
suspicion in the minds of respectable people, that a knowledge of its parentage might have
awakened was, of course, completely lulled.
POSTSCRIPT
Since the argument of this chapter was first developed and explored in lectures
(1965-71) and since it was circulated and widely
162
cited in mimeograph form (1969), it has had a curious and gratifying underground life -
sometimes cited, often tacitly addressed. I fancy that at least one thesis, more than one
substantial paper, and perhaps a book got written along lines that might have been
different if it had not been for the argument of this essay. Some subsequent studies have
comforted me by deepening our grasp of "socially diplomatic purposes," the
"mediating functions," and "prominent unifying role" of natural
theology and referring to its "fragmentation" and vulnerability to changing
scientific connections. Similarly, I, of course, welcome subsidiary theses which played no
part in my original formulation but which are in line with my own historiography. John
Brooke argues that "the fate of natural theology itself would be bound up with all
the pressures to which such traditions were subjected during the course of the 19th
century. It is impossible to understand the fortunes of particular concepts of natural
theology if they are detached from their ecclesiastical context." Moving further, I
take it that my argument is complemented by the claim that
in the case of Powell, for example, it has been recently and successfully shown that
his critique of the apologetic value of miracles and his desire to unseat "the
prejudice, that design can only be inferred when we cease to trace laws" was as much
a reaction against the excesses of the Oxford Movement as it was a response to the
expansion of scientific naturalism.
Other findings begin to qualify my claims for the role of natural theology: "A
recent study reminds us that the implications of geology for natural theology were a
relatively minor concern for the religious periodical press." This does not, of
course, touch the role of natural theology in the scientific and high-brow periodicals
which were the ones to which I was drawing attention. I would say the same of what John
Brooke identifies as the strategy of David Yule's dissertation:
By driving a wedge between the clerical scientists and the intellectual leaders of the
Christian churches Yule minimizes the role of natural theology within Christianity. His
argument does, however, lead to the refreshing conclusion that, for the discerning a work
such as Vestiges merely confirmed the wisdom of the complete detachment from the
internecine squabbles of the scientific apologists.
I am delighted that these two assiduous students in my earliest lecture courses found
so much to ruminate. I would say the same
163
about writings about these and other Darwinian topics by my students and junior
colleagues, including Roger Smith, Peter Bowler, John Durant, Roger Cooter, Edward Yoxen,
and Maureen McNeil. As time goes on, other students would, I think, at best express
ambivalence about the relationship between the period during which we worked together and
our subsequent trajectories, e.g., W. F. Bynum and Roy Porter. On the other hand, some
whom I did not officially supervise - Margot Waddell - or even meet - James R. Moore,
Eveleen Richards, and David Kohn - have made very pleasing acknowledgments, just as a few
others have persisted with the uncollegial relations that characterized our period of
working together. Finally, there is the odd exact contemporary of whom I can only wonder
what's eating them.
I should close this bit of gossip by saying that my own mentor in the Darwinian
literature was Sidney Smith, who turned out to live across the street from me in my first
year at Cambridge. He called on me and was both kind enough to introduce me to Lovejoy's The
Great Chain of Being and provocative enough to suggest that it would be a dead end to
look into the Malthus-PaleyDarwin interrelations. I had become curious about them by
reading Charles Gillispie's masterful bibliographic essay at the end of Genesis and
Geology.
The person who taught me how to think about Darwin was Walter - later Faye -
Cannon, whom I did not meet until some years later, while the people who had most to do
with my learning to think at all were teachers at Yale - Richard Rorty and Irwin Lieb -
and Gerd Buchdahl at Cambridge. A. O. Lovejoy, A. N. Whitehead, E. A. Burtt, Georg
Lukács, and Herbert Marcuse were the most challenging people whom I read, while my then
friend John Dunn taught me a great deal about the scale and depth of the interrelations
among intellectual and political matters. I have always regretted that we parted over
Marxism. Here, as elsewhere, there are many layers to the histories of relationships. Even
when they cease to be fruitful at one level, they can continue to be at others. Lest this
postscript be thought to be merely gossip, it is worth recalling that intellectual
networks and influences are just as important to history now as they were in the
nineteenth century as the foregoing essays - and especially the one to follow - attempt to
show.